메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 103, Issue 8, 2006, Pages 403-425

Error through misidentification: Some varieties

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 60950037321     PISSN: 0022362X     EISSN: 19398549     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.5840/jphil2006103824     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (37)

References (37)
  • 1
    • 0000694249 scopus 로고
    • Self-reference and Self-awareness
    • October 3
    • The label "(immunity to) error through misidentification" wasfirst introduced in the philosophical literature by Sydney Shoemaker, "Self-reference and Self-awareness, " this JOURNAL, LXV, 19 (October 3, 1968): 555-67,
    • (1968) JOURNAL , vol.65 , Issue.19 , pp. 555-567
  • 2
    • 0003904537 scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford
    • reprinted in Quassim Cassam, ed., Self-Knowledge (New York: Oxford, 1994), pp. 19-48
    • (1994) Self-Knowledge , pp. 19-48
    • Cassam, Q.1
  • 3
    • 84887680451 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Blackwell
    • (page reference to the latter) in connection with Wittgenstein'sdistinction, between uses of "I" as subject and as object - The Blue Book (Oxford: Blackwell, 1958), pp. 66-67.
    • (1958) The Blue Book , pp. 66-67
  • 4
    • 0004045957 scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford
    • The notion of quasi-memory is characterized by Gareth Evans as follows:"A subject q-remembers an event e if and only if (i) he has an apparentmemory of such an event, and (ii) that apparent memory in fact embodiesinformation deriving from the perception of that event by a person who is notnecessarily himself" - The Varieties of Reference (New York: Oxford, 1982), pp. 247-48. It is assumed that one could have memory impressions deriving fromsomeone else's past if one had the relevant brain cells transplanted into one'sbrain. Since quasi-memories and ordinary ones are phenomenologicallyindistinguishable, their phenomenological content is best expressed by locutionslike "I seem to remember being in Scotland five years ago, " or as"I have an (apparent) memory as of being in Scotland five years ago."It is then a further issue - an issue which I will not discuss in this paper -whether quasi-memories and ordinary ones should be taken to be intrinsically thesame kind of mental state whose difference resides merely in their differentcausal origins, or whether - in a "disjunctivist" spirit - they shouldbe taken, because of their different causal origin, as distinct and mutuallyexclusive mental states. For the purposes of this paper, we can be neutral onthis issue. For once it is allowed that memories and quasi-memories aresubjectively indistinguishable, it should also be allowed that the judgmentsbased on either of them will have the same structure of rational grounds. Therewill be more about the notion of grounds in the sequel. But to help fix ideas, Itake it that both in cases of memory-based self-ascriptions and in cases ofquasi-memory-based ones, subjects requested to justify them would offer thefollowing: "I seem to remember being F. Therefore, I was F."
    • (1982) The Varieties of Reference , pp. 247-248
  • 5
    • 77950025458 scopus 로고
    • Persons and Their Pasts
    • Shoemaker New York: Cambridge here pp. 23-24, 46
    • Shoemaker, "Persons and Their Pasts, " in his Identity, Cause, and Mind (New York: Cambridge, 1970), pp. 19-18, here see pp. 23-24, 46.
    • (1970) Identity, Cause, and Mind , pp. 19-18
  • 6
    • 79956895982 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Evans, pp. 235-48, here pp. 241-45
    • Evans, pp. 235-48, here pp. 241-45.
  • 7
    • 0003740191 scopus 로고
    • 222, New York: Oxford
    • See Parfit, Reasons and Persons (New York: Oxford, 1984), pp. 220, 222;
    • (1984) Reasons and Persons , pp. 220
    • Parfit1
  • 8
    • 0347864228 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reductionism and the First Person
    • Jonathan Dancy, ed. Malden, MA: Blackwell
    • and McDowell, "Reductionism and the First Person, " in Jonathan Dancy, ed., Reading Parfit (Malden, MA: Blackwell, 1997), pp. 230-50. Accordingto Parfit, memories, as such, have an identity-neutral content and can give oneinformation about the life of a specific human being only through theidentification of oneself with the person whose life is responsible for thememories one is having. Such an identification might be wrong but, moreimportantly, it could be made by different future selves. This would be the caseif, with an appropriate brain transplant, one's memories could survive in two(or more) different brains, belonging to two (or more) different human beings.Psychological continuity would then be preserved at the expense of personalidentity.
    • (1997) Reading Parfit , pp. 230-250
    • McDowell1
  • 9
    • 84855712933 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Personal Identity: Ethical Not Metaphysical
    • Graham F. Mac Donald and Cynthia Mac Donald, eds MA: Blackwell
    • The driving thought behind McDowell's position is that memories haveimmediate and irreducible first-person content. According to him, this is sobecause memories have the specific, biologically-selected function to retain, for each specific human being, information about his own past, and make itimmediately available to him in the first-person mode of thought. Memories, therefore, are situated in the life of a specific human being and this latterfact, contrary to what Locke and Parfit seem to maintain, cannot be abstractedaway in giving an account of persons and their identity. For an illuminatingdiscussion of Parfit's and McDowell's positions, see Carol Rovane, "Personal Identity: Ethical Not Metaphysical, " in Graham F. Mac Donaldand Cynthia Mac Donald, eds., McDowell and His Critics (Malden, MA: Blackwell, 2006), forthcoming.
    • (2006) McDowell and His Critics Malden
    • Rovane, C.1
  • 10
    • 0004208613 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford
    • Peacocke, Being Known (New York: Oxford, 1999), p. 263. The task oflocating the exact source of such a challenge in the case of reflections on theself - whether in what Peacocke calls the phenomenon of " representationalindependence" or in something else - falls outside the scope of this paper.
    • (1999) Being Known , pp. 263
    • Peacocke1
  • 11
    • 33748857143 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Self-knowledge: The Wittgensteinian Legacy
    • Wright, Barry Smith, and Cynthia McDonald, eds New York: Oxford
    • Evans, McDowell, Peacocke, and Crispin Wright in his "Self- knowledge: The Wittgensteinian Legacy, " in Wright, Barry Smith, and Cynthia McDonald, eds., Knowing Our Own Minds (New York: Oxford, 1998), pp. 13-45, justto mention the most prominent figures, have all made these points. Thearguments are usually that immunity to error through misidentification is commonto both some uses of "I" and, for example, to perceptualdemonstrative judgments, for which there is no temptation to think they may notrefer; and that immunity is a function of the absence of any identificationcomponent in the rational grounds for a given first person judgment and not ofthe fact that either there is no self to be identified in the first place, orthat the identification is secured by the special kind of entity presented toone for recognition.
    • (1998) Knowing Our Own Minds , pp. 13-45
    • Evans1    McDowell2    Peacocke3    Wright, C.4
  • 12
    • 79956930648 scopus 로고
    • Wittgenstein and the First Person
    • With respect to the former issue, we will see in the following thatmatters are far from being settled. With respect to the latter, nowadays nobodywould agree with Wittgenstein's position that all and only psychologicalself-ascriptions are immune to error though misidentification (but for adifferent interpretation of Wittgenstein's position, see Brian Garrett, "Wittgenstein and the First Person, " Australasian Journal of Philosophy, LXXIII (1995): 347-55). Since Shoemaker and Evans, it has becomecommonplace to hold that also nonpsychological self-ascriptions, such as thosebased on memory, perception, and somatic proprioception, as well asperception-based demonstrative judgments are immune to error throughmisidentification. Moreover, since Evans (see pp. 219-20), it has been widelyheld that inferential psychological self-ascriptions are liable to error throughmisidentification.
    • (1995) Australasian Journal of Philosophy , vol.73 , pp. 347-355
    • Garrett, B.1
  • 13
    • 0000244642 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Space of Reasons and Thinking as a Motor Process
    • Finally, John Campbell by appealing to the phenomenon of "thoughtinsertion", whereby schizophrenic patients claim that they have a giventhought which is not theirs, has gone so far as to argue that alsononinferential ones can be liable to such an error - see "Schizophrenia:The Space of Reasons and Thinking as a Motor Process, " The Monist, LXXXII(1999): 609-25.
    • (1999) The Monist , vol.82 , pp. 609-625
    • Schizophrenia1
  • 14
    • 0242399179 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thought Insertion and Immunity to Error through Misidentification, and What There Really Is to Our Notion of the Ownership of a Thought
    • 41-46
    • (For a discussion critical of Campbell's position, see my "Thought Insertion and Immunity to Error through Misidentification, " and "What There Really Is to Our Notion of the Ownership of a Thought, " Philosophy, Psychology and Psychiatry, IX, 1 (2002): 27-34, 41-46;
    • (2002) Philosophy, Psychology and Psychiatry , vol.9 , Issue.1 , pp. 27-34
  • 16
    • 33748876956 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Immunity to Error through Misidentification
    • Pryor, "Immunity to Error through Misidentification, "Philosophical Topics, XXVI, 1 (1998): 271-304.
    • (1998) Philosophical Topics , vol.26 , Issue.1 , pp. 271-304
    • Pryor1
  • 17
    • 79956933424 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Evans, pp. 235-48
    • See Evans, pp. 235-48;
  • 18
    • 79956933427 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • McDowell, pp. 239-41
    • McDowell, pp. 239-41;
  • 19
    • 60949986203 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wright, p. 20
    • Wright, p. 20.
  • 20
    • 0003575399 scopus 로고
    • Shoemaker Ithaca: Cornell
    • and McDowell. It should be noticed, however, that while Shoemaker himselfheld the view that memory-based self-ascriptions are grounded in first-personalmemory impressions (Shoemaker, Self-Knowledge and Self-Identity (Ithaca:Cornell, 1963), pp. 33-34)
    • (1963) Self-Knowledge and Self-Identity , pp. 33-34
  • 21
    • 60949412179 scopus 로고
    • Introspection and the Self
    • Shoemaker New York: Cambridge see p. 15
    • and yet, in the abnormal conditions envisaged, may be liable to errorthrough misidentification (Shoemaker, "Introspection and the Self, " inhis The First Person Perspective and Other Essays (New York: Cambridge, 1986), pp. 3-24 , see p. 15), it is in fact Parfit (pp. 220, 222), who has contributedto spreading the view that memory-based self-ascriptions are always based onidentity-neutral memory impressions and arrived at by holding in place therelevant identity beliefs.
    • (1986) The First Person Perspective and Other Essays , pp. 3-24
  • 22
    • 79956895938 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Evans, chapters 6, 7
    • Evans, chapters 6, 7;
  • 23
    • 0003434441 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford
    • and Peacocke, Sense and Content (New York: Oxford, 1983), pp. 143-14.
    • (1983) Sense and Content , pp. 143-214
    • Peacocke1
  • 24
    • 79956967232 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pryor, p. 281
    • Pryor, p. 281.
  • 25
    • 79956957502 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pryor, p. 283
    • Pryor, p. 283.
  • 26
    • 79956957500 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chapters 6, 7; Peacocke
    • See, for instance, Evans, chapters 6, 7; Peacocke, Sense and Content, pp.143-44.
    • Sense and Content , pp. 143-144
    • Evans1
  • 27
    • 85047280248 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Split between Speaker's and Semantic Reference and the Real Guarantee
    • August
    • The point is not taken universally. In my "Error through Misidentification, the Split between Speaker's and Semantic Reference and the Real Guarantee, " this JOURNAL, C, 8 (August 2003): 216-31,
    • (2003) JOURNAL , vol.C , Issue.8 , pp. 216-231
  • 28
    • 0007203416 scopus 로고
    • The First Person
    • Simon Guttenplan, ed New York: Oxford
    • discuss extensively those interpretations of error throughmisidentification which take it to be a referential mistake, such as Elisabeth Anscombe, "The First Person, " in Simon Guttenplan, ed., Mind and Language: Wolfson College Lectures 1974 (New York: Oxford, 1975), pp. 45-64;
    • (1975) Mind and Language: Wolfson College Lectures 1974 , pp. 45-64
    • Anscombe, E.1
  • 29
    • 40049087196 scopus 로고
    • First Person: The Demand for Identification-free Self-Reference
    • April
    • Andrea Christofidou, "First Person: The Demand for Identification-free Self-Reference, " this JOURNAL, XCII, 4 (April 1995):223-34;
    • (1995) JOURNAL , vol.92 , Issue.4 , pp. 223-234
    • Christofidou, A.1
  • 30
    • 0003827356 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Princeton: University Press
    • and Rovane, The Bounds of Agency (Princeton: University Press, 1998). Onthese latter views, when that error occurs, in using "a" one would infact refer to the person visually presented to one, rather than to its semanticreferent. So, in the Aunt Miriam example, when I am in the car park and Imistake a red-hatted woman approaching for Aunt Miriam, by saying "Aunt Miriam is wearing a red hat" I would be (speaker-) referring to the womanwho is actually approaching and not to my aunt. Since they do not find thisoutcome plausible in the case of the use of "I, " they conclude thatself-ascriptions are (almost) always immune to error through misidentification.In the paper I put forward the view that such an interpretation might in fact bebased on a conflation between (immunity to) error through misidentification, the (im)possibility of a split between speaker's and semantic reference and what I label the "real guarantee": namely, the fact that any competent useof "I" is such that the speaker knows which object is its semanticreferent, namely, oneself.
    • (1998) The Bounds of Agency
    • Rovane1
  • 33
    • 0039916411 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Skeptic and the Dogmatist
    • pp. 537-38
    • and Pryor's "The Skeptic and the Dogmatist, " Noûs, XXIV(2000): 517-49 - here pp. 537-38, respectively. So, in my view, althoughthey do not explicitly distinguish between the subject's own grounds for a givenjudgment and the background presuppositions of it, the best way of interpretingtheir dispute is to read it as bearing on whether background presuppositionsneed (or need not) be warranted.
    • (2000) Noûs , vol.24 , pp. 517-549
    • Pryor1
  • 34
    • 79956957412 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schizophrenia, the Space of Reasons and Thinking as a Motor Process, and Rovane
    • I take it that Evans and McDowell do both at least implicitly challengethe de facto side when they deny that a mere difference in metaphysicalconditions would make memory-based self-ascriptions liable to error throughmisidentification. Campbell, "Schizophrenia, the Space of Reasons and Thinking as a Motor Process, " and Rovane, The Bounds of Agency, pp. 220-32, openly challenge the logical side of it. While I have voiced my perplexitiesabout Campbell's and Rovane's proposals elsewhere (see my "Thought Insertion and Immunity to Error through Misidentification, " "What There Really Is to Our Own Notion of the Ownership of a Thought, " and"Immunity to Error through Misidentification, the Split between Speaker'sand Semantic Reference, and the Real Guarantee"), in the following I willargue that Evans and McDowell can, at most, claim for a revision of that notionin a more epistemologically-oriented direction, whose proper explanationcrucially depends on allowing for the existence of identification components aspart of a judgment's background presuppositions, contrary to Evans's officialposition (cf. footnote 11).
    • The Bounds of Agency , pp. 220-232
    • Campbell1
  • 36
    • 79956957481 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Being Known, p. 275
    • and Being Known, p. 275;


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.