메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 24, Issue 2, 2006, Pages 147-161

Correct logos and truth in Gorgias' Encomium of Helen

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 60949700616     PISSN: 07348584     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1525/rh.2006.24.2.147     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (15)

References (50)
  • 2
    • 85187416703 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Segal, Psychology of the Logos, 102.
    • Segal, "Psychology of the Logos," 102
  • 3
    • 85187417010 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Segal, Psychology of the Logos, 112.
    • Segal, "Psychology of the Logos," 112
  • 4
    • 85187426267 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Segal, Psychology of the Logos, 127.
    • Segal, "Psychology of the Logos," 127
  • 6
    • 85187413929 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On a similar note, W. K. C. Guthrie, The Sophists (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1971) 50, describes Gorgias' rhetoric as sophistic in every sense, where sophistic carries the same meaning of murky and shifty as it does in Plato's dialogues. Also on Gorgias' theory of logos in relation to deception and tragedy, Robert Wardy, The Birth of Rhetoric: Gorgias, Plato, and Their Successors (London: Routledge, 1996), 25-51.
    • On a similar note, W. K. C. Guthrie, The Sophists (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1971) 50, describes Gorgias' rhetoric as "sophistic in every sense," where "sophistic" carries the same meaning of murky and shifty as it does in Plato's dialogues. Also on Gorgias' theory of logos in relation to deception and tragedy, see Robert Wardy, The Birth of Rhetoric: Gorgias, Plato, and Their Successors (London: Routledge, 1996), 25-51
  • 7
    • 85187435548 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jacqueline de Romilly, The Great Sophists in Periclean Athens, trans. J. Lloyd (Oxford: Clarendon, 1992).
    • "Jacqueline de Romilly, The Great Sophists in Periclean Athens, trans. J. Lloyd (Oxford: Clarendon, 1992)
  • 8
    • 85187483869 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • So too George Kennedy, The Art of Persuasion in Greece (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1963), 61-68, and Classical Rhetoric and Its Christian and Secular Tradition from Ancient to Modern Times (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1999), 34-36, who concentrates on Gorgias' stylistic innovations in an effort to demonstrate their effectiveness.
    • So too George Kennedy, The Art of Persuasion in Greece (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1963), 61-68, and Classical Rhetoric and Its Christian and Secular Tradition from Ancient to Modern Times (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1999), 34-36, who concentrates on Gorgias' stylistic innovations in an effort to demonstrate their effectiveness
  • 9
    • 85187485249 scopus 로고
    • The Epistemology of Gorgias' Rhetoric: A Re-Examination
    • Richard Leo Enos, "The Epistemology of Gorgias' Rhetoric: A Re-Examination," The Southern Speech Communication Journal 42 (1976): 35-51 (p. 50)
    • (1976) The Southern Speech Communication Journal , vol.42 , Issue.35 , pp. 50
    • Leo Enos, R.1
  • 11
    • 84968188297 scopus 로고
    • Gorgias' Encomium to Helen and the Defense of Rhetoric
    • See John Poulakos, "Gorgias' Encomium to Helen and the Defense of Rhetoric," Rhetorica 1 (1983): 1-16
    • (1983) Rhetorica , vol.1 , pp. 1-16
    • Poulakos, J.1
  • 12
    • 61449090897 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gorgias' and Isocrates' Use of the Encomium
    • 51 1986
    • "Gorgias' and Isocrates' Use of the Encomium," Southern Speech Communication Journal 51 (1986): 300-307
    • Southern Speech Communication Journal , pp. 300-307
  • 13
    • 85187487467 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Also on the Encomium of Helen as an implied defense of rhetoric, even though rhetoric can take a license with truth, Wardy, cited in n. 5 above, 35-39.
    • Also on the Encomium of Helen as an implied defense of rhetoric, even though rhetoric can take a license with truth, see Wardy, cited in n. 5 above, 35-39
  • 14
    • 85187417212 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scott Consigny Gorgias, Sophist and Artist (Columbia, S.C.: University of South Carolina Press, 2001), lays out an approach he names anti-foundationalist and argues that Gorgias' account of logos is parodic in that it draws attention to the rhetoricity of every text (p. 30) neither confirming, nor denying truth but incorporating deception as something inevitable.
    • Scott Consigny Gorgias, Sophist and Artist (Columbia, S.C.: University of South Carolina Press, 2001), lays out an approach he names "anti- foundationalist" and argues that Gorgias' account of logos is "parodic" in that it draws attention to the "rhetoricity" of every text (p. 30) neither confirming, nor denying truth but incorporating deception as something inevitable
  • 15
    • 85187420255 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • All subsequent references to, quotations from, and translations of the Encomium of Helen are from D. M. MacDowell, Gorgias: Encomium of Helen (Bristol: Bristol Classical Press, 1982).
    • All subsequent references to, quotations from, and translations of the Encomium of Helen are from D. M. MacDowell, Gorgias: Encomium of Helen (Bristol: Bristol Classical Press, 1982)
  • 16
    • 85187471538 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • All references to Gorgias' other works are from Hermann Diels and Walter Kranz, Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker, 2 (Zurich: Weidmann, 1982), section 82.
    • All references to Gorgias' other works are from Hermann Diels and Walter Kranz, Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker, vol. 2 (Zurich: Weidmann, 1982), section 82
  • 17
    • 85187485878 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Edward Schiappa, The Beginnings of Rhetorical Theory in Classical Greece. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1999, has argued for a pre-disciplinary reading of the Encomium, i.e., a reading preceding Aristotle's division of rhetorical genres.
    • Edward Schiappa, The Beginnings of Rhetorical Theory in Classical Greece. (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1999, has argued for a "pre- disciplinary" reading of the Encomium, i.e., a reading preceding Aristotle's division of rhetorical genres
  • 18
    • 85187461102 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • G. B. Kerferd, The Sophistic Movement (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1981), argues that the result of Gorgias' treatment of logos is that its power on the soul is comparable to the power of drugs on the body.
    • G. B. Kerferd, The Sophistic Movement (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1981), argues that the result of Gorgias' treatment of logos is that its power on the soul is comparable to the power of drugs on the body
  • 19
    • 85187477576 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Michael Gagarin, Did the Sophists Aim to Persuade? Rhetorica 19 (2001): 275-91 (pp. 288-89). Kerferd, cited in n. 12 above, 80 contends that Gorgias distinguishes two kinds of persuasion, one good and one bad, but I do not this kind of argument anywhere in Gorgias' extant speeches or fragments.
    • Michael Gagarin, "Did the Sophists Aim to Persuade?" Rhetorica 19 (2001): 275-91 (pp. 288-89). Kerferd, cited in n. 12 above, 80 contends that Gorgias distinguishes two kinds of persuasion, one good and one bad, but I do not see this kind of argument anywhere in Gorgias' extant speeches or fragments
  • 20
    • 85187454984 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schiappa, cited in n. 11 above, 121; Kennedy, Art of Persuasion, cited in n. 6 above, 167-68.
    • Schiappa, cited in n. 11 above, 121; Kennedy, Art of Persuasion, cited in n. 6 above, 167-68
  • 21
    • 85187460207 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Guthrie, cited in n. 3 above, 193-94. For discussion of the problems connected with the interpretation and translation of On Not Being, Schiappa, cited in n. 11 above, 133-52.
    • Guthrie, cited in n. 3 above, 193-94. For discussion of the problems connected with the interpretation and translation of On Not Being, see Schiappa, cited in n. 11 above, 133-52
  • 22
    • 85187448479 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kerferd, cited in n. 12 above, 81
    • Kerferd, cited in n. 12 above, 81
  • 23
    • 84966071688 scopus 로고
    • The Sophists and Relativism
    • Richard Bett, "The Sophists and Relativism," Phronesis 34 (1989): 139-69 (pp. 150-53)
    • (1989) Phronesis , vol.34 , Issue.139 , pp. 150-153
    • Bett, R.1
  • 24
    • 85187419773 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schiappa, cited in n. 11 above, 122-23
    • Schiappa, cited in n. 11 above, 122-23
  • 25
    • 85187441501 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schiappa, cited in n. 11 above, 123
    • Schiappa, cited in n. 11 above, 123
  • 26
    • 85187488490 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Translation from Michael Gagarin and Paul Woodruff, eds. and trans., Early Greek Political Thought: From Homer to the Sophists (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), 203.
    • Translation from Michael Gagarin and Paul Woodruff, eds. and trans., Early Greek Political Thought: From Homer to the Sophists (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), 203
  • 27
    • 85187453821 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Trans. Gagarin/Woodruff, Early Greek Political Thought, 203.
    • Trans. Gagarin/Woodruff, Early Greek Political Thought, 203
  • 28
    • 85187458815 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Plato maybe deliberately misrepresenting Gorgias' views of logos in the Gorgias, when he has him say that the rhetorical art is to be able to persuade with speeches judges in the law courts, or statesmen in the Council, or the people in the Assembly or at any other meeting and afterwards agree with Socrates' definition that the art of rhetoric is the artisan of persuasion (Gorgias 452e-453a, It seems to me unlikely that the same person who, in a public situation (such as the oral performance of the Encomium of Helen, labels persuasion as evil (Encomium 14, would, in an equally public situation and presumably more than once-for Plato to cite it in his dialogue, define his art as the art of persuasion. It is quite possible that Plato invented the definition of rhetoric himself, just as he probably invented the word rhetoric. The word rhetorike does not appear in any of the fragments of the soph
    • Plato maybe deliberately misrepresenting Gorgias' views of logos in the Gorgias, when he has him say that the rhetorical art is "to be able to persuade with speeches judges in the law courts, or statesmen in the Council, or the people in the Assembly or at any other meeting" and afterwards agree with Socrates' definition that the "art of rhetoric is the artisan of persuasion" (Gorgias 452e-453a). It seems to me unlikely that the same person who, in a public situation (such as the oral performance of the Encomium of Helen), labels persuasion as "evil" (Encomium 14), would, in an equally public situation (and presumably more than once-for Plato to cite it in his dialogue), define his art as the art of persuasion. It is quite possible that Plato invented the definition of rhetoric himself, just as he probably invented the word "rhetoric." The word rhetorike does not appear in any of the fragments of the sophists; see Edward Schiappa, "Did Plato Coin Rhetorike?" American Journal of Philology 111 (1990): 457-70
  • 29
    • 85187485648 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • also Schiappa, Protagoras and Logos: A Study in Greek Philosophy and Rhetoric, 2nd ed. (Columbus: University of South Carolina Press, 2003), 39-63.
    • also Schiappa, Protagoras and Logos: A Study in Greek Philosophy and Rhetoric, 2nd ed. (Columbus: University of South Carolina Press, 2003), 39-63
  • 30
    • 85187430094 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Atheneaus' comment that, after reading the dialogue that bears his name, Gorgias is said to have exclaimed, How well Plato knows how to satirize! (Deipnosophistae 11.113.2 (Kaibel) = DK 82.A15a, trans. Sprague).
    • Cf. Atheneaus' comment that, after reading the dialogue that bears his name, Gorgias is said to have exclaimed, "How well Plato knows how to satirize!" (Deipnosophistae 11.113.2 (Kaibel) = DK 82.A15a, trans. Sprague)
  • 31
    • 85187449006 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Philostratus, Epistulae et dialexeis 73 = DK 82.A35, Diodorus Siculus 12.53.3 = DK 82.A4.
    • Cf. Philostratus, Epistulae et dialexeis 73 = DK 82.A35, Diodorus Siculus 12.53.3 = DK 82.A4
  • 32
    • 0041073778 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1.1404a, DK 82.A29
    • Rhetoric 1.1404a = DK 82.A29
    • Rhetoric
  • 33
    • 85187470818 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Segal, cited in n. 1 above, p. 127
    • Segal, cited in n. 1 above, p. 127
  • 34
    • 85187412552 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As Schiappa has demonstrated, certain individual phrases are clearly rhythmic, yet the speech fails to repeat an overall pattern that could be recognized as metered poetry (Schiappa, Beginnings of Rhetorical Theory, cited in n. 11 above, p. 111). He argues that both Gorgias and Thrasymachus draw upon poetic meters but do not depend on them; meter is a natural consequence rather than being an end in itself (p. 113).
    • As Schiappa has demonstrated, certain individual phrases are clearly rhythmic, yet the speech fails to repeat an overall pattern that could be recognized as metered poetry (Schiappa, Beginnings of Rhetorical Theory, cited in n. 11 above, p. 111). He argues that both Gorgias and Thrasymachus draw upon poetic meters but do not depend on them; "meter is a natural consequence rather than being an end in itself" (p. 113)
  • 35
    • 85187461766 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Suidas, Lexicon G. 388 = DK 82.A2, Diodorus Siculus 12.53.4 = DK 82.A4.
    • See Suidas, Lexicon G. 388 = DK 82.A2, Diodorus Siculus 12.53.4 = DK 82.A4
  • 36
    • 85187415785 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schiappa, cited in n. 11 above, 85-105, argues that Gorgias' style, although not poetic in the strict sense of the word, resembles poetry in that it is not everyday language and strikes the listener as strange (p. 94).
    • Schiappa, cited in n. 11 above, 85-105, argues that Gorgias' style, although not "poetic" in the strict sense of the word, "resembles" poetry in that it is not everyday language and strikes the listener as strange (p. 94)
  • 37
    • 85187433903 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kennedy cited in n. 6 above, pp. 64-66
    • Kennedy cited in n. 6 above, pp. 64-66
  • 40
    • 85187475870 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schiappa, cited in n. 11 above, 101, describes Gorgias as a prose rhapsode.
    • Schiappa, cited in n. 11 above, 101, describes Gorgias as a "prose rhapsode."
  • 41
    • 85187412099 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MacDowell, cited in n. 10 above, 16. John Poulakos, cited in n. 9 above, p. 3, argues that the word in the last sentence indicates that the composition could not have been intended as a model speech for students because it would undermine its own purpose.
    • MacDowell, cited in n. 10 above, 16. John Poulakos, cited in n. 9 above, p. 3, argues that the word in the last sentence indicates that the composition could not have been intended as a model speech for students because it would undermine its own purpose
  • 42
    • 85187448648 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schiappa, cited in n. 11 above, 131
    • Schiappa, cited in n. 11 above, 131
  • 45
    • 85187457111 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schiappa, Protagoras and Logos, cited in n. 22 above, pp. 163-64.
    • Schiappa, Protagoras and Logos, cited in n. 22 above, pp. 163-64
  • 46
    • 85187458110 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gagarin, Antiphon the Athenian, 38-63, argues that Antiphon referred to as the orator, Antiphon known as the sophist (who wrote Truth and Concord), and Antiphon the author of the Tetralogies are one and the same person.
    • Gagarin, Antiphon the Athenian, 38-63, argues that Antiphon referred to as "the orator," Antiphon known as "the sophist" (who wrote Truth and Concord), and Antiphon the author of the Tetralogies are one and the same person
  • 48
    • 85187482821 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schiappa, cited in n. 22 above, 164; Gagarin, Correct Argument in Sophistic Rhetoric, cited in n. 35 above, p. 10.
    • Schiappa, cited in n. 22 above, 164; Gagarin, "Correct Argument in Sophistic Rhetoric," cited in n. 35 above, p. 10
  • 49
    • 85187432767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DK 82.B7-8a, Isocrates, Panegyricus 1-3.
    • Cf. DK 82.B7-8a, Isocrates, Panegyricus 1-3
  • 50
    • 85187439128 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A shorter version of this paper was presented at the fourteenth biennial meeting of the ISHR in Madrid in July 2003. I am grateful to the audience, as well as to Rhetorica's referees, Rhetorica's editor, Harvey Yunis, and especially, to my advisors Professors Michael Gagarin and Jeffrey Walker, for their suggestions and invaluable help
    • A shorter version of this paper was presented at the fourteenth biennial meeting of the ISHR in Madrid in July 2003. I am grateful to the audience, as well as to Rhetorica's referees, Rhetorica's editor, Harvey Yunis, and especially, to my advisors Professors Michael Gagarin and Jeffrey Walker, for their suggestions and invaluable help


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.