메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 21, Issue 4, 2008, Pages 440-453

Freedom of occupational choice

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 60949171201     PISSN: 00340006     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/j.1467-9329.2008.00412.x     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (19)

References (13)
  • 1
    • 0040609766 scopus 로고
    • Universal Grants versus Socialism: Reply to Six Critics
    • at pp. 727 and 757 n. 12
    • See, for example, Robert van der Veen and Philippe Van Parijs, 'Universal Grants versus Socialism: Reply to Six Critics', Theory and Society, 15 (1986): 723-57, at pp. 727 and 757 n. 12
    • (1986) Theory and Society , vol.15 , pp. 723-57
    • Veen Der R.Van1    Van Parijs, P.2
  • 2
    • 79955275495 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Notes on the Universal Grant Proposal
    • Cohen offers a critique of such a freedom-based defence of an unconditional basic income in G. A. Cohen, 'Notes on the Universal Grant Proposal', Basic Income Studies, 1 (2006): 1-3
    • (2006) Basic Income Studies , vol.1 , pp. 1-3
    • Cohen, G.A.1
  • 3
    • 84935413249 scopus 로고
    • On the Currency of Egalitarian Justice
    • at p. 912
    • It is worth recalling that, in a different context, Cohen endorses an 'offensive tastes' objection to welfare egalitarianism, which he characterizes as follows: The offensive tastes criticism of welfarism is that the pleasure a person takes in discriminating against other people or in subjecting others to a lesser liberty should not count equally with other satisfactions in the calculus of justice. From the point of view of justice, such pleasures deserve condemnation, and the corresponding preferences have no claim to be satisfied, even if they would have to be satisfied for welfare equality to prevail. (G. A. Cohen, 'On the Currency of Egalitarian Justice', Ethics, 99 (1989): 906-44, at p. 912.) Note that Cohen draws no distinction between those who can and those who cannot help but have their offensive tastes. Presumably he thinks such preferences have no claim to be satisfied even if they are incorrigible
    • (1989) Ethics , vol.99 , pp. 906-944
    • Cohen, G.A.1
  • 4
    • 33745813462 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In his reply to an earlier version of this paper, Cohen advanced the view that it would be unjust to force an inegalitarian into a different occupation because it is not legitimate to impose on people ideas of justice with which they can reasonably disagree. . . . In other words, one cannot 'suppose that all the urgency and dignity of justice applies to one's own political interpretation of justice' (Williams, In the Beginning was the Deed, p. 125), even if one thinks it correct. So one can't coerce the disbeliever in equality
    • The Beginning Was the Deed , pp. 125
    • Williams1
  • 5
    • 79955168990 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reading: Reply to Mike Otsuka
    • ('Reading: Reply to Mike Otsuka', manuscript, pp. 13-14)
    • Manuscript , pp. 13-14
  • 6
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • rev. ed., (Cambridge, Mass, Harvard University Press)
    • John Rawls, A Theory of Justice, rev. ed. (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1999), p. 53
    • (1999) A Theory of Justice , pp. 53
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 8
    • 84926117416 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Prerogatives to Depart from Equality
    • Anthony O'Hear, ed., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • See also Michael Otsuka, 'Prerogatives to Depart from Equality', in Anthony O'Hear, ed., Political Philosophy, Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 58 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), pp. 95-111
    • (2006) Political Philosophy, Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement , vol.58 , pp. 95-111
    • Otsuka, M.1
  • 9
    • 84921979312 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press, ch. 1, sec. II
    • See Michael Otsuka, Libertarianism without Inequality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003), ch. 1, sec. II
    • (2003) Libertarianism Without Inequality
    • Otsuka, M.1
  • 12
    • 0039757888 scopus 로고
    • Actions, Intentions, and Consequences: The Doctrine of Doing and Allowing
    • Warren Quinn, 'Actions, Intentions, and Consequences: The Doctrine of Doing and Allowing', Philosophical Review, 98 (1989): 287-312, at pp. 308-10
    • (1989) Philosophical Review , vol.98 , Issue.287-312 , pp. 308-310
    • Quinn, W.1
  • 13
    • 84925898311 scopus 로고
    • Nozick on Rights, Liberty, and Property
    • Cf. Scanlon: 'It may be true, as Nozick claims, that there is a continuum of interferences extending from taxation to forced labor, each foreclosing a few more options than the preceding. But the fact that there is such a continuum is no reason why we must be indifferent between any two points along it.' (Thomas Scanlon, 'Nozick on Rights, Liberty, and Property', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 6 (1976): 3-25, at pp. 7-8.)
    • (1976) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.6 , Issue.3-25 , pp. 7-8
    • Scanlon, T.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.