메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 22, Issue , 2002, Pages 83-139

Aristotle's definition of soul and the programme of the de anima

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 60949473110     PISSN: 02657651     EISSN: None     Source Type: Book Series    
DOI: None     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (128)

References (18)
  • 1
    • 80054661226 scopus 로고
    • (Chicago)
    • So Deborah Modrak: 'According to Aristotle, ancient dualism took several forms: one form was materialistic in that the separate psychical substance was identified with a material element; the other was dualist in the modern sense, i.e., the psychical substance was incorporeal. Aristotle is sharply critical of all two-substance views as well as materialist monism' (Aristotle: The Power of Perception (Chicago, 1987), 83 n. 1).
    • (1987) The Power of Perception , Issue.1 , pp. 83
    • Aristotle1
  • 2
    • 61149161310 scopus 로고
    • (Cambridge)
    • Against R. Wardy, The Chain of Change (Cambridge, 1990), 222 n.: 'But of course if in an un-Aristotelian spirit one distinguishes between soul and ensouled body, then it no longer makes any sense to say that the soul undergoes alteration. So if Aristotle does allow himself to say this, it must be because he is characteristically thinking in terms of an animate in which the individual collectively are the sensitive part of the soul.' It is not un-Aristotelian even in the De anima to distinguish between the soul and the ensouled body, and Physics 7 makes it perfectly clear that the sensitive soul, which is not a body or a sensible thing, undergoes alteration. I do not know why Wardy thinks that 'of course' such a soul could not undergo alteration; Plato certainly thought the soul could be moved by the body, and Physics 7, while criticizing the Timaeus' theory of soul on some points (notably in denying that is a circular motion in the intellectual soul - more on this below), remains close to it on others.
    • (1990) The Chain of Change , pp. 222
    • Wardy, R.1
  • 3
    • 0040693023 scopus 로고
    • Aristotle and the Mind-Body Problem
    • pp. 86-7
    • As far as I know, the scholars I have mentioned have never discussed the texts on the soul's being moved. The only recent scholar I know who shows any awareness of these texts is Robert Heinaman, in 'Aristotle and the Mind-Body Problem', Phronesis, 37 (1990), 83-102, who briefly discusses some of the texts, pp. 86-7, and rightly concludes that Aristotle has changed his mind between these texts and the De anima.
    • (1990) Phronesis , vol.37 , pp. 83-102
    • Heinaman, R.1
  • 4
    • 79955324480 scopus 로고
    • Dialectic, Motion, and Perception: De Anima, Book I
    • Oxford
    • This point is rightly stressed by Charlotte Witt in her article 'Dialectic, Motion, and Perception: De Anima, Book I', in M. Nussbaum and A. Rorty (eds.), Essays on Aristotle's De Anima (Oxford, 1992), 169-83;
    • (1992) Essays on Aristotle's De Anima , pp. 169-183
    • Nussbaum, M.1    Rorty, A.2
  • 5
    • 60949528872 scopus 로고
    • Aristotle's Motionless Soul
    • it is also discussed by M. Tweedale, 'Aristotle's Motionless Soul', Dialogue, 29 (1990), 123-32, by Heinaman, 'Aristotle and the Mind-Body Problem', and otherwise by almost nobody. Many scholars have difficulty in recognizing'this basic fact about De anima 1, and insist on reading as 'naturalistic' criticisms of soul - body dualism w hat are in fact 'anti-naturalistic' criticisms of the thesis that the soul is moved.
    • (1990) Dialogue , vol.29 , pp. 123-32
    • Tweedale, M.1
  • 6
    • 85018817924 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Metaphysics Λ 8
    • M. Frede and D. Charles (eds.) (Oxford) at 253
    • (against G. E. R. Lloyd, 'Metaphysics Λ 8', in M. Frede and D. Charles (eds.), Aristotle's Metaphysics Lambda (Oxford, 2000), 245-73 at 253).
    • (2000) Aristotle's Metaphysics Lambda , pp. 245-73
    • Lloyd, G.E.R.1
  • 7
    • 14844324016 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Aristotle's Conception of the Soul
    • at 103-4
    • M. Frede, 'On Aristotle's Conception of the Soul', in Nussbaum and Rorty, Essays on Aristotle's Deanima, 93-107 at 103-4. Frede speaks of Aristotle's 'rejection of the assumption that the soul is an entity distinct from the body it animates and the proper subject of a class of predicates we ascribe to living things, namely the mental predicates' (p. 103).
    • Nussbaum and Rorty, Essays on Aristotle's Deanima , pp. 93-107
    • Frede, M.1
  • 12
    • 80054636562 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am not sure how many people agree or disagree with Everson on the semantic issue, or indeed how many people are aware of the problem. Nussbaum is aware of it, and apparently agnostic: 'psuchè is said to be the entelecheia of sôma phusikon organikon, a natural tool-like body, or body equipped with useful tool-like parts' (in her 'The Text of Aristotle's De Anima', in Nussbaum and Rorty, Essays on Aristotle's De Anima, 1-6 at 6).
    • I am not sure how many people agree or disagree with Everson on the semantic issue, or indeed how many people are aware of the problem. Nussbaum is aware of it, and apparently agnostic: 'psuchè is said to be the entelecheia of sôma phusikon organikon, a natural tool-like body, or body equipped with useful tool-like parts' (in her 'The Text of Aristotle's De Anima', in Nussbaum and Rorty, Essays on Aristotle's De Anima, 1-6 at 6).
  • 14
    • 85007952791 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is not totally obvious from this text whether he is thinking about the whole body of an animal or plant, or the parts of its body, or both, but nothing in the context suggests that he is thinking about the parts. In any case, we know, from the other texts we have seen, that the whole body is an and even if the present text is talking about the parts and saying that they are of the soul, it will still imply that the whole too is an of the soul. The point that Everson can be right about the meaning of even though the in the definition of soul is the whole animal body, since the whole body is an of soul, has been made quite rightly by Jonathan Barnes in his review of Everson, Classical Review, NS 49 (1999), 120-2.
    • (1999) Classical Review, NS , vol.49 , pp. 120-122
  • 16
    • 61249391193 scopus 로고
    • (Spring)
    • b18-35, marked by Jaeger as a later addition), on his own view not all activities are See my discussion in 'The Origins of Aristotle's Concept of and Ancient Philosophy, 14 (Spring 1994), 73-114.
    • (1994) The Origins of Aristotle's Concept of and Ancient Philosophy , vol.14 , pp. 73-114
  • 17
    • 61449376388 scopus 로고
    • The Order of Aristotle's Psychological Writings
    • Irving Block ('The Order of Aristotle's Psychological Writings', American Journal of Philology, 82 (1961), 50-77) thinks this makes the Pana naturalia texts likely to be later (because, Block thinks, more philosophically satisfactory) than the De anima; I think it is more likely that the De anima texts are later, and that from the point of view of the De anima the Parva naturalia account remains too close to Plato.
    • (1961) American Journal of Philology , vol.82 , pp. 50-77
    • Block, I.1
  • 18
    • 80054675502 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Collecting the Letters
    • Nov.
    • This is how Plato describes the activity of in the Theaetetus, Statesman, and Philebus; the texts are gathered and discussed in my 'Collecting the Letters', Phronesis, 43/4 (Nov. 1998), 291-305.
    • (1998) Phronesis , vol.43 , Issue.4 , pp. 291-305


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.