-
1
-
-
0003689801
-
-
Cambridge, Mass, Harvard University Press
-
Robert B. Brandom, Making It Explicit (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1994), p. 74
-
(1994)
Making It Explicit
, pp. 74
-
-
Brandom, R.B.1
-
2
-
-
0003665678
-
-
Oxford: Basil Blackwell
-
See, for example, Saul Kripke, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1982) and the literature prompted by it. The problems should not, though, lead us to infer that we cannot know how someone is representing things to be when they speak or write (Should we stop asking people the way to coffee shops?) or that usage is not central (Should we tell dictionary makers to change their ways?)
-
(1982)
Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language
-
-
Kripke, S.1
-
3
-
-
33751168902
-
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
For the connection between the correspondence theory and representation, see Marian David, Correspondence and Disquotation (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 1994, pp. 31-51
-
(1994)
Correspondence and Disquotation
, pp. 31-51
-
-
David, M.1
-
4
-
-
0003563462
-
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
Huw Price, Time's Arrow & Archimedes' Point (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996), p. 4. He argues that the Archimedean view of time, the view from nowhen, as he describes it, delivers the block view
-
(1996)
Time's Arrow & Archimedes' Point
, pp. 4
-
-
Price, H.1
-
7
-
-
33746128227
-
Noneism or Allism?
-
A view we might call linguistic idealism, as Mark Sainsbury pointed out to me. Traditional idealists allow that language represents without creating, though what is represented is the nature of actual and possible patterns in ideas. This, however, is plausible only as a view about language in their mouths. As David Lewis, 'Noneism or Allism?', Mind, 99 (1990), pp. 23-31, argues, if idealism is true, 'There is a table in at least one unoccupied room' is true in Berkeley or Mill's mouth, but false in Locke's
-
(1990)
Mind
, vol.99
, pp. 23-31
-
-
Lewis, D.1
-
8
-
-
33748137633
-
On Natural Properties in Metaphysics
-
See, e.g., Barry Taylor, 'On Natural Properties in Metaphysics', Mind, 102 (1993), pp. 81-100
-
(1993)
Mind
, vol.102
, pp. 81-100
-
-
Taylor, B.1
-
9
-
-
79955354317
-
-
esp. §IV. However, late in the paper, Taylor writes as if he were only insisting that our classifications always concern, to one extent or another, how things relate to us, as if he were simply denying the possibility of the Archimedean point (see the reference to realism 'as celebrated in Sydney' on p. 99), and that is a separate issue
-
As Celebrated in Sydney
, pp. 99
-
-
-
10
-
-
79955170848
-
-
Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 2nd ed
-
Michael Devitt, Realism and Truth (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 2nd ed. 1991), p. 238
-
(1991)
Realism and Truth
, pp. 238
-
-
Devitt, M.1
-
12
-
-
0011173730
-
Representation and Interpretation
-
And desire, e.g, K. A. Mohyeldin Said et al, eds Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
And desire, see, e.g., Donald Davidson, 'Representation and Interpretation', in Modelling the Mind, K. A. Mohyeldin Said et al., eds (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990), p. 16
-
(1990)
Modelling the Mind
, pp. 16
-
-
Davidson, D.1
-
13
-
-
0003434441
-
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
Christopher Peacocke, Sense and Content (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1983)
-
(1983)
Sense and Content
-
-
Peacocke, C.1
-
14
-
-
84924003277
-
Psychologism and Behaviorism
-
and Ned Block, 'Psychologism and Behaviorism', Philosophical Review, 90 (1981), pp. 5-43
-
(1981)
Philosophical Review
, vol.90
, pp. 5-43
-
-
Block, N.1
-
15
-
-
0001823030
-
Eliminative Materialism and the Propositional Attitudes
-
Paul M. Churchland, 'Eliminative Materialism and the Propositional Attitudes', Journal of Philosophy, 78 (1981), pp. 67-90
-
(1981)
Journal of Philosophy
, vol.78
, pp. 67-90
-
-
Churchland, P.M.1
-
16
-
-
0001184171
-
How to Define Theoretical Terms
-
David Lewis, 'How to Define Theoretical Terms', The Journal of Philosophy, 67 (1970), pp. 427-46
-
(1970)
The Journal of Philosophy
, vol.67
, pp. 427-446
-
-
Lewis, D.1
|