메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 34, Issue 2, 2008, Pages 157-176

Judgment and the reification of the faculties: A reconstructive reading of Arendt's Life of the Mind

Author keywords

critique; Hannah Arendt; judgment; life of the mind; modernity; nihilism; thinking; understanding; will; worldliness

Indexed keywords


EID: 57749139734     PISSN: 01914537     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1177/0191453707084279     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (21)

References (58)
  • 1
    • 0003922756 scopus 로고
    • Mary McCarthy (New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich). This is a one-volume edition of what was originally published as two volumes. Part I is ‘Thinking’ and Part II is ‘Willing’
    • Hannah Arendt, The Life of the Mind, ed. Mary McCarthy (New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1978). This is a one-volume edition of what was originally published as two volumes. Part I is ‘Thinking’ and Part II is ‘Willing’.
    • (1978) The Life of the Mind
    • Arendt, H.1
  • 2
    • 0004007294 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • edited with an interpretive essay by Ronald Beiner (Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press)
    • Hannah Arendt, Lectures on Kant's Political Philosophy, edited with an interpretive essay by Ronald Beiner (Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press, 1992).
    • (1992) Lectures on Kant's Political Philosophy
    • Arendt, H.1
  • 3
    • 0003924260 scopus 로고
    • See also Arendt's ‘The Crisis in Culture: Its Social and its Political Significance’, ‘Truth and Politics’ and ‘Freedom and Politics’, all in, Harmondsworth, Mx: Penguin, especially
    • See also Arendt's ‘The Crisis in Culture: Its Social and its Political Significance’, ‘Truth and Politics’ and ‘Freedom and Politics’, all in Between Past and Future: Eight Exercises in Political Thought (Harmondsworth, Mx: Penguin, 1977), especially pp. 219–26.
    • (1977) Between Past and Future: Eight Exercises in Political Thought , pp. 219-226
  • 4
    • 16244401525 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hannah Arendt on Judgment: The Unwritten Doctrine of Reason
    • Ronald Beiner and Jennifer Nedelsky (eds), New York: Rowman & Littlefield, This is the most valuable collection on the topic
    • Albrecht Wellmer, ‘Hannah Arendt on Judgment: The Unwritten Doctrine of Reason’, in Ronald Beiner and Jennifer Nedelsky (eds) Judgment, Imagination and Politics: Themes from Kant and Arendt (New York: Rowman & Littlefield, 2001), p. 165. This is the most valuable collection on the topic.
    • (2001) Judgment, Imagination and Politics: Themes from Kant and Arendt , pp. 165
    • Wellmer, A.1
  • 5
    • 0003979560 scopus 로고
    • Other key texts on Arendt's approach to judgment include:, London: Methuen, especially ch. 6
    • Other key texts on Arendt's approach to judgment include: Ronald Beiner, Political Judgment (London: Methuen, 1983), especially ch. 6;
    • (1983) Political Judgment
    • Beiner, R.1
  • 6
    • 83455265268 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arendt's Theory of Judgment
    • Dana Villa (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Maurizio Passerin d'Entrèves, ‘Arendt's Theory of Judgment’, in Dana Villa (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Hannah Arendt (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), pp. 245–60;
    • (2000) The Cambridge Companion to Hannah Arendt , pp. 245-260
    • Passerin d'Entrèves, M.1
  • 7
    • 53249141470 scopus 로고
    • Judging in a World of Appearances: a Commentary on Hannah Arendt's Unwritten Finale
    • Ronald Beiner, Lewis and Sandra Hinchman (eds), Albany: State University of New York Press
    • Ronald Beiner, ‘Judging in a World of Appearances: a Commentary on Hannah Arendt's Unwritten Finale’, in Lewis and Sandra Hinchman (eds) Hannah Arendt: Critical Essays (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1994), pp. 365–87.
    • (1994) Hannah Arendt: Critical Essays , pp. 365-387
  • 8
    • 0012810014 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An analogy might be drawn here with Marx scholarship. When Marx scholars sought to reconstruct Marx's planned but incomplete work on law, morality and the state, a less than satisfactory approach was simply to pull together the various passages in which Marx commented on or expressed his opinions about these various issues. The more fruitful and certainly more scientific approach was to reconstruct the methodology that Marx employed in his critique of political economy and apply it, flexibly and with due regard to the shift of subject matter, to the absent critique of political philosophy. This approach has not always been done well because the thinking of Marx scholars has too often been locked within the categories of political economy, but as a mode of reconstruction it is superior to the search for Marx's scattered and situated ‘views’ on these subjects. See my own, London: Routledge, ch. 5, ‘Right and Value: the Unity of Hegel and Marx’
    • An analogy might be drawn here with Marx scholarship. When Marx scholars sought to reconstruct Marx's planned but incomplete work on law, morality and the state, a less than satisfactory approach was simply to pull together the various passages in which Marx commented on or expressed his opinions about these various issues. The more fruitful and certainly more scientific approach was to reconstruct the methodology that Marx employed in his critique of political economy and apply it, flexibly and with due regard to the shift of subject matter, to the absent critique of political philosophy. This approach has not always been done well because the thinking of Marx scholars has too often been locked within the categories of political economy, but as a mode of reconstruction it is superior to the search for Marx's scattered and situated ‘views’ on these subjects. See my own Political Investigations: Hegel, Marx, Arendt (London: Routledge, 2001), ch. 5, ‘Right and Value: the Unity of Hegel and Marx’.
    • (2001) Political Investigations: Hegel, Marx, Arendt
  • 9
    • 84997917014 scopus 로고
    • The relation to Kant is never far from the surface. Arendt writes of Kant's ‘paradoxical legacy … just as man comes of age and is declared autonomous, he is utterly debased’. She comments that this legacy is an accurate reflection of ‘the antinomical structure of human being as it is situated in the world’. The splitting of the life of the mind into the distinct ‘faculties’ of thinking, willing and judging turns out to be one aspect of the antinomical structure of human beings as we are currently situated in the world. Kant recognizes and helps to create one of modernity's major accomplishments, the autonomy of reason, but for Arendt he pays too big a price for it: the separation of reason into allegedly autonomous fields, New York: Harcourt Brace
    • The relation to Kant is never far from the surface. Arendt writes of Kant's ‘paradoxical legacy … just as man comes of age and is declared autonomous, he is utterly debased’. She comments that this legacy is an accurate reflection of ‘the antinomical structure of human being as it is situated in the world’. The splitting of the life of the mind into the distinct ‘faculties’ of thinking, willing and judging turns out to be one aspect of the antinomical structure of human beings as we are currently situated in the world. Kant recognizes and helps to create one of modernity's major accomplishments, the autonomy of reason, but for Arendt he pays too big a price for it: the separation of reason into allegedly autonomous fields. Essays in Understanding 1930–1954 (New York: Harcourt Brace, 1994), pp. 169–71.
    • (1994) Essays in Understanding 1930–1954 , pp. 169-171
  • 10
    • 84882214457 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Evil and Plurality: Hannah Arendt's Way to The Life of the Mind I
    • Cited in, Larry May and Jerome Kohn (eds), Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
    • Cited in Jerome Kohn, ‘Evil and Plurality: Hannah Arendt's Way to The Life of the Mind I’, in Larry May and Jerome Kohn (eds) Hannah Arendt: Twenty Years Later (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1997), p. 163.
    • (1997) Hannah Arendt: Twenty Years Later , pp. 163
    • Kohn, J.1
  • 11
    • 0001807516 scopus 로고
    • Interpretive Essay
    • writes: ‘It is not merely that the already completed accounts of two mental faculties were to be supplemented by a yet-to-be-provided third but, rather, that those two accounts themselves remain deficient without the promised synthesis in judging … So we arrive at the threshold of Judging still in search of solutions to the basic problems that impelled Arendt to write The Life of the Mind’, Chicago: Chicago University Press
    • Ronald Beiner writes: ‘It is not merely that the already completed accounts of two mental faculties were to be supplemented by a yet-to-be-provided third but, rather, that those two accounts themselves remain deficient without the promised synthesis in judging … So we arrive at the threshold of Judging still in search of solutions to the basic problems that impelled Arendt to write The Life of the Mind’ (‘Interpretive Essay’, in Hannah Arendt Lectures on Kant's Political Philosophy [Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1992]), pp. 89–90.
    • (1992) Hannah Arendt Lectures on Kant's Political Philosophy , pp. 89-90
    • Beiner, R.1
  • 12
    • 0004273060 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I find curious parallels between the structure of Life of the Mind and Arendt's earlier work On Revolution. In the latter Arendt distinguished between three moments of the revolutionary tradition: the American, the French, and the ‘lost treasure’ of town hall and council democracy that has existed on the margins of every modern revolutionary movement. At first sight, it appears that Arendt is positive about the tradition of 1776, negative about the tradition of 1789 and finds the realization of the revolutionary Idea in the lost treasure of participatory democracy. On reflection, however, we find along with Arendt that the American revolutionary tradition has its own disabling contradictions (e.g. its prioritization of private rights over rights of public participation); that the French revolutionary tradition represents a huge achievement despite the Terror (especially its formulation of the ‘constitution of liberty’); and that the ‘lost treasure’ of radical participatory democracy has far more problems than is apparent at first sight. Arendt finishes the text on this note when she calls the council system an ‘aristocratic’ form of government run by a self-constituting elite (OR 279–80). As her study of revolution unfolds, it becomes apparent that there is no ‘pure’ revolutionary tradition, no ideal form of actualization, no formula for liberation from tyranny and the constitution of liberty that does not reinstate the perplexities of foundation and new beginnings. The underlying structure of On Revolution, then, is not ‘dialectical’ or rather is dialectical only in the sense that it is a study of the development of the idea of revolution as it dissolves and produces its various particularizations. The lesson Arendt drew or seems to have drawn is not to repudiate the modern revolutionary tradition but to retain our political judgment in the midst of its perplexities. See, Harmondsworth, Penguin
    • I find curious parallels between the structure of Life of the Mind and Arendt's earlier work On Revolution. In the latter Arendt distinguished between three moments of the revolutionary tradition: the American, the French, and the ‘lost treasure’ of town hall and council democracy that has existed on the margins of every modern revolutionary movement. At first sight, it appears that Arendt is positive about the tradition of 1776, negative about the tradition of 1789 and finds the realization of the revolutionary Idea in the lost treasure of participatory democracy. On reflection, however, we find along with Arendt that the American revolutionary tradition has its own disabling contradictions (e.g. its prioritization of private rights over rights of public participation); that the French revolutionary tradition represents a huge achievement despite the Terror (especially its formulation of the ‘constitution of liberty’); and that the ‘lost treasure’ of radical participatory democracy has far more problems than is apparent at first sight. Arendt finishes the text on this note when she calls the council system an ‘aristocratic’ form of government run by a self-constituting elite (OR 279–80). As her study of revolution unfolds, it becomes apparent that there is no ‘pure’ revolutionary tradition, no ideal form of actualization, no formula for liberation from tyranny and the constitution of liberty that does not reinstate the perplexities of foundation and new beginnings. The underlying structure of On Revolution, then, is not ‘dialectical’ or rather is dialectical only in the sense that it is a study of the development of the idea of revolution as it dissolves and produces its various particularizations. The lesson Arendt drew or seems to have drawn is not to repudiate the modern revolutionary tradition but to retain our political judgment in the midst of its perplexities. See Hannah Arendt, On Revolution (Harmondsworth, Penguin, 1988).
    • (1988) On Revolution
    • Arendt, H.1
  • 13
    • 84997933177 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Judgment and the Moral Foundations of Politics
    • See, for example, Beiner and Nedelsky
    • See, for example, Seyla Benhabib, ‘Judgment and the Moral Foundations of Politics’, in Beiner and Nedelsky, Judgment, Imagination and Politics.
    • Judgment, Imagination and Politics
    • Benhabib, S.1
  • 15
    • 34249815057 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thinking and Moral Considerations
    • ed. Jerome Kohn (New York: Schocken
    • Hannah Arendt, ‘Thinking and Moral Considerations’, in Responsibility and Judgment, ed. Jerome Kohn (New York: Schocken, 2003), pp. 159–60.
    • (2003) Responsibility and Judgment , pp. 159-160
    • Arendt, H.1
  • 17
    • 65249143700 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thinking and Moral Considerations
    • Arendt, ‘Thinking and Moral Considerations’, p. 189.
    • Arendt1
  • 20
    • 65249143700 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thinking and Moral Considerations
    • Arendt, ‘Thinking and Moral Considerations’, p. 167.
    • Arendt1
  • 21
    • 65249143700 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thinking and Moral Considerations
    • Arendt, ‘Thinking and Moral Considerations’, p. 167
    • Arendt1
  • 24
    • 84998141011 scopus 로고
    • New York: Harvest, ch. 10, ‘A Classless Society’, part II
    • Hannah Arendt, The Origins of Totalitarianism (New York: Harvest, 1976), ch. 10, ‘A Classless Society’, part II, pp. 326–40.
    • (1976) The Origins of Totalitarianism , pp. 326-340
    • Arendt, H.1
  • 25
    • 0004188742 scopus 로고
    • New York: Vintage Press
    • Friedrich Nietzsche, Will to Power (New York: Vintage Press, 1969), p. 9.
    • (1969) Will to Power , pp. 9
    • Nietzsche, F.1
  • 27
    • 66549115948 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Banality of Philosophy: Arendt on Heidegger and Eichmann
    • See, May and Kohn
    • See Dana Villa, ‘The Banality of Philosophy: Arendt on Heidegger and Eichmann’, in May and Kohn, Hannah Arendt: Twenty Years Later, pp. 179–96.
    • Hannah Arendt: Twenty Years Later , pp. 179-196
    • Villa, D.1
  • 28
    • 0007083008 scopus 로고
    • What is Freedom?
    • Hannah Arendt, Penguin: Harmondsworth
    • Hannah Arendt, ‘What is Freedom?’, in Between Past and Future (Penguin: Harmondsworth, 1977), pp. 157–61.
    • (1977) Between Past and Future , pp. 157-161
  • 30
    • 84900470967 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Social Question
    • These quotations are drawn from, ch. 2, and footnote at p. 321
    • These quotations are drawn from On Revolution, ch. 2, ‘The Social Question’, pp. 73–94 and footnote at p. 321.
    • On Revolution , pp. 73-94
  • 38
    • 84997908553 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and 216. We may be reminded of Arendt's comment in her discussion of the camps to the effect that the nihilist principle of freedom that everything is permitted came to mean only that everything is possible and can be destroyed. Arendt, Origins, p. 340
    • Arendt, Life of the Mind II, pp. 207 and 216. We may be reminded of Arendt's comment in her discussion of the camps to the effect that the nihilist principle of freedom that everything is permitted came to mean only that everything is possible and can be destroyed. Arendt, Origins, p. 340.
    • Life of the Mind II , pp. 207
    • Arendt1
  • 39
    • 0003516201 scopus 로고
    • Hegel put it well: ‘Only in destroying something does this negative will have a feeling of its own existence … its actualization can only be the fury of destruction.’, ed. Allen Wood, §5 A and R (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Paradoxically, there are some interesting parallels between the respective analyses of Hegel and Arendt
    • Hegel put it well: ‘Only in destroying something does this negative will have a feeling of its own existence … its actualization can only be the fury of destruction.’ G. W. F. Hegel, Elements of the Philosophy of Right, ed. Allen Wood, §5 A and R (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991). Paradoxically, there are some interesting parallels between the respective analyses of Hegel and Arendt.
    • (1991) Elements of the Philosophy of Right
    • Hegel, G.W.F.1
  • 41
    • 84998162648 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • When I think of something, it no longer stands opposed to me as something external. I re-present it in my mind and thereby make it my own. Similarly, when I am active, I again make things my own in a practical way — by making them into objects of my will
    • writes:, §5 R
    • Hegel writes: ‘When I think of something, it no longer stands opposed to me as something external. I re-present it in my mind and thereby make it my own. Similarly, when I am active, I again make things my own in a practical way — by making them into objects of my will’ (Philosophy of Right, §5 R).
    • Philosophy of Right
    • Hegel1
  • 44
    • 0003462961 scopus 로고
    • Alessandro Ferrara has alerted me to the importance of Rudolf Makkreel's investigation of the space that separates the two extremes of pure determinant and pure reflective judgment, and of the intermediate forms of ‘oriented reflective judgment’ where the orienting factor reduces the otherwise vast range in which the search for principle might take place without pinpointing a subsuming principle. See, Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press
    • Alessandro Ferrara has alerted me to the importance of Rudolf Makkreel's investigation of the space that separates the two extremes of pure determinant and pure reflective judgment, and of the intermediate forms of ‘oriented reflective judgment’ where the orienting factor reduces the otherwise vast range in which the search for principle might take place without pinpointing a subsuming principle. See Rudolf Makkreel, Imagination and Interpretation in Kant: The Hermeneutical Import of the Critique of Judgment (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1994);
    • (1994) Imagination and Interpretation in Kant: The Hermeneutical Import of the Critique of Judgment
    • Makkreel, R.1
  • 54
    • 0036920381 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Identifying the Unprecedented: Hannah Arendt, Totalitarianism and the Critique of Sociology
    • See
    • See Peter Baehr, ‘Identifying the Unprecedented: Hannah Arendt, Totalitarianism and the Critique of Sociology’, American Sociological Review 67(6) (2002): 804–31;
    • (2002) American Sociological Review , vol.67 , Issue.6 , pp. 804-831
    • Baehr, P.1
  • 55
    • 33847332444 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of Politics and Social Science: Totalitarianism in the Dialogue of David Riesman and Hannah Arendt
    • and
    • and ‘Of Politics and Social Science: Totalitarianism in the Dialogue of David Riesman and Hannah Arendt’, European Journal of Political Theory 3(2): 191–217.
    • European Journal of Political Theory , vol.3 , Issue.2 , pp. 191-217
  • 58
    • 34250843619 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Theodicy in Jerusalem
    • See, Steven Ascheim (ed.), Berkeley: University of California Press
    • See Susan Neiman, ‘Theodicy in Jerusalem’, in Steven Ascheim (ed.) Hannah Arendt in Jerusalem (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2001), pp. 65–90.
    • (2001) Hannah Arendt in Jerusalem , pp. 65-90
    • Neiman, S.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.