메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 42, Issue 4, 2004, Pages 449-488

Kant's model of causality: Causal powers, laws, and Kant's reply to Hume

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 60950219253     PISSN: 00225053     EISSN: 15384586     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1353/hph.2004.0081     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (20)

References (31)
  • 1
    • 79954876250 scopus 로고
    • e.g, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul
    • Hume's fuller views on causality are naturally more complex than the brief summary provided below indicates. For more comprehensive discussions, see, e.g., Barry Stroud, Hume (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1978),
    • (1978) Hume
    • Stroud, B.1
  • 6
    • 60950247507 scopus 로고
    • The Representation of Causation and Hume's Two Definitions of 'Cause'
    • and Don Garrett "The Representation of Causation and Hume's Two Definitions of 'Cause'," Nous 27 (1993) : 167-90.
    • (1993) Nous , vol.27 , pp. 167-190
    • Garrett, D.1
  • 7
    • 79954836972 scopus 로고
    • Moreover, the reception of Hume in Germany, documented by Günter Gawlick and Lothar Kreimendahl, Hume in der deutschen Aufklärung: Umrisse einer Rezeptionsgeschichte (Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: Frommann-Holzboog, 1987),
    • (1987) Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: Frommann-Holzboog
  • 8
    • 60949174120 scopus 로고
    • Kant's Conception of Hume's Problem
    • Moreover, since Hamann had certainly read the Treatise, he could have brought Hume's critical points to Kant's attention in their conversations, and, to make matters even less clear, one cannot necessarily count on Hamann for straightforward objective accuracy in representing Hume's views, since Hamann had a distinctive agenda that departed considerably from Hume's. A helpful historical discussion of this issue is Manfred Kuehn's "Kant's Conception of Hume's Problem," Journal of the History of Philosophy 21 (1983): 175-93. In this paper, I abstract from the complex historical details in order to focus on a systematic comparison of Kant's and Hume's positions.
    • (1983) Journal of the History of Philosophy , vol.21 , pp. 175-193
    • Kuehn, M.1
  • 9
    • 0003851654 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Paul Guyer and Allen Wood, ed. & trans. (New York: Cambridge University Press
    • Translations from the Critique of Pure Reason will be from Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, Paul Guyer and Allen Wood, ed. & trans. (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998).
    • (1998) Critique of Pure Reason
    • Kant, I.1
  • 10
    • 0346052766 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Karl Ameriks and Steve Naragon, ed. & trans. (New York: Cambridge University Press
    • Translations from Kant's lectures on metaphysics will be from Immanuel Kant, Lectures on Metaphysics, Karl Ameriks and Steve Naragon, ed. & trans. (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1997). In a few instances, I have made minor modifications in these translations.
    • (1997) Lectures on Metaphysics
    • Kant, I.1
  • 13
    • 0002328793 scopus 로고
    • Causal Laws and the Foundations of Natural Science
    • Paul Guyer, ed, New York: Cambridge University Press
    • Michael Friedman, "Causal Laws and the Foundations of Natural Science," in Paul Guyer, ed. The Cambridge Companion to Kant (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1992), 161-99,
    • (1992) The Cambridge Companion to Kant , pp. 161-199
    • Friedman, M.1
  • 14
    • 33748307132 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • and James Van Cleve, Problems from Kant (New York: Oxford University Press, 1999).
    • (1999) Problems from Kant
    • Van Cleve, J.1
  • 15
    • 54949153367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hume's Answer to Kant
    • Of course, hybrid interpretations are possible. For example, one common strategy is to establish the "every-event-some-cause" principle first and then use the idea that a causal rule implies generality in order to establish the "like-cause-like-effect" principle. See Lorne Falkenstein, "Hume's Answer to Kant," Nôs 32 (1998): 331-60.
    • (1998) Nôs , vol.32 , pp. 331-360
    • Falkenstein, L.1
  • 16
    • 0039599641 scopus 로고
    • The Development of Physical Influx in Early Eighteenth Century Germany: Gottsched, Knutzen, and Crusius
    • For a fuller assessment of the historical evidence (which does not lend support to this claim, but suggests rather that on the issue of causality Kant was focused more on Leibnizian-Wolffian considerations) , see my "The Development of Physical Influx in Early Eighteenth Century Germany: Gottsched, Knutzen, and Crusius," Review of Metaphysics 49 (1995): 295-339,
    • (1995) Review of Metaphysics , vol.49 , pp. 295-339
  • 17
    • 84945066062 scopus 로고
    • Kant's Theory of Physical Influx
    • and "Kant's Theory of Physical Influx," Archiv für Geschichte derPhilosophie 77 (1995): 285-324.
    • (1995) Archiv für Geschichte derPhilosophie , vol.77 , pp. 285-324
  • 18
    • 79954682993 scopus 로고
    • L.A. Selby-Bigge, ed., P.H. Nidditch, rev. (Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • See David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, L.A. Selby-Bigge, ed., P.H. Nidditch, rev. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978), 26-33.
    • (1978) A Treatise of Human Nature , pp. 26-33
    • Hume, D.1
  • 19
    • 0003743257 scopus 로고
    • See, for example, Hume's conclusion that "In a word, then, every effect is a distinct event from its cause," David Hume, An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1977), 19. Moreover, if Kant was not aware of Hume's actual position, then this fact ends up providing additional support for understanding Kant's reply to Hume as I do below.
    • (1977) An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding , pp. 19
    • Hume, D.1
  • 21
    • 0346218796 scopus 로고
    • New York: Cambridge University Press
    • 2 in A; this causally necessitates a later alteration in B; and so on" (178, emphasis added).
    • (1978) Kant: An Introduction
    • Broad, C.D.1
  • 22
    • 0013539391 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kant's Third Analogy of Experience
    • See my "Kant's Third Analogy of Experience," in Kant-Studien 88 (1997): 406-4:1, for a detailed reconstruction of Kant's argument in the Third Analogy.
    • (1997) Kant-Studien , vol.88 , pp. 406-404
  • 23
    • 79954674466 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mrongovius lectures: Causality is the determination of a cause by which it becomes a cause, or the determination of the relation of a thing as cause to a determined effect
    • See, for example, his Metaphysics Mrongovius lectures: "Causality is the determination of a cause by which it becomes a cause, or the determination of the relation of a thing as cause to a determined effect. Thus the cause is always to be distinguished from the causality" (29:893)
    • Thus the cause is always to be distinguished from the causality , pp. 893
    • Metaphysics1
  • 24
  • 25
    • 60949740238 scopus 로고
    • Kant on Self-Identity
    • For an interesting discussion of Kant's reply to Hume on the issue of self-consciousness, see Patricia Kitcher "Kant on Self-Identity," Philosophical Review 91 (1982): 41-72.
    • (1982) Philosophical Review , vol.91 , pp. 41-72
    • Kitcher, P.1
  • 27
    • 10844253693 scopus 로고
    • From Kant to Frank: The Ineliminable Subject
    • ed. K. Ameriks and D. Sturma Albany: SUNY Press
    • For helpful discussions of this aspect of Kant's account of self-consciousness, see Karl Ameriks "From Kant to Frank: The Ineliminable Subject," in The Modern Subject: Conceptions of the Self in Classical German Philosophy, ed. K. Ameriks and D. Sturma (Albany: SUNY Press, 1995), 217-30,
    • (1995) The Modern Subject: Conceptions of the Self in Classical German Philosophy , pp. 217-230
    • Ameriks, K.1
  • 28
    • 79954689921 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Is Subjectivity a Non-Thing, an Absurdity [Unding]? On Some Difficulties in Naturalistic Reductions of Self-Consciousness
    • and Manfred Frank "Is Subjectivity a Non-Thing, an Absurdity [Unding]? On Some Difficulties in Naturalistic Reductions of Self-Consciousness," in The Modern Subject, 177-97.
    • The Modern Subject , pp. 177-197
    • Frank, M.1
  • 29
    • 71449116717 scopus 로고
    • Berkeley's 'Notion' of Spiritual Substance
    • Berkeley encounters a similar difficulty on this point, since for him ideas are necessarily passive, yet the self is supposed to be active. He solves the problem by claiming that he has not an idea, but rather a "notion" of the self. While introducing a notion of the self in this fashion might initially seem to be ad hoc, Berkeley may be responding to an in dependent philosophical concern. For an excellent discussion of Berkeley's position, see Robert Adams "Berkeley's 'Notion' of Spiritual Substance," Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 55 (1973): 47-69.
    • (1973) Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie , vol.55 , pp. 47-69
    • Adams, R.1
  • 30
    • 0000694249 scopus 로고
    • Self-reference and Self-awareness
    • esp. 563
    • For perhaps different reasons, Shoemaker endorses both of these points in "Self-reference and Self-awareness," The Journal of Philosophy 65 (1968): 555-67, esp. 563, when he says: "I think that the main source of trouble here is the tendency to think of awareness as a kind of perception, i.e., to think of it on the model of sense-perception" and when he notes that if the use of first-person pronouns as a subject "were not possible then there would be much else, and much that we take for granted, that would also not be possible" (564).
    • (1968) The Journal of Philosophy , vol.65 , pp. 555-567
  • 31
    • 0041982165 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Stanford: CSLI Publications
    • For a discussion of how a formal (mathematical) framework could be filled in with mechanical and physical content, see Michael Friedman, The Dynamics of Reason (Stanford: CSLI Publications, 2001).
    • (2001) The Dynamics of Reason
    • Friedman, M.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.