메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 44, Issue 1, 2006, Pages 25-45

Hume on promises and the peculiar act of the mind

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 60949936918     PISSN: 00225053     EISSN: 15384586     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1353/hph.2006.0007     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (9)

References (22)
  • 2
    • 0004088235 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2nd ed., eds. L. A. Selby-Bigge and P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • numerals following 'SBN' indicate a page in David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, 2nd ed., eds. L. A. Selby-Bigge and P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1978).
    • (1978) A Treatise of Human Nature
    • Hume, D.1
  • 3
    • 80053887612 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard Press ch.10
    • For example, there is no discussion of the peculiar act of mind in the otherwise illuminating account of Hume's theory of promise given by Annette Baier in A Progress of Sentiments [Progress] (Cambridge, MA: Harvard Press, 1991), ch.10. I have learned a great deal, however, from Baier's detailed and perceptive interpretation.
    • (1991) Annette Baier in A Progress of Sentiments [Progress]
  • 4
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge. MA: Harvard University Press
    • John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge. MA: Harvard University Press, 1971). 344-50;
    • (1971) A Theory of Justice , pp. 344-350
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 6
    • 0003867020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard Press ch. 7
    • and What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, MA: Harvard Press, 1998), ch. 7.
    • (1998) What We Owe to Each Other
  • 7
    • 80053686176 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hume's Difficulty with the Virtue of Honesty
    • See Rachel Cohon. "Hume's Difficulty with the Virtue of Honesty," Hume Studies 23 (1997) : 91-112. In the present text I spell out the parallel process for promise-keeping.
    • (1997) Hume Studies , vol.23 , pp. 91-112
    • Cohon, R.1
  • 8
    • 0004316542 scopus 로고
    • Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press
    • One interpreter who reads this text as I do, as saying that moral approval and disapproval strengthened by "propaganda" provide a principal motive of just action, is Páll S. Árdal, Passion and Value in Hume's Treatise (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1966), 186-87 (where he sees the resultant problem of circularity as basically insoluble).
    • (1966) Passion and Value in Hume's Treatise , pp. 186-187
    • Árdal, S.1
  • 9
    • 0004101434 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • London: Routledge
    • J. L. Mackie, in Hume's Moral Theory (London: Routledge, 1980), 100-101, thinks moral sentiment plays some role in motivation. Self-interest is the principal motive, but our interests will be well served only if people develop stable dispositions to keep promises even where it does not serve their interest to do so. We fulfill the occasional disadvantageous promise because the human psyche is inflexible: "dispositions. cannot be quickly switched on and off." (So, no further motive would seem to be involved.) But the development of the full disposition to keep promises depends upon moral feeling: "the very fact that I have promised to do something should be felt to give me a reason for doing it."
    • (1980) Hume's Moral Theory , pp. 100-101
    • Mackie, J.L.1
  • 12
    • 80053834821 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, Part II, esp. chs. 7 and 9 see, e.g
    • Francis Snare, Morals, Motivation and Convention (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1991), Part II, esp. chs. 7 and 9 (see, e.g., 265-69).
    • (1991) Morals, Motivation and Convention , pp. 265-269
    • Snare, F.1
  • 13
    • 80053749208 scopus 로고
    • Artificial Virtues and the Sensible Knave" ["Artificial Virtues"]
    • David Gauthier, "Artificial Virtues and the Sensible Knave" ["Artificial Virtues"], Hume Studies 18 (1992): 401-27.
    • (1992) Hume Studies , vol.18 , pp. 401-427
    • Gauthier, D.1
  • 14
    • 84880851660 scopus 로고
    • Hume's Noble Lie: an Account of his Artificial Virtues
    • To some extent, and in different ways, both Gauthier and Haakonssen are indebted to Marcia Baron's account of Hume's artificial virtues as involving a "noble lie" we all must believe in order to possess fidelity and honesty: the lie that every act of compliance serves the agent's own interest. See "Hume's Noble Lie: an Account of his Artificial Virtues." Canadian Journal of Philosophy 12 (1982): 539-55,
    • (1982) Canadian Journal of Philosophy , vol.12 , pp. 539-555
  • 15
    • 61149117876 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aldershot: Ashgate/Dartmouth
    • repr. in Hume: Moral and Political Philosophy, ed. Rachel Cohen (Aldershot: Ashgate/Dartmouth, 2001). Gauthier thinks that the Hume of the Treatise does not see it as a lie-he believes it himself, but the Hume of the moral Enquiry realizes its falsehood.
    • (2001) Hume: Moral and Political Philosophy
    • Cohen, R.1
  • 16
    • 80053830683 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Gauthier's interpretation of the Treatise, the peculiar act of the mind may be mistakenly postulated by nonconventionalists (although he does not say why they would postulate the willing of an obligation rather than just some non-moral motive or other), and perhaps an illusion of it resides in the popular imagination (though he does not say why it would). But Hume himself "has no need to burden his own account with such an act" (Gauthier, "Artificial Virtues," 416). However, alas for Hume, he does it anyway.
    • Artificial Virtues , pp. 416
    • Gauthier1
  • 17
    • 27844552003 scopus 로고
    • On The Primacy of Character
    • eds. O. Flanagan and A. O. Rorty Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
    • See G. Watson, "On The Primacy of Character," in Identity, Character and Morality: Essays in Moral Psychology, eds. O. Flanagan and A. O. Rorty (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1990), 449-69;
    • (1990) Identity, Character and Morality: Essays in Moral Psychology , pp. 449-469
    • Watson, G.1
  • 18
    • 0000322565 scopus 로고
    • Virtue and Reason
    • and J. McDowell, "Virtue and Reason," Monist 62 (1979), 331-50.
    • (1979) Monist , vol.62 , pp. 331-350
    • McDowell, J.1
  • 19
    • 0348123860 scopus 로고
    • Applying Virtue Ethics
    • eds. R. Hursthouse, G. Lawrence and W.S. Quinn Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Some virtue theorists will be perfectly happy with this result. See Rosalind Hursthouse, "Applying Virtue Ethics," in Virtues and Reasons: Philippa Foot and Moral Theory, eds. R. Hursthouse, G. Lawrence and W.S. Quinn (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995), 57-75.
    • (1995) Virtues and Reasons: Philippa Foot and Moral Theory , pp. 57-75
    • Hursthouse, R.1
  • 21
    • 0000685612 scopus 로고
    • The Schizophrenia of Modern Moral Theories" [" Schizophrenia"]
    • Michael Stocker, "The Schizophrenia of Modern Moral Theories" ["Schizophrenia"], Journal of Philosophy 73 (1976): 453-66.
    • (1976) Journal of Philosophy , vol.73 , pp. 453-466
    • Stocker, M.1
  • 22
    • 37949022958 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Bernard Williams, "Persons, Character and Morality," in his Moral Luck (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981). 18. (Williams's actual example is more complex than this, and is aimed to make a subtler point, in criticism of Kantian ethics. He thinks that should the man reason that saving his wife in preference to a stranger is permissible and not unfair to the stranger, this would be "one thought too many" and incompatible with genuine love, which would motivate him to save her solely because it is she who needs saving.)
    • (1981) Persons, Character and Morality, in his Moral Luck , pp. 18
    • Williams, B.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.