-
1
-
-
85063705249
-
-
New York: St. Martins, Kants works have been referenced the following way, using Akademie pagination: trans N. Kemp-Smith (1965) LE: Lectures on Ethics trans. L. Infield (Indianapolis: Hackett 1930) GS: Kants Gesammelte Schriften (BerlinGrunter 1934), my trans. GW: Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals trans. L. Beck (New York: Macmillan 1959) (referred to as Groundwork) MM: The Metaphysics of Morals trans. M. Gregor (CambridgeCambridge University Press 1993): ‘Perpetual Peace,’ Perpetual Peace and Other Essays trans. T. Humphrey (Indianapolis: Hackett 1983) TP: ‘On the Proverb: That may be true Theory, but is of no Practical Use,’ Perpetual Peace and Other Essays (referred to as ‘Theory and Practice’) UH: ‘Idea for a Universal History with a Cosmopolitan Intent,’ Perpetual Peace and Other Essays
-
New York: St. Martin's. Kant's works have been referenced in the following way, using Akademie pagination:CPR: Critique of Pure Reason trans N. Kemp-Smith (1965) LE: Lectures on Ethics trans. L. Infield (Indianapolis: Hackett 1930) GS: Kant's Gesammelte Schriften (BerlinGrunter 1934), my trans. GW: Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals trans. L. Beck (New York: Macmillan 1959) (referred to as Groundwork) MM: The Metaphysics of Morals trans. M. Gregor (CambridgeCambridge University Press 1993) PP: ‘Perpetual Peace,’ in Perpetual Peace and Other Essays trans. T. Humphrey (Indianapolis: Hackett 1983) TP: ‘On the Proverb: That may be true in Theory, but is of no Practical Use,’ in Perpetual Peace and Other Essays (referred to as ‘Theory and Practice’) UH: ‘Idea for a Universal History with a Cosmopolitan Intent,’ in Perpetual Peace and Other Essays
-
CPR: Critique of Pure ReasonLectures on EthicsGS: Kant's Gesammelte SchriftenFoundations of the Metaphysics of MoralsGroundwork) MM: The Metaphysics of MoralsPP:Perpetual Peace and Other EssaysTP:Perpetual Peace and Other EssaysUH:Perpetual Peace and Other Essays
-
-
-
3
-
-
0004051088
-
-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, My interpretation of Kants views on beneficence draws to a great degree on Hermans persuasive treatment of them
-
Herman, B., 1993. The Practice of Moral Judgment 65Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. My interpretation of Kant's views on beneficence draws to a great degree on Herman's persuasive treatment of them.
-
(1993)
The Practice of Moral Judgment
, pp. 65
-
-
Herman, B.1
-
4
-
-
0021559716
-
-
Allen Buchanan argues that Kants ‘impossibility willing’ rationale supports the much stronger conclusion that we cannot will that others ever fail to provide aid— that is, that on any occasion which aid is needed, providing it is morally obligatory; thus there is fact no discretion or latitude allowed beneficence (A. Buchanan, ‘The Right to a Decent Minimum of Health Care,’ Philosophy and Public Affairs13 [] 55–78, at 74–5).I follow Herman rejecting this strong construal of the duty of beneficence. She argues that such a ‘radical commitment of aid would not be supportive of the expression of rational agency ones life,’ because it would allow no balancing of the gravity of the need with the costs imposed on the giver, and thus would undermine the rational ‘life activity’ of the giver which is the very point of mutual aid (70). That balancing is possible only by the (potential) giver of aid, so discretion and latitude are necessary for the point of the duty to be achieved
-
1984. Allen Buchanan argues that Kant's ‘impossibility in willing’ rationale supports the much stronger conclusion that we cannot will that others ever fail to provide aid— that is, that on any occasion in which aid is needed, providing it is morally obligatory; thus there is in fact no discretion or latitude allowed in beneficence (A. Buchanan, ‘The Right to a Decent Minimum of Health Care,’ Philosophy and Public Affairs13 [] 55–78, at 74–5).I follow Herman in rejecting this strong construal of the duty of beneficence. She argues that such a ‘radical commitment of aid would not be supportive of the expression of rational agency in one's life,’ because it would allow no balancing of the gravity of the need with the costs imposed on the giver, and thus would undermine the rational ‘life activity’ of the giver which is the very point of mutual aid (70). That balancing is possible only by the (potential) giver of aid, so discretion and latitude are necessary for the point of the duty to be achieved.
-
(1984)
-
-
-
5
-
-
85063702916
-
-
Compare Herman: ‘One might view the idea of taking anothers ends as my own not the sense that I should be prepared to act his place (I act for him; I get for him what he wants when he cannot) but, rather, the sense that I support his status as a pursuer of ends, so that I am prepared to do what is necessary to help him maintain that status. We might say I help him pursue-his-ends and not I help him the pursuit of his ends. This interpretation… leads me to view the well-being of another as something more than the (passive) satisfaction of his desires. What I support is the others active and successful pursuit of his self-defined goals’ (70
-
Compare Herman: ‘One might view the idea of taking another's ends as my own not in the sense that I should be prepared to act in his place (I act for him; I get for him what he wants when he cannot) but, rather, in the sense that I support his status as a pursuer of ends, so that I am prepared to do what is necessary to help him maintain that status. We might say “I help him pursue-his-ends” and not “I help him in the pursuit of his ends.” This interpretation… leads me to view the well-being of another as something more than the (passive) satisfaction of his desires. What I support is the other's active and successful pursuit of his self-defined goals’ (70).
-
-
-
-
6
-
-
79957077584
-
-
Kant apparently had worries along these lines himself. He expresses reservations about state welfare provision along with his personal concern for the poor 8000: ‘The helpless poor must be supported and, when they are children, be well cared-for. Why? because we are men and not beasts. This (follows) flows not from the rights of the poor as citizens but from their needs as men. Not just the innocent; for then there would be few. Who shall support them? The question is not whether it is the State or the citizen, for when the State provides for them, the citizen provides for them as well, but instead, whether from the free will of the citizens or through coercion they will be supported— as a gift or as a tax. The latter brings out a competition for provisions among the candidates; it is a means of acquisition and also a claim to entitlement (titulus der Ansprüche). And who shall determine helplessness?’ (GS XIX, 578
-
Reflexion Kant apparently had worries along these lines himself. He expresses reservations about state welfare provision along with his personal concern for the poor in 8000: ‘The helpless poor must be supported and, when they are children, be well cared-for. Why? because we are men and not beasts. This (follows) flows not from the rights of the poor as citizens but from their needs as men. Not just the innocent; for then there would be few. Who shall support them? The question is not whether it is the State or the citizen, for when the State provides for them, the citizen provides for them as well, but instead, whether from the free will of the citizens or through coercion they will be supported— as a gift or as a tax. The latter brings out a competition for provisions among the candidates; it is a means of acquisition and also a claim to entitlement (titulus der Ansprüche). And who shall determine helplessness?’ (GS XIX, 578)
-
Reflexion
-
-
-
7
-
-
0003803948
-
-
Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press
-
Rosen, A., 1993. Kant's Theory of Justice 191Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
-
(1993)
Kant's Theory of Justice
, pp. 191
-
-
Rosen, A.1
-
8
-
-
85063703667
-
-
Oxford: Blackwell, The instrumental view is defended by Mary Gregor, Howard Williams, Kants Political Philosophy (Oxford: Blackwell 1983), 193ff.; Wolfgang Kersting, ‘Kants Concept of the State,’ Essays on Kants Political Philosophy H. Williams, ed. (Cardiff: University of Wales Press 1992), 164n.; and Bruce Aune, Kants Theory of Morals (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press 1979), 157, 160. Thomas Pogge takes the instrumental rationale to be primary, but argues that the ‘enlightenment’ of the populace might support a more expansive notion (‘Kants Theory of Justice,’ Kant-Studien7 [1988] 407–33, at 422n). Jeffrie Murphy, like Rosen, takes Kant to justify the public provision of welfare from beneficence (Kant: The Philosophy of Right [London: Macmillan 1970], 146). A similar rationale for welfare is offered by Alan Gewirth, although it is not ascribed to Kant (‘Private Philanthropy and Positive Rights,’ Social Philosophy and Policy4 [1985] 60–7). Joseph Grcic (‘Kant on Revolution and Economic Inequality,’ Kant-Studien 77 [1987] 447–57, at 455) and Harry van der Linden (Kantian Ethics and Socialism [Indianapolis: Hackett 1988], 203) offer justifications for welfare which ostensibly depend on Kants principles of autonomy; however, I think they (like Pogges second rationale) are best understood as resting on freedom, which is the approach Leslie Mulholland takes (Kants System of Rights [New York: Columbia University Press 1990]). I consider this line of argument Section V below
-
1963. Laws of Freedom 36Oxford: Blackwell. The instrumental view is defended by Mary Gregor, Howard Williams, Kant's Political Philosophy (Oxford: Blackwell 1983), 193ff.; Wolfgang Kersting, ‘Kant's Concept of the State,’ Essays on Kant's Political Philosophy H. Williams, ed. (Cardiff: University of Wales Press 1992), 164n.; and Bruce Aune, Kant's Theory of Morals (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press 1979), 157, 160. Thomas Pogge takes the instrumental rationale to be primary, but argues that the ‘enlightenment’ of the populace might support a more expansive notion (‘Kant's Theory of Justice,’ Kant-Studien7 [1988] 407–33, at 422n). Jeffrie Murphy, like Rosen, takes Kant to justify the public provision of welfare from beneficence (Kant: The Philosophy of Right [London: Macmillan 1970], 146). A similar rationale for welfare is offered by Alan Gewirth, although it is not ascribed to Kant (‘Private Philanthropy and Positive Rights,’ Social Philosophy and Policy4 [1985] 60–7). Joseph Grcic (‘Kant on Revolution and Economic Inequality,’ Kant-Studien 77 [1987] 447–57, at 455) and Harry van der Linden (Kantian Ethics and Socialism [Indianapolis: Hackett 1988], 203) offer justifications for welfare which ostensibly depend on Kant's principles of autonomy; however, I think they (like Pogge's second rationale) are best understood as resting on freedom, which is the approach Leslie Mulholland takes (Kant's System of Rights [New York: Columbia University Press 1990]). I consider this line of argument in Section V below.
-
(1963)
Laws of Freedom
, pp. 36
-
-
-
10
-
-
85063702806
-
-
I thank an anonymous referee for suggesting this line of thought. An argument to this effect is made (in a non-Kantian context) by James Sterba (From Liberty to Welfare/105 [1994] 64–98, at 78f); Allen Buchanan argues for a ‘decent minimum of health care’ on just these grounds (‘The Right to a Decent Minimum of Health Care,’ 70ff.; see also A. Buchanan, ‘Justice and Charity,’ Ethics97 [1987] 558–75
-
Ethics, I thank an anonymous referee for suggesting this line of thought. An argument to this effect is made (in a non-Kantian context) by James Sterba ('From Liberty to Welfare/105 [1994] 64–98, at 78f); Allen Buchanan argues for a ‘decent minimum of health care’ on just these grounds (‘The Right to a Decent Minimum of Health Care,’ 70ff.; see also A. Buchanan, ‘Justice and Charity,’ Ethics97 [1987] 558–75).
-
Ethics
-
-
-
11
-
-
85063703215
-
-
At points Rosen suggests something like this argument (cf. Rosen, 188, 204), but it gets tangled with (i) the idea that the state as a moral person has its own duty of beneficence, or (ii) the idea that individual ends of self-preservation justify the general will in providing public welfare (200–2, 206–7), or (iii) the idea that a social minimum is necessary as a condition of external freedom. The arguments from self-preservation and freedom I consider below.
-
At points Rosen suggests something like this argument (cf. Rosen, 188, 204), but it gets tangled with (i) the idea that the state as a moral person has its own duty of beneficence, or (ii) the idea that individual ends of self-preservation justify the general will in providing public welfare (200–2, 206–7), or (iii) the idea that a social minimum is necessary as a condition of external freedom. The arguments from self-preservation and freedom I consider below.
-
-
-
-
12
-
-
0347203045
-
”This Enormous Army”: The Mutual Aid Tradition of American Frternal Societies before the Twentieth Century
-
See and Stephen Davies, ‘Two Conceptions of Welfare: Voluntarism and Incorporationism,’ Social Philosophy and Policy141997 39–68, for evidence to this effect British and American history of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries
-
Beito, David. 1997. ‘”This Enormous Army”: The Mutual Aid Tradition of American Frternal Societies before the Twentieth Century,’. Social Philosophy and Policy, 14: 20–38. See and Stephen Davies, ‘Two Conceptions of Welfare: Voluntarism and Incorporationism,’ Social Philosophy and Policy141997 39–68, for evidence to this effect in British and American history of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries.
-
(1997)
Social Philosophy and Policy
, vol.14
, pp. 20-38
-
-
Beito, D.1
-
13
-
-
0004255456
-
-
Indianapolis: Hackett, Rousseau distinguishes the general will, which ‘considers only the general interest,’ from the ‘will of all,’ which ‘considers private interest and is merely the sum of private wills’ (J.-J. Rousseau, trans. D. Cress [], 155). As Mulholland observes (333), this is not Kants conception of the general will, as it lacks the a priori nature which is crucial for Kant. My understanding of Kants account of the general will is greatly indebted to Mulholland
-
1987. Basic Political Writings Indianapolis: Hackett. Rousseau distinguishes the general will, which ‘considers only the general interest,’ from the ‘will of all,’ which ‘considers private interest and is merely the sum of private wills’ (J.-J. Rousseau, trans. D. Cress [], 155). As Mulholland observes (333), this is not Kant's conception of the general will, as it lacks the a priori nature which is crucial for Kant. My understanding of Kant's account of the general will is greatly indebted to Mulholland.
-
(1987)
Basic Political Writings
-
-
-
15
-
-
85063697362
-
-
Kant says a kind of ‘despotism’ results from ‘an executive power which all citizens make decisions about and, if need be, against one (who therefore does not agree); consequently, all, who are not quite all, decide, so that the general will contradicts both itself and freedom’ (352
-
PP Kant says a kind of ‘despotism’ results from ‘an executive power in which all citizens make decisions about and, if need be, against one (who therefore does not agree); consequently, all, who are not quite all, decide, so that the general will contradicts both itself and freedom’ (352).
-
PP
-
-
-
16
-
-
85063698619
-
-
Rosen notes that Kant assumes that every rational being seeks the maximum amount of external freedom and the minimum restrictions on liberty, so that ‘maximum equal liberty is one of the rational ends of the general will, or of a people considered as a whole’ (137). Cf. also Kersting (‘Kants Concept of the State,’ 151
-
Rosen notes that Kant assumes that every rational being seeks the maximum amount of external freedom and the minimum restrictions on liberty, so that ‘maximum equal liberty is one of the rational ends of the general will, or of a people considered as a whole’ (137). Cf. also Kersting (‘Kant's Concept of the State,’ 151).
-
-
-
-
17
-
-
85063702895
-
-
Rosen attempts to avoid this problem by claiming that since the welfare institutions are an expression of the general will, they are not coercively imposed. He claims that ‘In a Kantian republic, governments are popularly elected and the policies they adopt, including those concerned with social welfare and taxation, are not, if honestly presented at election time, coercively imposed on an unwilling citizenry…. Their governing by popular consent means that their policies bear the imprint of the popular will…. they can be represented, within the context of the liberal conception of electoral consent, as voluntary restrictions imposed by a people on its own freedom’ (Rosen, 204). But there is no support for this anything Kant says; worse, it manifestly rests on the misconception of the general will rejected above
-
Rosen attempts to avoid this problem by claiming that since the welfare institutions are an expression of the general will, they are not coercively imposed. He claims that ‘In a Kantian republic, governments are popularly elected and the policies they adopt, including those concerned with social welfare and taxation, are not, if honestly presented at election time, coercively imposed on an unwilling citizenry…. Their governing by popular consent means that their policies bear the imprint of the popular will…. they can be represented, within the context of the liberal conception of electoral consent, as voluntary restrictions imposed by a people on its own freedom’ (Rosen, 204). But there is no support for this in anything Kant says; worse, it manifestly rests on the misconception of the general will rejected above.
-
-
-
-
18
-
-
85063698328
-
-
David Schmidtz observes that even if our minimal needs for self-preservation are rationally required, having them assured by the state may not be. As he puts the point, ‘That we are better off having food, clothing, and shelter is beyond question; that we are better off having guaranteed provision of such things is not’ (D. Schmidtz, ‘Guarantees,’ 14 [] 1–19, at 1
-
1997. Social Philosophy and Policy David Schmidtz observes that even if our minimal needs for self-preservation are rationally required, having them assured by the state may not be. As he puts the point, ‘That we are better off having food, clothing, and shelter is beyond question; that we are better off having guaranteed provision of such things is not’ (D. Schmidtz, ‘Guarantees,’ 14 [] 1–19, at 1).
-
(1997)
Social Philosophy and Policy
-
-
-
19
-
-
39049156552
-
-
Hillel Steiner claims, for instance, that to be rightful initial distributions of property must be the object of social contract. He proposes that a refinement on Henry Georges strategy to collectivize and distribute land rents may be required by such a contract (H. Steiner, ‘Liberty and Equality,’ 29 [1981] 555–69). While Steiner does not purport to interpret Kants political theory, the conception of freedom he articulates is a good fit for this line of argument. Other arguments from liberty to welfare are offered by J. Sterba, ‘From Liberty to Welfare’; G.A. Cohen, ‘Capitalism, Freedom, and the Proletariat,’ The Idea of Freedom: Essays Honour of Isaiah Berlin A. Ryan, ed. (Oxford; Oxford University Press 1979); and Ernest Loevinsohn, Liberty and the Redistribution of Property/Philosophy and Public Affairs 61976 226–39
-
Political Studies, Hillel Steiner claims, for instance, that to be rightful initial distributions of property must be the object of social contract. He proposes that a refinement on Henry George's strategy to collectivize and distribute land rents may be required by such a contract (H. Steiner, ‘Liberty and Equality,’ 29 [1981] 555–69). While Steiner does not purport to interpret Kant's political theory, the conception of freedom he articulates is a good fit for this line of argument. Other arguments from liberty to welfare are offered by J. Sterba, ‘From Liberty to Welfare’; G.A. Cohen, ‘Capitalism, Freedom, and the Proletariat,’ The Idea of Freedom: Essays in Honour of Isaiah Berlin A. Ryan, ed. (Oxford; Oxford University Press 1979); and Ernest Loevinsohn, 'Liberty and the Redistribution of Property/Philosophy and Public Affairs 61976 226–39
-
Political Studies
-
-
-
20
-
-
0345570006
-
Politics, Freedom, and Order: Kant's Political Philosophy
-
Guyer P., (ed), New York: Cambridge University Press,. Edited by
-
Kersting, W., 1992. “ ‘Politics, Freedom, and Order: Kant's Political Philosophy,’ ”. In Cambridge Companion to Kant Edited by: Guyer, P., 351New York: Cambridge University Press.
-
(1992)
Cambridge Companion to Kant
, pp. 351
-
-
Kersting, W.1
-
22
-
-
85063698966
-
-
’ (‘, Kants Concept of the State,’ 153), though Kersting argues that the standing of this ‘contingent’ principle with freedom and equality cannot be justified within Kantian theory
-
As does Kant's third principle of law, independence (TP 290), which, as Kersting himself argues, must be understood as an ‘economic characteristic’ (‘Kant's Concept of the State,’ 153), though Kersting argues that the standing of this ‘contingent’ principle with freedom and equality cannot be justified within Kantian theory.
-
As does Kant's third principle of law, independence (TP 290), which, as Kersting himself argues, must be understood as an ‘economic characteristic
-
-
-
23
-
-
85063703046
-
‘if I am holding a thing (and so physically connected with it), someone who affects it without my consent (e.g. snatches an apple from my hand) affects and diminishes what is internally mine (my freedom), so that his maxim is in direct contradiction with the axiom of Right’ (MM 250)
-
Kants idea seems to be that our innate right to freedom extends to our bodies and even to the land— the space on earth— we must occupy as embodied beings: he says ‘dragging me from my resting place’ is morally on par with wresting the apple from my hand (MM 248
-
Kant says that someone trying to ‘wrest the apple from my hand’ is wronging me ‘with regard to what is internally mine (freedom)’ (MM 248): ‘if I am holding a thing (and so physically connected with it), someone who affects it without my consent (e.g. snatches an apple from my hand) affects and diminishes what is internally mine (my freedom), so that his maxim is in direct contradiction with the axiom of Right’ (MM 250). Kant's idea seems to be that our innate right to freedom extends to our bodies and even to the land— the space on earth— we must occupy as embodied beings: he says ‘dragging me from my resting place’ is morally on par with wresting the apple from my hand (MM 248).
-
Kant says that someone trying to ‘wrest the apple from my hand’ is wronging me ‘with regard to what is internally mine (freedom)’ (MM 248)
-
-
-
24
-
-
85063701649
-
Now all men rightfully possess the area of the Earth wherein Nature or chance has placed them without their will, and so according to an innate right (before all acts establishing a right) in the possession of the earth on which they arrive, as the supreme condition of the possibility of use of the same so long as this is straightforwardly necessary for the bare preservation of their existence
-
‘Now all men rightfully possess the area of the Earth wherein Nature or chance has placed them without their will, and so according to an innate right (before all acts establishing a right) in the possession of the earth on which they arrive, as the supreme condition of the possibility of use of the same so long as this is straightforwardly necessary for the bare preservation of their existence’ (GS XXIII, 318).
-
GS XXIII
, vol.318
-
-
-
25
-
-
85063705111
-
Kant's conception of innate right, that a better conception would entail that others are obligated to provide for us if that is necessary for self-preservation. In response note, first, that even if this is right, it is not in any event the view Kant actually held, and second, that given his overall moral theory he had reason to reject this stronger thesis: It would unilaterally impose on others an even stronger obligation than
-
what is imposed by the view of innate right he actually held
-
It might be argued by the defender of welfare rights that this betrays a crucial defect in Kant's conception of innate right, that a better conception would entail that others are obligated to provide for us if that is necessary for self-preservation. In response note, first, that even if this is right, it is not in any event the view Kant actually held, and second, that given his overall moral theory he had reason to reject this stronger thesis: it would unilaterally impose on others an even stronger obligation than what is imposed by the view of innate right he actually held.
-
It might be argued by the defender of welfare rights that this betrays a crucial defect in
-
-
-
26
-
-
85063705727
-
-
There are those, of course, who through no fault of their own are not able to participate such cooperative arrangements (e.g. through physical disabilities), hence whose means of self-preservation are problematic. But it is important to see that an appeal to the innate right to freedom will not solve that problem, since such persons would likewise be incapable of securing their own survival absent the property rights structure that civil society implements. The argument from freedom is of no help to such cases, which often motivate concern for public welfare the first place. By way of contrast, the right to welfare defended by James Sterba is ‘conditional on people doing all that they legitimately can to provide for themselves’ (Sterba, 83n.; cf. also 77); the system he defends crippling disabilities would trigger that right. But Kants innate rights are not sensitive to these sorts of incapacities, nor do they impose the burden of support on others that Sterbas view does. Whether such cases are satisfactorily addressed by Kants instrumental rationale for welfare is a further question
-
There are those, of course, who through no fault of their own are not able to participate in such cooperative arrangements (e.g. through physical disabilities), hence whose means of self-preservation are problematic. But it is important to see that an appeal to the innate right to freedom will not solve that problem, since such persons would likewise be incapable of securing their own survival absent the property rights structure that civil society implements. The argument from freedom is of no help to such cases, which often motivate concern for public welfare in the first place. By way of contrast, the right to welfare defended by James Sterba is ‘conditional on people doing all that they legitimately can to provide for themselves’ (Sterba, 83n.; cf. also 77); in the system he defends crippling disabilities would ipso facto trigger that right. But Kant's innate rights are not sensitive to these sorts of incapacities, nor do they impose the burden of support on others that Sterba's view does. Whether such cases are satisfactorily addressed by Kant's instrumental rationale for welfare is a further question.
-
Ipso facto
-
-
|