-
2
-
-
85187416703
-
-
Segal, Psychology of the Logos, 102.
-
Segal, "Psychology of the Logos," 102
-
-
-
-
3
-
-
85187417010
-
-
Segal, Psychology of the Logos, 112.
-
Segal, "Psychology of the Logos," 112
-
-
-
-
4
-
-
85187426267
-
-
Segal, Psychology of the Logos, 127.
-
Segal, "Psychology of the Logos," 127
-
-
-
-
6
-
-
85187413929
-
-
On a similar note, W. K. C. Guthrie, The Sophists (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1971) 50, describes Gorgias' rhetoric as sophistic in every sense, where sophistic carries the same meaning of murky and shifty as it does in Plato's dialogues. Also on Gorgias' theory of logos in relation to deception and tragedy, Robert Wardy, The Birth of Rhetoric: Gorgias, Plato, and Their Successors (London: Routledge, 1996), 25-51.
-
On a similar note, W. K. C. Guthrie, The Sophists (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1971) 50, describes Gorgias' rhetoric as "sophistic in every sense," where "sophistic" carries the same meaning of murky and shifty as it does in Plato's dialogues. Also on Gorgias' theory of logos in relation to deception and tragedy, see Robert Wardy, The Birth of Rhetoric: Gorgias, Plato, and Their Successors (London: Routledge, 1996), 25-51
-
-
-
-
7
-
-
85187435548
-
-
Jacqueline de Romilly, The Great Sophists in Periclean Athens, trans. J. Lloyd (Oxford: Clarendon, 1992).
-
"Jacqueline de Romilly, The Great Sophists in Periclean Athens, trans. J. Lloyd (Oxford: Clarendon, 1992)
-
-
-
-
8
-
-
85187483869
-
-
So too George Kennedy, The Art of Persuasion in Greece (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1963), 61-68, and Classical Rhetoric and Its Christian and Secular Tradition from Ancient to Modern Times (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1999), 34-36, who concentrates on Gorgias' stylistic innovations in an effort to demonstrate their effectiveness.
-
So too George Kennedy, The Art of Persuasion in Greece (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1963), 61-68, and Classical Rhetoric and Its Christian and Secular Tradition from Ancient to Modern Times (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1999), 34-36, who concentrates on Gorgias' stylistic innovations in an effort to demonstrate their effectiveness
-
-
-
-
9
-
-
85187485249
-
The Epistemology of Gorgias' Rhetoric: A Re-Examination
-
Richard Leo Enos, "The Epistemology of Gorgias' Rhetoric: A Re-Examination," The Southern Speech Communication Journal 42 (1976): 35-51 (p. 50)
-
(1976)
The Southern Speech Communication Journal
, vol.42
, Issue.35
, pp. 50
-
-
Leo Enos, R.1
-
11
-
-
84968188297
-
Gorgias' Encomium to Helen and the Defense of Rhetoric
-
See John Poulakos, "Gorgias' Encomium to Helen and the Defense of Rhetoric," Rhetorica 1 (1983): 1-16
-
(1983)
Rhetorica
, vol.1
, pp. 1-16
-
-
Poulakos, J.1
-
12
-
-
61449090897
-
Gorgias' and Isocrates' Use of the Encomium
-
51 1986
-
"Gorgias' and Isocrates' Use of the Encomium," Southern Speech Communication Journal 51 (1986): 300-307
-
Southern Speech Communication Journal
, pp. 300-307
-
-
-
13
-
-
85187487467
-
-
Also on the Encomium of Helen as an implied defense of rhetoric, even though rhetoric can take a license with truth, Wardy, cited in n. 5 above, 35-39.
-
Also on the Encomium of Helen as an implied defense of rhetoric, even though rhetoric can take a license with truth, see Wardy, cited in n. 5 above, 35-39
-
-
-
-
14
-
-
85187417212
-
-
Scott Consigny Gorgias, Sophist and Artist (Columbia, S.C.: University of South Carolina Press, 2001), lays out an approach he names anti-foundationalist and argues that Gorgias' account of logos is parodic in that it draws attention to the rhetoricity of every text (p. 30) neither confirming, nor denying truth but incorporating deception as something inevitable.
-
Scott Consigny Gorgias, Sophist and Artist (Columbia, S.C.: University of South Carolina Press, 2001), lays out an approach he names "anti- foundationalist" and argues that Gorgias' account of logos is "parodic" in that it draws attention to the "rhetoricity" of every text (p. 30) neither confirming, nor denying truth but incorporating deception as something inevitable
-
-
-
-
15
-
-
85187420255
-
-
All subsequent references to, quotations from, and translations of the Encomium of Helen are from D. M. MacDowell, Gorgias: Encomium of Helen (Bristol: Bristol Classical Press, 1982).
-
All subsequent references to, quotations from, and translations of the Encomium of Helen are from D. M. MacDowell, Gorgias: Encomium of Helen (Bristol: Bristol Classical Press, 1982)
-
-
-
-
16
-
-
85187471538
-
-
All references to Gorgias' other works are from Hermann Diels and Walter Kranz, Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker, 2 (Zurich: Weidmann, 1982), section 82.
-
All references to Gorgias' other works are from Hermann Diels and Walter Kranz, Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker, vol. 2 (Zurich: Weidmann, 1982), section 82
-
-
-
-
17
-
-
85187485878
-
-
Edward Schiappa, The Beginnings of Rhetorical Theory in Classical Greece. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1999, has argued for a pre-disciplinary reading of the Encomium, i.e., a reading preceding Aristotle's division of rhetorical genres.
-
Edward Schiappa, The Beginnings of Rhetorical Theory in Classical Greece. (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1999, has argued for a "pre- disciplinary" reading of the Encomium, i.e., a reading preceding Aristotle's division of rhetorical genres
-
-
-
-
18
-
-
85187461102
-
-
G. B. Kerferd, The Sophistic Movement (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1981), argues that the result of Gorgias' treatment of logos is that its power on the soul is comparable to the power of drugs on the body.
-
G. B. Kerferd, The Sophistic Movement (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1981), argues that the result of Gorgias' treatment of logos is that its power on the soul is comparable to the power of drugs on the body
-
-
-
-
19
-
-
85187477576
-
-
Michael Gagarin, Did the Sophists Aim to Persuade? Rhetorica 19 (2001): 275-91 (pp. 288-89). Kerferd, cited in n. 12 above, 80 contends that Gorgias distinguishes two kinds of persuasion, one good and one bad, but I do not this kind of argument anywhere in Gorgias' extant speeches or fragments.
-
Michael Gagarin, "Did the Sophists Aim to Persuade?" Rhetorica 19 (2001): 275-91 (pp. 288-89). Kerferd, cited in n. 12 above, 80 contends that Gorgias distinguishes two kinds of persuasion, one good and one bad, but I do not see this kind of argument anywhere in Gorgias' extant speeches or fragments
-
-
-
-
20
-
-
85187454984
-
-
Schiappa, cited in n. 11 above, 121; Kennedy, Art of Persuasion, cited in n. 6 above, 167-68.
-
Schiappa, cited in n. 11 above, 121; Kennedy, Art of Persuasion, cited in n. 6 above, 167-68
-
-
-
-
21
-
-
85187460207
-
-
Guthrie, cited in n. 3 above, 193-94. For discussion of the problems connected with the interpretation and translation of On Not Being, Schiappa, cited in n. 11 above, 133-52.
-
Guthrie, cited in n. 3 above, 193-94. For discussion of the problems connected with the interpretation and translation of On Not Being, see Schiappa, cited in n. 11 above, 133-52
-
-
-
-
22
-
-
85187448479
-
-
Kerferd, cited in n. 12 above, 81
-
Kerferd, cited in n. 12 above, 81
-
-
-
-
23
-
-
84966071688
-
The Sophists and Relativism
-
Richard Bett, "The Sophists and Relativism," Phronesis 34 (1989): 139-69 (pp. 150-53)
-
(1989)
Phronesis
, vol.34
, Issue.139
, pp. 150-153
-
-
Bett, R.1
-
24
-
-
85187419773
-
-
Schiappa, cited in n. 11 above, 122-23
-
Schiappa, cited in n. 11 above, 122-23
-
-
-
-
25
-
-
85187441501
-
-
Schiappa, cited in n. 11 above, 123
-
Schiappa, cited in n. 11 above, 123
-
-
-
-
26
-
-
85187488490
-
-
Translation from Michael Gagarin and Paul Woodruff, eds. and trans., Early Greek Political Thought: From Homer to the Sophists (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), 203.
-
Translation from Michael Gagarin and Paul Woodruff, eds. and trans., Early Greek Political Thought: From Homer to the Sophists (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), 203
-
-
-
-
27
-
-
85187453821
-
-
Trans. Gagarin/Woodruff, Early Greek Political Thought, 203.
-
Trans. Gagarin/Woodruff, Early Greek Political Thought, 203
-
-
-
-
28
-
-
85187458815
-
-
Plato maybe deliberately misrepresenting Gorgias' views of logos in the Gorgias, when he has him say that the rhetorical art is to be able to persuade with speeches judges in the law courts, or statesmen in the Council, or the people in the Assembly or at any other meeting and afterwards agree with Socrates' definition that the art of rhetoric is the artisan of persuasion (Gorgias 452e-453a, It seems to me unlikely that the same person who, in a public situation (such as the oral performance of the Encomium of Helen, labels persuasion as evil (Encomium 14, would, in an equally public situation and presumably more than once-for Plato to cite it in his dialogue, define his art as the art of persuasion. It is quite possible that Plato invented the definition of rhetoric himself, just as he probably invented the word rhetoric. The word rhetorike does not appear in any of the fragments of the soph
-
Plato maybe deliberately misrepresenting Gorgias' views of logos in the Gorgias, when he has him say that the rhetorical art is "to be able to persuade with speeches judges in the law courts, or statesmen in the Council, or the people in the Assembly or at any other meeting" and afterwards agree with Socrates' definition that the "art of rhetoric is the artisan of persuasion" (Gorgias 452e-453a). It seems to me unlikely that the same person who, in a public situation (such as the oral performance of the Encomium of Helen), labels persuasion as "evil" (Encomium 14), would, in an equally public situation (and presumably more than once-for Plato to cite it in his dialogue), define his art as the art of persuasion. It is quite possible that Plato invented the definition of rhetoric himself, just as he probably invented the word "rhetoric." The word rhetorike does not appear in any of the fragments of the sophists; see Edward Schiappa, "Did Plato Coin Rhetorike?" American Journal of Philology 111 (1990): 457-70
-
-
-
-
29
-
-
85187485648
-
-
also Schiappa, Protagoras and Logos: A Study in Greek Philosophy and Rhetoric, 2nd ed. (Columbus: University of South Carolina Press, 2003), 39-63.
-
also Schiappa, Protagoras and Logos: A Study in Greek Philosophy and Rhetoric, 2nd ed. (Columbus: University of South Carolina Press, 2003), 39-63
-
-
-
-
30
-
-
85187430094
-
-
Atheneaus' comment that, after reading the dialogue that bears his name, Gorgias is said to have exclaimed, How well Plato knows how to satirize! (Deipnosophistae 11.113.2 (Kaibel) = DK 82.A15a, trans. Sprague).
-
Cf. Atheneaus' comment that, after reading the dialogue that bears his name, Gorgias is said to have exclaimed, "How well Plato knows how to satirize!" (Deipnosophistae 11.113.2 (Kaibel) = DK 82.A15a, trans. Sprague)
-
-
-
-
31
-
-
85187449006
-
-
Philostratus, Epistulae et dialexeis 73 = DK 82.A35, Diodorus Siculus 12.53.3 = DK 82.A4.
-
Cf. Philostratus, Epistulae et dialexeis 73 = DK 82.A35, Diodorus Siculus 12.53.3 = DK 82.A4
-
-
-
-
32
-
-
0041073778
-
-
1.1404a, DK 82.A29
-
Rhetoric 1.1404a = DK 82.A29
-
Rhetoric
-
-
-
33
-
-
85187470818
-
-
Segal, cited in n. 1 above, p. 127
-
Segal, cited in n. 1 above, p. 127
-
-
-
-
34
-
-
85187412552
-
-
As Schiappa has demonstrated, certain individual phrases are clearly rhythmic, yet the speech fails to repeat an overall pattern that could be recognized as metered poetry (Schiappa, Beginnings of Rhetorical Theory, cited in n. 11 above, p. 111). He argues that both Gorgias and Thrasymachus draw upon poetic meters but do not depend on them; meter is a natural consequence rather than being an end in itself (p. 113).
-
As Schiappa has demonstrated, certain individual phrases are clearly rhythmic, yet the speech fails to repeat an overall pattern that could be recognized as metered poetry (Schiappa, Beginnings of Rhetorical Theory, cited in n. 11 above, p. 111). He argues that both Gorgias and Thrasymachus draw upon poetic meters but do not depend on them; "meter is a natural consequence rather than being an end in itself" (p. 113)
-
-
-
-
35
-
-
85187461766
-
-
Suidas, Lexicon G. 388 = DK 82.A2, Diodorus Siculus 12.53.4 = DK 82.A4.
-
See Suidas, Lexicon G. 388 = DK 82.A2, Diodorus Siculus 12.53.4 = DK 82.A4
-
-
-
-
36
-
-
85187415785
-
-
Schiappa, cited in n. 11 above, 85-105, argues that Gorgias' style, although not poetic in the strict sense of the word, resembles poetry in that it is not everyday language and strikes the listener as strange (p. 94).
-
Schiappa, cited in n. 11 above, 85-105, argues that Gorgias' style, although not "poetic" in the strict sense of the word, "resembles" poetry in that it is not everyday language and strikes the listener as strange (p. 94)
-
-
-
-
37
-
-
85187433903
-
-
Kennedy cited in n. 6 above, pp. 64-66
-
Kennedy cited in n. 6 above, pp. 64-66
-
-
-
-
40
-
-
85187475870
-
-
Schiappa, cited in n. 11 above, 101, describes Gorgias as a prose rhapsode.
-
Schiappa, cited in n. 11 above, 101, describes Gorgias as a "prose rhapsode."
-
-
-
-
41
-
-
85187412099
-
-
MacDowell, cited in n. 10 above, 16. John Poulakos, cited in n. 9 above, p. 3, argues that the word in the last sentence indicates that the composition could not have been intended as a model speech for students because it would undermine its own purpose.
-
MacDowell, cited in n. 10 above, 16. John Poulakos, cited in n. 9 above, p. 3, argues that the word in the last sentence indicates that the composition could not have been intended as a model speech for students because it would undermine its own purpose
-
-
-
-
42
-
-
85187448648
-
-
Schiappa, cited in n. 11 above, 131
-
Schiappa, cited in n. 11 above, 131
-
-
-
-
43
-
-
85187429794
-
Correct Argument in Sophistic Rhetoric
-
Michael Gagarin, "Correct Argument in Sophistic Rhetoric" (delivered at the fifteenth biennial meeting of the ISHR in Los Angeles in July 2005), and Antiphon the Athenian: Oratory, Law, and Justice in the Age of the Sophists (Austin: University of Texas Press, 2002), 26-27
-
(2002)
(delivered at the fifteenth biennial meeting of the ISHR in Los Angeles in July 2005), and Antiphon the Athenian: Oratory, Law, and Justice in the Age of the Sophists (Austin: University of Texas Press
, pp. 26-27
-
-
Gagarin, M.1
-
45
-
-
85187457111
-
-
Schiappa, Protagoras and Logos, cited in n. 22 above, pp. 163-64.
-
Schiappa, Protagoras and Logos, cited in n. 22 above, pp. 163-64
-
-
-
-
46
-
-
85187458110
-
-
Gagarin, Antiphon the Athenian, 38-63, argues that Antiphon referred to as the orator, Antiphon known as the sophist (who wrote Truth and Concord), and Antiphon the author of the Tetralogies are one and the same person.
-
Gagarin, Antiphon the Athenian, 38-63, argues that Antiphon referred to as "the orator," Antiphon known as "the sophist" (who wrote Truth and Concord), and Antiphon the author of the Tetralogies are one and the same person
-
-
-
-
48
-
-
85187482821
-
-
Schiappa, cited in n. 22 above, 164; Gagarin, Correct Argument in Sophistic Rhetoric, cited in n. 35 above, p. 10.
-
Schiappa, cited in n. 22 above, 164; Gagarin, "Correct Argument in Sophistic Rhetoric," cited in n. 35 above, p. 10
-
-
-
-
49
-
-
85187432767
-
-
DK 82.B7-8a, Isocrates, Panegyricus 1-3.
-
Cf. DK 82.B7-8a, Isocrates, Panegyricus 1-3
-
-
-
-
50
-
-
85187439128
-
-
A shorter version of this paper was presented at the fourteenth biennial meeting of the ISHR in Madrid in July 2003. I am grateful to the audience, as well as to Rhetorica's referees, Rhetorica's editor, Harvey Yunis, and especially, to my advisors Professors Michael Gagarin and Jeffrey Walker, for their suggestions and invaluable help
-
A shorter version of this paper was presented at the fourteenth biennial meeting of the ISHR in Madrid in July 2003. I am grateful to the audience, as well as to Rhetorica's referees, Rhetorica's editor, Harvey Yunis, and especially, to my advisors Professors Michael Gagarin and Jeffrey Walker, for their suggestions and invaluable help
-
-
-
|