메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 8, Issue , 2004, Pages 38-61

Three accounts of respect for persons in Kant's ethics

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 60950389572     PISSN: 13694154     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S1369415400001862     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (11)

References (24)
  • 1
    • 0004291536 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • and the Metaphysics of Morals (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), the second half of which is the Doctrine of Virtue. References will be to the Prussian Academy pagination, and inserted into the text. I will abbreviate the Groundwork as G, the Critique of Practical Reason as C2, and the Metaphysics of Morals as MdS.
    • (1996) Metaphysics of Morals
  • 2
    • 0141624757 scopus 로고
    • New York: Harper & Row
    • For example, H. J. Paton argues that FHE 'may be said to enjoin respect for personality as such', and that '[s]trictly speaking, this formula, like all others, should cover rational beings as such; but since the only rational beings with whom we are acquainted are men, we are bidden to respect men as men, or men as rational beings'. Paton, The Categorical Imperative (New York: Harper & Row, 1965), p. 165.
    • (1965) The Categorical Imperative , pp. 165
    • Paton1
  • 3
    • 31144436667 scopus 로고
    • Carl R Cranor stops just short of drawing this conclusion in 'Kant's respect-for-persons principle', International Studies in Philosophy, 12 (1980), 19-40, holding that '[s]omeone might be able to argue for this claim' - that is, that FHE can be understood, on Kant's terms, as a principle enjoining respect for persons - 'but an argument is needed' (p. 31). I attempt such an argument below.
    • (1980) International Studies in Philosophy , vol.12 , pp. 19-40
    • Cranor, C.R.1
  • 5
    • 83455240567 scopus 로고
    • Two kinds of respect
    • The distinction implicit in these passages tracks the distinction Stephen Darwall draws between recognition-respect and appraisal-respect in 'Two kinds of respect', Ethics, 88 (1977), 36-49
    • (1977) Ethics , vol.88 , pp. 36-49
  • 6
    • 17544370399 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • in many but not all respects, as Marcia Baron notes in 'Love and respect in the Doctrine of Virtue', in Mark Timmons (ed.), Kant's Metaphysics of Morals: Interpretive Essays (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002), pp. 397-8. Rather than risk confusion, I have adopted the (admittedly awkward) vocabulary above. Hill draws a similar distinction, between what he calls 'respect for a person's position' and 'respect for a person's merit', in Hill, 'Must respect be earned?'.
    • (2002) Kant's Metaphysics of Morals: Interpretive Essays , pp. 397-398
    • Timmons, M.1
  • 8
    • 84955870998 scopus 로고
    • Andrews Reath's very helpful discussion in 'Kant's theory of moral sensibility
    • I borrow this characterization from Andrews Reath's very helpful discussion in 'Kant's theory of moral sensibility', Kant-Studien, 80 (1989), 293.
    • (1989) Kant-Studien , vol.80 , pp. 293
  • 9
    • 80053679548 scopus 로고
    • Neill emphasizes in 'Universal laws and ends-in-themselves
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • As Onora O'Neill emphasizes in 'Universal laws and ends-in-themselves', Constructions of Reason (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989), pp. 138-9.
    • (1989) Constructions of Reason , pp. 138-139
    • As Onora, O.1
  • 10
    • 84935594790 scopus 로고
    • Mutual aid and respect for persons
    • See Barbara Herman, 'Mutual aid and respect for persons', Ethics, 94 (1984), 577-602, reprinted in Herman, The Practice of Moral Judgment (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1993), pp. 45-72.
    • (1984) Ethics , vol.94 , pp. 577-602
    • Herman, B.1
  • 12
    • 80053808851 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Carbondale and Edwardsville, IL: Southern Illinois University Press, section A
    • See the contrast Kant draws between temperament and character in Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View, trans. V. L. Dowdell and H. H. Rudnick (Carbondale and Edwardsville, IL: Southern Illinois University Press, 1996), part 2, section A.
    • (1996) Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View , Issue.PART 2
    • Dowdell, V.L.1    Rudnick, H.H.2
  • 15
    • 0346834831 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, for a very fine-grained treatment of these puzzles
    • See Paul Guyer, Kant on Freedom, Law, and Happiness (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), pp. 303-23, for a very fine-grained treatment of these puzzles.
    • (2000) Kant on Freedom, Law, and Happiness , pp. 303-323
    • Guyer, P.1
  • 16
    • 0009200422 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Basil Blackwell
    • On this question, and on the taxonomy of duties in Kant's practical philosophy generally, see Mary Gregor, Laws of Freedom (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1963), pp. 95-112;
    • (1963) Laws of Freedom , pp. 95-112
    • Gregor, M.1
  • 17
    • 0344914004 scopus 로고
    • New York: Columbia University Press
    • Onora Nell, Acting on Principle (New York: Columbia University Press, 1975), pp. 43-58;
    • (1975) Acting on Principle , pp. 43-58
    • Nell, O.1
  • 18
    • 60950661319 scopus 로고
    • From the Groundwork to the Metaphysics of Morals: What happened to morality in Kant's theory of justice?'
    • and Walter E. Schaller, 'From the Groundwork to the Metaphysics of Morals: what happened to morality in Kant's theory of justice?', History of Philosophy Quarterly, 12 (1995), 333-45.
    • (1995) History of Philosophy Quarterly , vol.12 , pp. 333-345
    • Schaller, W.E.1
  • 19
    • 67349200755 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There is more still contained in the claim that duties of right are duties for which external constraint is possible, but we need not attend to the further details here. I attempt a more comprehensive unpacking of the nuances of 'possibility' here in 'Necessity, deterrence and standing', Legal Theory, 8 (2002), 339-58.
    • (2002) Legal Theory , vol.8 , pp. 339-358
  • 20
    • 84876408038 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This 'offence', it seems to me, is the breach of a duty of respect, which, then, seems to be satisfied by a (mere) omission. But if this is right, we have the odd consequence that one might discharge a duty of virtue with base or at least amoral motives. On this question and other issues in Kant's treatment of the duties of love and respect I have not raised here see Baron, 'Love and respect in the Doctrine of Virtue', pp. 391-407.
    • Love and respect in the Doctrine of Virtue , pp. 391-407
    • Baron1
  • 21
    • 80053663986 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kantian respect and particular persons
    • Robert Noggle, 'Kantian respect and particular persons', Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 29 (1999), 455.
    • (1999) Canadian Journal of Philosophy , vol.29 , pp. 455
    • Noggle, R.1
  • 22
    • 33748676820 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Did Kant respect persons?
    • Michael Neuman, 'Did Kant respect persons?', Res Publica, 6 (2000), 299.
    • (2000) Res Publica , vol.6 , pp. 299
    • Neuman, M.1
  • 24
    • 84876417716 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Neuman similarly allows that the duty of beneficence requires us to consider the desires of others - and so that respect for persons is at least in part for persons as we ordinarily understand ourselves - but dismisses the significance of this owing to the fact that the duty of beneficence is, among other things, imperfect, and so 'not even a true moral obligation' (Neuman, 'Did Kant respect persons?', p. 298).
    • Did Kant respect persons , pp. 298
    • Neuman1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.