메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 102, Issue 7, 2005, Pages 327-356

Evaluating social reasons: Hobbes versus Hegel

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 60950002772     PISSN: 0022362X     EISSN: 19398549     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.5840/jphil2005102713     Document Type: Conference Paper
Times cited : (13)

References (40)
  • 1
    • 84930561211 scopus 로고
    • Reason and Agreement in Social Contract Views
    • (Spring)
    • The importance of such reasons has been stressed by a number of philosophers in recent years. See, for instance, Samuel Freeman, "Reason and Agreement in Social Contract Views," Philosophy and Public Affairs, XIX, 2 (Spring 1990): 122-57, who calls such reasons "public," and uses them to distinguish Hobbesian from Rousseauvian social contract theories;
    • (1990) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.19 , Issue.2 , pp. 122-157
    • Freeman, S.1
  • 3
    • 0000757630 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Reasons We Can Share
    • (New York: Cambridge)
    • and "The Reasons We Can Share," reprinted in Creating the Kingdom of Ends (New York: Cambridge, 1996), pp. 275-310, where she refers to reasons as intersubjective and finds their original articulation in Kant;
    • (1996) Creating the Kingdom of Ends , pp. 275-310
  • 4
    • 0010083144 scopus 로고
    • Explanation and Practical Reason, Irreducibly Social Goods, and to Follow a Rule
    • (Cambridge: Harvard) 127-45, 165-80
    • Charles Taylor, "Explanation and Practical Reason," "Irreducibly Social Goods," and "To Follow a Rule," all reprinted in Philosophical Arguments (Cambridge: Harvard, 1995), pp. 34-60, 127-45, 165-80, where he talks of "common understandings" and traces their importance in practical reasoning to Hegel and Wittgenstein;
    • (1995) Philosophical Arguments , pp. 34-60
    • Taylor, C.1
  • 5
    • 79956401563 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Four Models of Practical Reasoning
    • (New York: Cambridge)
    • and Onora O'Neill, "Four Models of Practical Reasoning," reprinted in Bounds of Justice (New York: Cambridge, 2000), pp. 11-28, where she contrasts "action-based" accounts of practical reason with "teleological" ones, tracing the former back to Hegel, Wittgenstein, and Kant, and the latter to Plato and Hume.
    • (2000) Bounds of Justice , pp. 11-28
    • O'Neill, O.1
  • 6
    • 60950094318 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Outline of a Theory of Reasonable Deliberation
    • (December)
    • I have described such reasons elsewhere as "we"-reasons. See my "Outline of a Theory of Reasonable Deliberation," Canadian Journal of Philosophy, XXX (December 2000): 551-80.
    • (2000) Canadian Journal of Philosophy , vol.30 , pp. 551-580
  • 7
    • 0004262394 scopus 로고
    • (Princeton: University Press)
    • I borrow the term "plural subject" from Margaret Gilbert, who uses it in her analysis of collective action and intention. See, for instance, her On Social Facts (Princeton: University Press, 1989). I use it in a somewhat looser fashion, though in the same spirit: roughly, a plural subject exists any time it is appropriate for its members to refer to it using the first person plural.
    • (1989) On Social Facts
  • 11
    • 0004073426 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Joel Anderson, trans. (Cambridge: MIT,)
    • and Axel Honneth, The Struggle for Recognition, Joel Anderson, trans. (Cambridge: MIT, 1996). Note also that while the Hegelian approach draws on some resources to be found in the work of Hegel, it does not exhaust them. My reason for drawing on some but not all of the resources in Hegel is that those I draw on are less intricately connected to Hegel's full metaphysical system and thus are more accessible to those of a Hobbesian persuasion.
    • (1996) The Struggle for Recognition
    • Honneth, A.1
  • 12
    • 0003867020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Cambridge: Harvard,)
    • It thus also has affinities with the contractualist view of T.M. Scanlon. See his What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge: Harvard, 1999). In particular, I think the Hegelian approach discussed below provides a helpful framework for thinking about the appropriate criteria for reasonable rejection within Scanlon's theory. On the difference between theories of rational choice and theories of reasonable deliberation, see my "Outline of a Theory of Reasonable Deliberation."
    • (1999) What We Owe to Each Other
    • Scanlon, T.M.1
  • 13
    • 0007310158 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Idea of Public Reason Revisited
    • Freeman ed, Cambridge: Harvard
    • See, for instance, Rawls, "The Idea of Public Reason Revisited," reprinted in Collected Papers, Freeman, ed. (Cambridge: Harvard, 1999), pp. 573-615.
    • (1999) Collected Papers , pp. 573-615
    • Rawls1
  • 14
    • 85012444788 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Team Preferences
    • See Sugden, "Team Preferences," Economics and Philosophy, XVI (2000): 175-204;
    • (2000) Economics and Philosophy , vol.16 , pp. 175-204
    • Sugden1
  • 15
    • 0009949549 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Interactive Team Reasoning: A Contribution to the Theory of Cooperation
    • and Bacharach, "Interactive Team Reasoning: A Contribution to the Theory of Cooperation," Research in Economics, LII (1999): 117-47. In team reasoning, each member of a team figures out what to do by figuring out what set of moves would jointly produce the best result for the team, and then doing her part.
    • (1999) Research in Economics , vol.52 , pp. 117-147
    • Bacharach1
  • 16
    • 79956404783 scopus 로고
    • Rational Fools
    • (Cambridge: MIT), chapter 4
    • There is another question which lies in these waters and from which it is important to distinguish the question that concerns me here: To what degree must the interests that ultimately ground reasons be subjective? According to some formulations of rational choice theory, reasons must find support in the satisfaction of preferences or a change in utility. Such theories will have to account for George's concern for Alice with something akin to sympathy. Amartya Sen accuses such theories of describing "rational fools" and suggests that an adequate account of rationality will have to take account of more objective sources of reasons, such as what he calls commitments. See his "Rational Fools," reprinted in Choice, Welfare, and Measurement (Cambridge: MIT, 1982), chapter 4. Sen's concern is with how broadly we conceive of individual interests, and thus with what can inform the individual evaluative standpoint. Mine, in contrast, is with how to evaluate reasons that do not appeal to that standpoint, however broadly construed. Clearly there is some overlap between the questions, as the more broadly we construe the individual standpoint, the wider the terrain of reasons it can support. Nevertheless, the sub-Hobbesian could accept objective sources of individual interest without thereby abandoning his claim that all reasons must be evaluated from the individual standpoint.
    • (1982) Choice, Welfare, and Measurement
  • 17
    • 0040936835 scopus 로고
    • Edwin Curley, ed, Indianapolis: Hackett
    • Hobbes, Leviathan, Edwin Curley, ed. (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1994);
    • (1994) Leviathan
    • Hobbes1
  • 19
    • 79956401526 scopus 로고
    • (Cambridge: MIT)
    • There is a deep question of Hobbes interpretation here that I want to bracket. Hobbes's belief in the kind of indirect reduction that lies at the heart of Gauthier's work is displayed most prominently in the argument against the Fool in Leviathan. His more orthodox tendencies appear most clearly in his claims that the laws of nature do not bind in the absence of an enforcer. In calling the approach outlined in this section Hobbesian, I mean to invoke the Hobbes who argues against the Fool. The more orthodox game-theoretic work of someone like Ken Binmore also claims to be Hobbesian, but allies itself with the other aspect of Hobbes's view. See his Game Theory and the Social Contract, Volume I: Playing Fair and Volume II: Just Playing (Cambridge: MIT, 1994).
    • (1994) Game Theory and the Social Contract, I: Playing Fair and II: Just Playing
  • 20
    • 0002921553 scopus 로고
    • Two Concepts of Rules
    • It will help some readers at this point to draw a connection between this approach and Rawls's discussion of practices in "Two Concepts of Rules," The Philosophical Review, LXIV, 1 (1955): 3-32
    • (1955) The Philosophical Review , vol.64 , Issue.1 , pp. 3-32
  • 21
    • 84897924575 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • reprinted in Collected Papers, pp. 20-46. Social reasons are reasons internal to a practice. Their immediate authority stems from the constitutive features of the practice. The Hobbesian claims, however, that only practices that I can support from my individual evaluative standpoint can generate reasons with normative force. Thus, while the reasons within a practice need not appeal to our individual interests, the reasons that support the practice as a whole do.
    • Collected Papers , pp. 20-46
  • 22
    • 84870789968 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chapter 18, pars. 1-2
    • Hobbes, Leviathan, p. 110 (chapter 18, pars. 1-2);
    • Leviathan , pp. 110
    • Hobbes1
  • 23
    • 77954362573 scopus 로고
    • C.B. MacPherson, ed. (Indianapolis: Hackett,) (§222)
    • John Locke, Second Treatise of Government, C.B. MacPherson, ed. (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1980), p. 111 (§222).
    • (1980) Second Treatise of Government , pp. 111
    • Locke, J.1
  • 24
    • 0003516201 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • H.B. Nisbet, trans., Allen Wood, ed. (New York: Cambridge), §158
    • Hegel, Elements of the Philosophy of Right, H.B. Nisbet, trans., Allen Wood, ed. (New York: Cambridge, 1991), §158.
    • (1991) Elements of the Philosophy of Right
    • Hegel1
  • 25
    • 0242692920 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Ithaca: Cornell), especially chapter 6
    • This, of course, raises the question of what to say about cases where a social reason is presented to me on grounds that I belong to a plural subject, where I would reject such membership, or where despite the accuracy of the ascription, it is not one I happily assent to. Clearly, this possibility and its apparent structural similarity to the kinds of cases I have been discussing raises serious problems for any broadly Hegelian account. Nevertheless, I bracket them here, as I think a full description of the Hegelian picture even in the ideal situation where all membership in plural subjects are endorsed and affirmed, is sufficiently difficult and controversial without adding in this further wrinkle. I do, however, think that the model I develop below has the resources to address this problem. For further discussion of this point, see my Reasonably Radical (Ithaca: Cornell, 2001), especially chapter 6.
    • (2001) Reasonably Radical
  • 27
    • 0010918842 scopus 로고
    • (New York: Cambridge)
    • This harmony is one of the things that makes the modern social world worthy of what Hegel calls "reconciliation." For a discussion of the importance of reconciliation to Hegel's work, and the argument that the modern social world is worthy of reconciliation, see Michael Hardimon, Hegel's Social Philosophy: The Project of Reconciliation (New York: Cambridge, 1994). Note that the project of reconciliation involves showing each member of modern society that they can comfortably occupy their various plural subjects, that these practical identities fit together, rather than showing, as the Hobbesian would aim to do, that they are each mutually advantageous.
    • (1994) Hegel's Social Philosophy: The Project of Reconciliation
    • Hardimon, M.1
  • 28
    • 0003516201 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • §77
    • Hegel makes precisely this point about contracts; see Elements of the Philosophy of Right, §77. It forms one of the grounds of his criticism of social contract theory; see §75.
    • Elements of the Philosophy of Right
  • 29
    • 85039098569 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Taylor would, I think, deny this point. He claims that the goodness of an irreducibly social good requires not only our common understanding of the good, but our common valuation of it as good. See "Irreducibly Social Goods," p. 139. The Hegelian position described above differs from Taylor on this point. According to the view I am articulating here, whether the evaluation of social reasons can devolve back to individual members of the plural subject depends on the particular content and constitution of the plural subject, not merely on its being plural. This view is thus vulnerable to the sophisticated Hobbesian objection in a way that Taylor's view might not be. On the other hand, it is also thereby a position a Hobbesian might be more likely to find attractive.
    • Irreducibly Social Goods , pp. 139
  • 30
    • 33749712305 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This also marks a difference with Taylor's view, as I understand it. For Taylor, practical reason involves a kind of interpretational discovery rather than a kind of mutual (re)-construction. See, for instance, "Explanation and Practical Reason," p. 36. The claim that there is a fact of the matter about what practical reasons there are that is prior to the act of reasoning together, then, is a point on which Taylor agrees with the Hobbesian and not the Hegelian.
    • Explanation and Practical Reason , pp. 36
  • 31
    • 79956407592 scopus 로고
    • Four Models of Practical Reasoning; Barbara Herman
    • (Cambridge: Harvard)
    • Much philosophical discussion that distinguishes Hobbesian from Kantian or Rousseauvian approaches to practical reason has focused on this substantive difference. See, for instance, O'Neill, "Four Models of Practical Reasoning"; Barbara Herman, The Practice of Moral Judgment (Cambridge: Harvard, 1993).
    • (1993) The Practice of Moral Judgment
    • O'Neill1
  • 32
    • 84868434206 scopus 로고
    • The Politics of Redemption
    • The core of this idea in Rousseau is described in Gauthier, "The Politics of Redemption," Revue de l'Université d'Ottawa, XLIX (1979): 329-56
    • (1979) Revue de l'Université d'Ottawa , vol.49 , pp. 329-356
    • Gauthier1
  • 33
    • 0003499773 scopus 로고
    • (Idiaca: Cornell), especially pp. 92-94
    • reprinted in Moral Dealing: Contract, Ethics, and Reason (Idiaca: Cornell, 1990), pp. 77-109, especially pp. 92-94.
    • (1990) Moral Dealing: Contract, Ethics, and Reason , pp. 77-109
  • 34
    • 84922894776 scopus 로고
    • Social Contract as Ideology
    • (Winter)
    • The general approach, as well as its connection to Hegel, forms the backdrop of Gauthier, "Social Contract as Ideology," Philosophy and Public Affairs, VI, 1 (Winter 1977): 130-64
    • (1977) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.6 , Issue.1 , pp. 130-164
    • Gauthier1
  • 35
    • 85039111269 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • reprinted in Moral Dealing, pp. 325-54.
    • Moral Dealing , pp. 325-354
  • 36
    • 84925888891 scopus 로고
    • Justice and Natural Endowment
    • Inconsistency with a deep fact of human nature seems to be what sinks Rousseau in "The Politics of Redemption." Inconsistency with our "everyday awareness of ourselves" prevents this theory from providing a reconciliation between rationality and Rawls's theory of justice in Gauthier, "Justice and Natural Endowment," Social Theory and Practice, III (1974): 3-26
    • (1974) Social Theory and Practice , vol.3 , pp. 3-26
    • Gauthier1
  • 37
    • 0039564168 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Cambridge: Harvard), especially chapter 2
    • One exemplary exception to this, whose argument I follow below, is Elijah Millgram, Practical Induction (Cambridge: Harvard, 1997), especially chapter 2.
    • (1997) Practical Induction
    • Millgram, E.1
  • 38
    • 85039123558 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chapter 7
    • I discuss the place of such reasons in political deliberation in my Reasonably Radical, chapter 7.
    • Reasonably Radical
  • 40
    • 0004199157 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Ithaca: Cornell)
    • It seems to me that there might be quite interesting constraints beyond the obvious "can't be in two places at once" variety, and that thinking about the relationship between practical reasoning and the individual self from this perspective might shed light on both practical reasoning and the self. For a taste of the kind of reflection and constraints I have in mind, see Marya Schechtman, The Constitution of Selves (Ithaca: Cornell, 1996), especially part II, where she develops what she calls a narrative view of the self.
    • (1996) The Constitution of Selves
    • Schechtman, M.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.