메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 119, Issue 1, 2008, Pages 9-30

Vindicating the normativity of rationality

(1)  Southwood, Nicholas a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 58749088936     PISSN: 00141704     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1086/592586     Document Type: Conference Paper
Times cited : (53)

References (67)
  • 1
    • 58749085857 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is what Niko Kolodny calls objective rationality Why Be Rational? Mind 114 [2005, 509-63, 510
    • This is what Niko Kolodny calls "objective rationality" ("Why Be Rational?" Mind 114 [2005]: 509-63, 510).
  • 2
    • 36749009731 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Normative Requirements
    • See
    • See John Broome, "Normative Requirements," Ratio 12 (1999): 398-412,
    • (1999) Ratio , vol.12 , pp. 398-412
    • Broome, J.1
  • 3
    • 58749116762 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Reasons, in Reason and Value: Themes from the Moral Philosophy of Joseph Raz, ed. Jay Wallace, Michael Smith, Samuel Schefiler, and Philip Pettit (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004), 28-55;
    • and "Reasons," in Reason and Value: Themes from the Moral Philosophy of Joseph Raz, ed. Jay Wallace, Michael Smith, Samuel Schefiler, and Philip Pettit (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004), 28-55;
  • 4
    • 58749103972 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolodny, Why Be Rational?; T. M. Scanlon, Structural Irrationality, in Common Minds: Themes from the Philosophy of Philip Pettit, ed. Geoffrey Brennan, Robert E. Goodin, Frank Jackson, and Michael Smith (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007), 84-103.
    • Kolodny, "Why Be Rational?"; T. M. Scanlon, "Structural Irrationality," in Common Minds: Themes from the Philosophy of Philip Pettit, ed. Geoffrey Brennan, Robert E. Goodin, Frank Jackson, and Michael Smith (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007), 84-103.
  • 5
    • 58749096299 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To say that rational requirements are requirements of internal coherence is not necessarily to say that they are merely requirements for internal coherence. The latter implies a certain view about the logical form of rational requirements on which I intend to remain neutral here. See n. 5 below.
    • To say that rational requirements are requirements of internal coherence is not necessarily to say that they are merely requirements for internal coherence. The latter implies a certain view about the logical form of rational requirements on which I intend to remain neutral here. See n. 5 below.
  • 6
    • 58749089422 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Candidates include (i) the requirement not to believe that p if you believe that not-p (belief consistency), (ii) the requirement to believe that q if you believe that p and that if p then q (belief closure), (iii) the requirement to intend to Y if you intend to X and believe that your Xing requires that you Y (instrumental rationality), (iv) the requirement not to intend to X if you intend not to X (intention coherence), and (v) the requirement to intend to X if you believe you ought to X (enkrasia).
    • Candidates include (i) the requirement not to believe that p if you believe that not-p (belief consistency), (ii) the requirement to believe that q if you believe that p and that if p then q (belief closure), (iii) the requirement to intend to Y if you intend to X and believe that your Xing requires that you Y (instrumental rationality), (iv) the requirement not to intend to X if you intend not to X (intention coherence), and (v) the requirement to intend to X if you believe you ought to X (enkrasia).
  • 7
    • 58749102718 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One important issue of formulation that has recently received a lot of attention concerns how to understand the logical form, of rational requirements. As Broome has pointed out, there are two importantly different ways that rational requirements might be formulated. Take what Broome calls enkrasia: the requirement to intend to X if you believe you ought to X. According to what Broome calls the narrow scope interpretation of enkrasia, the requirement is conditional in the sense of requiring one to intend to X conditional on believing that you ought to X. In other words, it is to be interpreted as follows: if you believe that you ought to X, then you are rationally required to intend to X. By contrast, according to what Broome calls the wide scope interpretation, the requirement is a conditional, since it ranges over the whole conditional proposition. So, the correct interpretation of enkrasia is this: you are rationally required if you believe you o
    • One important issue of formulation that has recently received a lot of attention concerns how to understand the logical form, of rational requirements. As Broome has pointed out, there are two importantly different ways that rational requirements might be formulated. Take what Broome calls "enkrasia": the requirement to intend to X if you believe you ought to X. According to what Broome calls the "narrow scope" interpretation of enkrasia, the requirement is conditional in the sense of requiring one to intend to X conditional on believing that you ought to X. In other words, it is to be interpreted as follows: if you believe that you ought to X, then you are rationally required to intend to X. By contrast, according to what Broome calls the "wide scope" interpretation, the requirement is a conditional, since it ranges over the whole conditional proposition. So, the correct interpretation of enkrasia is this: you are rationally required (if you believe you ought to X, to intend to X). I shall remain neutral here about whether rational requirements have narrow or wide scope.
  • 8
    • 58749090876 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This issue has also recendy begun to receive a fair bit of critical attention. See John Broome, Does Rationality Give Us Reasons? Philosophical Issues 15 2005, 321-37
    • This issue has also recendy begun to receive a fair bit of critical attention. See John Broome, "Does Rationality Give Us Reasons?" Philosophical Issues 15 (2005): 321-37,
  • 9
    • 62449299401 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Is Rationality Normative? Disputatio 23 (2007) : 161-78;
    • and "Is Rationality Normative?" Disputatio 23 (2007) : 161-78;
  • 10
    • 58749091781 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolodny, Why Be Rational?; Scanlon, Structural Irrationality; Nadeem Hussain, The Requirements of Rationality (unpublished manuscript, Stanford University, 2007), available at http://www.stan.ford.edu/~hussain.n/StanfordPersonal/Online-Papers-files/ HussainRequirementsv24.pdf.
    • Kolodny, "Why Be Rational?"; Scanlon, "Structural Irrationality"; Nadeem Hussain, "The Requirements of Rationality" (unpublished manuscript, Stanford University, 2007), available at http://www.stan.ford.edu/~hussain.n/StanfordPersonal/Online-Papers-files/ HussainRequirementsv24.pdf.
  • 14
    • 58749113385 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 165, 177.
    • , vol.165 , pp. 177
    • Broome1
  • 15
    • 58749111406 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There are three main kinds of skeptical strategies that have been deployed widiin the literature: (i) trying to show that the apparent normativity of rationality cannot be vindicated, (ii) trying to show that the apparent normativity of rationality can be explained away, and (iii) trying to show that the thesis that rationality is normative results in a kind of objectionable bootstrapping. All three strategies are pursued by Kolodny in Why Be Rational? I shall focus here only on i.
    • There are three main kinds of skeptical strategies that have been deployed widiin the literature: (i) trying to show that the apparent normativity of rationality cannot be vindicated, (ii) trying to show that the apparent normativity of rationality can be explained away, and (iii) trying to show that the thesis that rationality is normative results in a kind of objectionable bootstrapping. All three strategies are pursued by Kolodny in "Why Be Rational?" I shall focus here only on i.
  • 18
    • 58749097194 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is somewhat, obscured, by the fact that Kolodny sometimes uses the phrase the normativity of rationality when he really means the apparent normativity of rationality. See Sec. U.C
    • This is somewhat, obscured, by the fact that Kolodny sometimes uses the phrase "the normativity of rationality" when he really means the apparent normativity of rationality. See Sec. U.C.
  • 20
    • 0003867020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, chap. 1
    • T. M. Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998), chap. 1.
    • (1998) What We Owe to Each Other
    • Scanlon, T.M.1
  • 25
    • 58749102002 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course, this already concedes that we are able to dispose ourselves in a way that makes it impossible to fail to conform with rational requirements, which is questionable to say the least
    • Of course, this already concedes that we are able to dispose ourselves in a way that makes it impossible to fail to conform with rational requirements, which is questionable to say the least.
  • 29
    • 0012697616 scopus 로고
    • Something like this view appears to have been endorsed by, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Something like this view appears to have been endorsed by Michael H. Robins, Promising, Intending and Moral Autonomy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985).
    • (1985) Promising, Intending and Moral Autonomy
    • Robins, M.H.1
  • 30
    • 58749091580 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is also hinted at in Bruno Verbeek, Rational Self-Commitment, in Rationality and Commitment, ed. Fabienne Peter and Hans Bernhard Schmid (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008).
    • It is also hinted at in Bruno Verbeek, "Rational Self-Commitment," in Rationality and Commitment, ed. Fabienne Peter and Hans Bernhard Schmid (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008).
  • 31
    • 58749104312 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Broome, Is Rationality Normative? 1.77.
    • Broome, "Is Rationality Normative?" 1.77.
  • 32
    • 33747894421 scopus 로고
    • Does Moral Philosophy Rest on a Mistake?
    • H. A. Prichard, "Does Moral Philosophy Rest on a Mistake?" Mind 21 (1912): 21-37.
    • (1912) Mind , vol.21 , pp. 21-37
    • Prichard, H.A.1
  • 33
    • 58749086863 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Since writing the current essay, I have learned that Nadeem Hussain has independently made a suggestion much along the same lines in his excellent unpublished essay The Requirements of Rationality.
    • Since writing the current essay, I have learned that Nadeem Hussain has independently made a suggestion much along the same lines in his excellent unpublished essay "The Requirements of Rationality."
  • 34
    • 0040280001 scopus 로고
    • Autonomist Internalism and the Justification of Morals
    • See
    • See Stephen Darwall, "Autonomist Internalism and the Justification of Morals," Noûs 24 (1990): 257-67;
    • (1990) Noûs , vol.24 , pp. 257-267
    • Darwall, S.1
  • 37
    • 58749111219 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I shall therefore set aside expressivist theories of rationality of the kind endorsed by Allan Gibbard in Wise Choices, Apt Feelings: A Theory of Normative Judgement Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990
    • I shall therefore set aside expressivist theories of rationality of the kind endorsed by Allan Gibbard in Wise Choices, Apt Feelings: A Theory of Normative Judgement (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990).
  • 39
    • 58749113384 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Requirements of Rationality
    • Hussain, "The Requirements of Rationality," 7, 46 (emphasis added).
    • 46 (emphasis added) , vol.7
    • Hussain1
  • 40
    • 58749105776 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 2. Hussain does not say exactly what he takes being committed to a principle to involve but presumably it is meant to be an amalgam of various psychological attitudes such as taking the principle to be a valid rational requirement, being disposed to transition in accordance with it, being disposed, to disapprove of known violations of it, and taking the aforementioned, attitudes to be justified.
    • Ibid., 2. Hussain does not say exactly what he takes being "committed" to a principle to involve but presumably it is meant to be an amalgam of various psychological attitudes such as taking the principle to be a valid rational requirement, being disposed to transition in accordance with it, being disposed, to disapprove of known violations of it, and taking the aforementioned, attitudes to be justified.
  • 43
    • 58749108960 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Notice that it is possible to deny Hussain's claim, here and yet hold that it is a necessary condition for something's counting as a rational requirement that we be able to satisfy it by engaging in reasoning. The latter is, in effect, Kolodny's reasoning test on rational requirements (Kolodny, Why Be Rational? 520).
    • Notice that it is possible to deny Hussain's claim, here and yet hold that it is a necessary condition for something's counting as a rational requirement that we be able to satisfy it by engaging in reasoning. The latter is, in effect, Kolodny's "reasoning test" on rational requirements (Kolodny, "Why Be Rational?" 520).
  • 44
    • 58749106737 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It might be thought that this implicitly assumes a wide-scope conception of rationality. But that would be a mistake. One might instead hold a narrow-scope conception of rationality and yet still deny that rational requirements apply only to reasoning. A narrow-scope version of the requirement of instrumental rationality is as follows: if you intend to X and believe your Xing requires your intending to Y, then you are rationally required, to intend to Y. This requirement, applies to you if and. when you have the intention of Xing. It does not fail to apply to you if you happen not to be engaging in any reasoning
    • It might be thought that this implicitly assumes a wide-scope conception of rationality. But that would be a mistake. One might instead hold a narrow-scope conception of rationality and yet still deny that rational requirements apply only to reasoning. A narrow-scope version of the requirement of instrumental rationality is as follows: if you intend to X and believe your Xing requires your intending to Y, then you are rationally required, to intend to Y. This requirement, applies to you if and. when you have the intention of Xing. It does not fail to apply to you if you happen not to be engaging in any reasoning.
  • 45
    • 58749089791 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This echoes Andrew Reisner's argument against the version, of the distinctive object account that Broome used to endorse in Reisner, Why Rational Requirements Are Not Normative Requirements unpublished manuscript, University of McGill, 2006, available at
    • This echoes Andrew Reisner's argument against the version, of the distinctive object account that Broome used to endorse in Reisner, "Why Rational Requirements Are Not Normative Requirements" (unpublished manuscript, University of McGill, 2006), available at http://www.mcgill.ca/ files/philosophy/RationalRequirementsandNormative Requirementswebpageversion. pdf.
  • 46
    • 58749099234 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This objection will apply to any version of the distinctive object account
    • This objection will apply to any version of the distinctive object account.
  • 48
    • 84881773411 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and What Good Is a Will? in Action in Context, ed. Anton Leist and Holger Baumann (Berlin: de Gruyter, 2007), 193-215.
    • and "What Good Is a Will?" in Action in Context, ed. Anton Leist and Holger Baumann (Berlin: de Gruyter, 2007), 193-215.
  • 50
    • 58749115536 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Intention, Belief and Instrumental Rationality, in Reasons for Action, ed. David. Sobel and Steven Wall (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, forthcoming), manuscript available at http://www-philosophy. stanford.edu/fss/pa.pers/BratmanIBIR.pdf,
    • "Intention, Belief and Instrumental Rationality," in Reasons for Action, ed. David. Sobel and Steven Wall (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, forthcoming), manuscript available at http://www-philosophy. stanford.edu/fss/pa.pers/BratmanIBIR.pdf,
  • 51
    • 58749091946 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Intention, Belief, Practical, Theoretical, in Spheres of Reason, ed. Jens Timmerman, John Skorupski, and Simon Robertson (Oxford: Oxford University Press, forthcoming), manuscript, available at http://www-philosophy.stanford.edu/fss/papers/BratmanIBPT.pdf.
    • and "Intention, Belief, Practical, Theoretical," in Spheres of Reason, ed. Jens Timmerman, John Skorupski, and Simon Robertson (Oxford: Oxford University Press, forthcoming), manuscript, available at http://www-philosophy.stanford.edu/fss/papers/BratmanIBPT.pdf.
  • 54
    • 60949115963 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Why Be Rational?
    • Kolodny
    • Scanlon, "Structural Irrationality"; Kolodny, "Why Be Rational?" 557-60.
    • Scanlon1
  • 60
    • 58749096483 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I think it is also possible to see that the subject reasons account fails in the task of explaining away the normativity of rationality for reasons presented extremely eloquently by Nadeem Hussain. Hussain writes: If I say to [my friends, You are irrational, then, naturally enough, they take me to be making a criticism of them, a normative claim, that they ought to change their attitudes, and they immediately, you can rest assured, feel the pressure to what they perceive as a. challenge. Now imagine that in the face of the initial, heated response, I say, Calm down, I'm just making a descriptive psychological claim and one that you already agree with. Look, after all, you granted that you don't have sufficient reason to have A, and that, you have A, I am sure we can imagine the look of utter perplexity that would cross their faces Hussain, The Requirements of Rationality, 29
    • I think it is also possible to see that the subject reasons account fails in the task of explaining away the normativity of rationality for reasons presented extremely eloquently by Nadeem Hussain. Hussain writes: "If I say to [my friends], 'You are irrational', then, naturally enough, they take me to be making a criticism of them ... a normative claim, that they ought to change their attitudes, and they immediately, you can rest assured, feel the pressure to what they perceive as a. challenge. Now imagine that in the face of the initial, heated response, I say, 'Calm down, I'm just making a descriptive psychological claim and one that you already agree with. Look, after all, you granted that you don't have sufficient reason to have A, and that, you have A. . . .' I am sure we can imagine the look of utter perplexity that would cross their faces" (Hussain, "The Requirements of Rationality," 29).
  • 61
    • 0004207980 scopus 로고
    • See, New York: Oxford University Press
    • See Thomas Nagel, The View from Nowhere (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986),
    • (1986) The View from Nowhere
    • Nagel, T.1
  • 62
    • 58749109575 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Equality and Partiality (New York: Oxford University Press, 1991).
    • and Equality and Partiality (New York: Oxford University Press, 1991).
  • 63
    • 58749108421 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We do not have infallible access to the content of our first-personal standpoint. So, for example, I might, think that, a certain kind of activity is important, to me, whereas in fact it isn't
    • We do not have infallible access to the content of our first-personal standpoint. So, for example, I might, think that, a certain kind of activity is important, to me, whereas in fact it isn't.
  • 64
    • 58749100784 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There are a number of answers that will obviously not do. Thus, it will not do to say that they are norms that describe the proper functioning of our agential systems. Such norms fail to capture the distinctively first-personal character of standpoint-relative demands. Nor will it do to say that they are prudential norms, norms that are grounded in what is good for us. What is good for us and what our standpoints require may diverge
    • There are a number of answers that will obviously not do. Thus, it will not do to say that they are norms that describe the proper functioning of our agential systems. Such norms fail to capture the distinctively first-personal character of standpoint-relative demands. Nor will it do to say that they are prudential norms, norms that are grounded in what is good for us. What is good for us and what our standpoints require may diverge.
  • 66
    • 58749088349 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I take this to be neutral in respect to whether rational requirements have wide or narrow scope. See n. 5
    • I take this to be neutral in respect to whether rational requirements have wide or narrow scope. See n. 5.
  • 67
    • 58749106199 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One question that might be thought to arise for the first-personal audiority account concerns the relation between the perspective-relative demands of rationality and other kinds of demands, in particular how to weigh them up if they conflict. It. may be thought, that it will be hard, to escape some kind of normative incommensurability. This is a fascinating issue that I cannot hope to address properly here. But let me just note that, even if the first-personal authority account did generate normative incommensurability, it is not obvious to me that this would be such, a serious problem. There are a number of other instances where normative incommensurability seems to be something that, we must live with. Consider, for example, cases where we epistemically ought to believe propositions that we prudentially ought not to believe. To ask what, we really ought to believe in such contexts seems simply wrongheaded
    • One question that might be thought to arise for the first-personal audiority account concerns the relation between the perspective-relative demands of rationality and other kinds of demands, in particular how to weigh them up if they conflict. It. may be thought, that it will be hard, to escape some kind of normative incommensurability. This is a fascinating issue that I cannot hope to address properly here. But let me just note that, even if the first-personal authority account did generate normative incommensurability, it is not obvious to me that this would be such, a serious problem. There are a number of other instances where normative incommensurability seems to be something that, we must live with. Consider, for example, cases where we epistemically ought to believe propositions that we prudentially ought not to believe. To ask what, we "really ought" to believe in such contexts seems simply wrongheaded.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.