메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 103, Issue 2-3, 2004, Pages 357-374

The anti-human: Man and citizen before the declaration of the rights of man and of the citizen

(1)  Maslan, Susan a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 60950466728     PISSN: 00382876     EISSN: 15278026     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1215/00382876-103-2-3-357     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (21)

References (15)
  • 1
    • 74549188914 scopus 로고
    • (Paris: [n.p.])
    • Henri Grégoire (abbé). Motion en faveur des juifs (Paris: [n.p.], 1789), 1. Throughout this essay I construe "homme" as human being as, I believe, did Grégoire and his contemporaries
    • (1789) Motion en Faveur des Juifs , pp. 1
    • Grégoire, H.1
  • 2
    • 79955339464 scopus 로고
    • Discourse on the Origin and the Foundations of Inequality among Men
    • [New York: Harper and Row]
    • Grégoire, Motion, ii. Abbé Grégoire opens himself up here for some potential contradictions or corrections. His conception of "humanity," like that of so many of his contemporaries, privileges above all sensibility: human beings are those who suffer, who feel, who sympathize, who are touched by the feelings of others, who are happy and, especially, unhappy. The capacity to feel, rather than the capacity to reason, is the necessary condition for inclusion in the category of the human. Jean-Jacques Rousseau, of course, is a crucial figure in the development of the cult of sensibility. But he is far from alone; indeed, he is typical in his assertion that the capacity to feel is the primary qualification for humanity. Rousseau argues in the Discourse on the Origin and the Foundations of Inequality among Men, the work in which he seeks to discover and to represent the very nature of man, that man's nature, at its most essential, is constituted by two principles: the instinct for self-preservation and the "natural repugnance at seeing any sentient being, and especially any being like ourselves, perish or suffer." Natural law and natural rights stem from the combination of these two principles. Rousseau goes on to note that animals are feeling creatures and that "since they in some measure partake in our nature through the sentience with which they are endowed, it will be judged that they must also participate in natural right" (Discourse on the Origin and the Foundations of Inequality among Men, trans. Victor Gourevitch [New York: Harper and Row, 1986], 132-33). Rousseau can thus be seen as a theorist of animal rights. But my point here is that Rousseau's argument for the shared nature of man and animals undoes Grégoire's attempt to assert Jews' humanity by distinguishing Jews from beasts of burden
    • (1986) , pp. 132-133
    • Gourevitch, V.1
  • 7
    • 5244378861 scopus 로고
    • French Feminists and the Rights of'Man': Olympe de Gouges's Declarations
    • On Olympe de Gouges's declaration, see Joan Wallach Scott, "French Feminists and the Rights of'Man': Olympe de Gouges's Declarations," History Workshop Journal 28 (1989): 1-21
    • (1989) History Workshop Journal , vol.28 , pp. 1-21
    • Wallach Scott, J.1
  • 8
    • 0004175858 scopus 로고
    • (New York: Harcourt, Brace, and Jovano-vich)
    • Hannah Arendt, The Origins of Totalitarianism (New York: Harcourt, Brace, and Jovano-vich, [1951] 1973)
    • (1951) The Origins of Totalitarianism
    • Arendt, H.1
  • 9
    • 0003931980 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. Daniel Heller-Roazen (Stanford: Stanford University Press)
    • Giorgio Agamben, Homo Sour: Sovereign Power and Bare Life, trans. Daniel Heller-Roazen (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1998)
    • (1998) Homo Sour: Sovereign Power and Bare Life
    • Agamben, G.1
  • 10
    • 0010154281 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Paris: Seuil/Gallimard)
    • Foucault defines biopolitics in Il faut défendre la société (Paris: Seuil/Gallimard, 1997), 216-20
    • (1997) Il Faut Défendre la Société , pp. 216-220
    • Foucault1
  • 12
    • 79955279399 scopus 로고
    • ed. Alain Niderst (Rouen: Université de Rouen)
    • Pierre Corneille, Théâtre complet, ed. Alain Niderst (Rouen: Université de Rouen, 1984-1986), 1.3
    • (1984) Théâtre Complet
    • Corneille, P.1
  • 13
    • 61049250641 scopus 로고
    • (Paris: Gallimard)
    • For the claim that Curiace is feminine, see Serge Doubrovsky's classic Corneille et le dialectique du héros (Paris: Gallimard, 1963). For Doubrovsky, Curiace's expressions of desolation, self-pity, and anger at the gods demonstrate his impotence (a feminine trait for Doubrovsky) and underscore, in opposition, Horace's virtue. Doubrovsky argues that Horace is a more noble character than Curiace because he has powerful sentiments, but he forces himself to overcome them. In fact, the textual evidence for Horace's emotional ties to others is very slim
    • (1963) Classic Corneille et le Dialectique du Héros
    • Doubrovsky, S.1
  • 14
    • 63249136285 scopus 로고
    • (Paris: Minuit)
    • My account here opposes that of Louis Herland, who argues that Horace's project of self-transcendence and self-mastery makes him a true man, with man defined as being a creature of his own making. See Herland, Corneille ou la naissance de l'homme (Paris: Minuit, 1952)
    • (1952) Corneille Ou la Naissance de l'Homme
    • Herland1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.