메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 34, Issue 3, 2008, Pages 203-246

Rawls, equality, and democracy

Author keywords

communicative action; democracy; difference principle; distribution; equality; Immanuel Kant; John Rawls; just wants; liberal neutrality; social minimum; subordination; toleration

Indexed keywords


EID: 57749131760     PISSN: 01914537     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1177/0191453707087251     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (4)

References (49)
  • 1
    • 84998114596 scopus 로고
    • References to, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press), are identified as TJ. Page citations are to the original edition
    • References to John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), are identified as TJ. Page citations are to the original edition.
    • (1971) A Theory of Justice
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 2
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고
    • (New York: Columbia University Press), is identified as PL
    • John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993), is identified as PL.
    • (1993) Political Liberalism
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 3
    • 0003836741 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ed. Erin Kelly (Cambridge: Harvard University Press), is identified as RS
    • John Rawls, Justice as Fairness: A Restatement, ed. Erin Kelly (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2001), is identified as RS.
    • (2001) Justice as Fairness: A Restatement
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 4
    • 84949546729 scopus 로고
    • Neutrality, Process, and Rationality: Flawed Interpretations of Equal Protection
    • My listing differs in two respects from Rawls' own report (TJ, 504–5). First, Rawls adds that equality applies at the level of rule application. Roughly meaning regularity, equality requires ‘treating like cases alike’. I neglect this formal ‘rule of law’ principle because it does not relate to any controversial aspect of the substantive meaning of equality. Second, Rawls' list of three levels does not distinguish my second level, the modeling of basic equality by the structure of the original position, an issue that merits separate consideration. My primary earlier work on equality, on which this article especially in Part II draws
    • My listing differs in two respects from Rawls' own report (TJ, 504–5). First, Rawls adds that equality applies at the level of rule application. Roughly meaning regularity, equality requires ‘treating like cases alike’. I neglect this formal ‘rule of law’ principle because it does not relate to any controversial aspect of the substantive meaning of equality. Second, Rawls' list of three levels does not distinguish my second level, the modeling of basic equality by the structure of the original position, an issue that merits separate consideration. My primary earlier work on equality, on which this article especially in Part II draws, C. Edwin Baker, ‘Neutrality, Process, and Rationality: Flawed Interpretations of Equal Protection’, Texas Law Review 58 (1980): 1029–96.
    • (1980) Texas Law Review , vol.58 , pp. 1029-1096
    • Baker, C.E.1
  • 5
    • 84926271658 scopus 로고
    • Outcome Equality or Equality of Respect: The Substantive Content of Equal Protection
    • contrasts in respect to the first point above with
    • C. Edwin Baker, ‘Outcome Equality or Equality of Respect: The Substantive Content of Equal Protection’, University of Pennsylvania Law Review 131 (1983): 933–98, contrasts in respect to the first point above with.
    • (1983) University of Pennsylvania Law Review , vol.131 , pp. 933-998
    • Baker, C.E.1
  • 6
    • 0000316467 scopus 로고
    • Empty Idea of Equality
    • Peter Westen, ‘Empty Idea of Equality’, Harvard Law Review 95 (1982): 537–96.
    • (1982) Harvard Law Review , vol.95 , pp. 537-596
    • Westen, P.1
  • 7
    • 84997980541 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Grounded Universal Commitments
    • See, (MS, November 2006; obtainable from the author at University of Pennsylvania School of Law [ebaker@law.upenn.edu])
    • See C. Edwin Baker, ‘Grounded Universal Commitments’ (MS, November 2006; obtainable from the author at University of Pennsylvania School of Law [ebaker@law.upenn.edu]).
    • Baker, C.E.1
  • 8
    • 51149095135 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf., (Oxford: Oxford University Press), (distinguishing interest-based [e.g. Hobbes or Gauthier] and rights-based social contract theories)
    • Cf. Samuel Freeman, Justice and the Social Contract (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007), pp. 18 ff. (distinguishing interest-based [e.g. Hobbes or Gauthier] and rights-based social contract theories).
    • (2007) Justice and the Social Contract , pp. 18 ff
    • Freeman, S.1
  • 9
    • 84998096711 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • fully adequate scheme of equal basic liberties
    • Largely in response to a critique by, Rawls subsequently modifies this principle to refer to)
    • Largely in response to a critique by H. L. A. Hart, Rawls subsequently modifies this principle to refer to ‘fully adequate scheme of equal basic liberties’ (RS, 42).
    • RS , vol.42
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 10
    • 0007180841 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Morality, Identity, and “Constitutional Patriotism”
    • (1011–12). This point about universalism and its not being available in every form of life could justify liberals following (any persuasive) recommendations of Kantian constructivism without accepting new justifications advanced in PL. at 112–14
    • Frank I. Michelman, ‘Morality, Identity, and “Constitutional Patriotism”’, Denver University Law Review 76 (1999): 1009–28 (1011–12). This point about universalism and its not being available in every form of life could justify liberals following (any persuasive) recommendations of Kantian constructivism without accepting new justifications advanced in PL. at 112–14.
    • (1999) Denver University Law Review , vol.76 , pp. 1009-1028
    • Michelman, F.I.1
  • 11
    • 84997980541 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Grounded Universal Commitments
    • See, See also, below
    • See Baker, ‘Grounded Universal Commitments’. See also Part III, below.
    • Baker1
  • 12
    • 33645815488 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Core of the Case Against Judicial Review
    • Among democrats who accept that justice at least limits the decisions that the democratic majorities can properly make, some would have these limits found and interpreted by a judiciary, others argue that the public itself (or its elected representatives) should have sole authority to do so, while possibilities such as under-enforcement of constitutional norms give a role to each. Parties at either actual constitutional conventions or the envisioned constitutional stage of Rawls' four-stage sequence could have reason to assign interpretative authority as to some of the requirements of justice to the judiciary while leaving other requirements of justice to determination by democrat majorities
    • Among democrats who accept that justice at least limits the decisions that the democratic majorities can properly make, some would have these limits found and interpreted by a judiciary, others argue that the public itself (or its elected representatives) should have sole authority to do so, while possibilities such as under-enforcement of constitutional norms give a role to each. Parties at either actual constitutional conventions or the envisioned constitutional stage of Rawls' four-stage sequence could have reason to assign interpretative authority as to some of the requirements of justice to the judiciary while leaving other requirements of justice to determination by democrat majorities. Jeremy Waldron, ‘The Core of the Case Against Judicial Review’, Yale Law Journal 111 (2006): 1346–1406.
    • (2006) Yale Law Journal , vol.111 , pp. 1346-1406
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 13
    • 33745960206 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press)
    • Lawrence G. Sager, Justice in Plainclothes (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2004).
    • (2004) Justice in Plainclothes
    • Sager, L.G.1
  • 14
    • 84997953044 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Liberal, the Procedural, and the Contractual in Normative Constitutional Conceptions
    • (MS, ch. 2)
    • Frank I. Michelman, ‘The Liberal, the Procedural, and the Contractual in Normative Constitutional Conceptions’ (MS, 2007, ch. 2).
    • (2007)
    • Michelman, F.I.1
  • 15
    • 84998098743 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I read Rawls to relate this concern to ‘choice’ because he notes that unless the least advantaged have these political rights, the better situated may further entrench their position in the settlement of social questions)
    • I read Rawls to relate this concern to ‘choice’ because he notes that unless the least advantaged have these political rights, the better situated may further entrench their position in the settlement of social questions (TJ, 225).
    • TJ , pp. 225
  • 19
    • 0000352104 scopus 로고
    • Reply to Habermas
    • TJ, 197, n. 2. Rawls emphasized the real world side of this distinction in his reply to Habermas
    • TJ, 197, n. 2. Rawls emphasized the real world side of this distinction in his reply to Habermas. John Rawls, ‘Reply to Habermas’, Journal of Philosophy 92 (1995): 132–80.
    • (1995) Journal of Philosophy , vol.92 , pp. 132-180
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 20
    • 84997947240 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also, ed. Samuel Freeman (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)
    • See also John Rawls, Lectures on the History of Political Philosophy, ed. Samuel Freeman (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2007), p. 4.
    • (2007) Lectures on the History of Political Philosophy , pp. 4
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 21
    • 84998187175 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • it is rational for the parties to suppose that they do want a larger share, since in any case they are not compelled to accept more
    • Even if some individuals have conceptions of the good for which certain primary goods are not needed, Rawls notes that, from behind the veil of ignorance, than they want)
    • Even if some individuals have conceptions of the good for which certain primary goods are not needed, Rawls notes that, from behind the veil of ignorance, ‘it is rational for the parties to suppose that they do want a larger share, since in any case they are not compelled to accept more’ than they want (TJ, 143).
    • TJ , pp. 143
  • 22
    • 0004273805 scopus 로고
    • Seeing this point undermines a major criticism of Rawls in, (New York: Basic Books)
    • Seeing this point undermines a major criticism of Rawls in Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974).
    • (1974) Anarchy, State, and Utopia
    • Nozick, R.1
  • 23
    • 84997864826 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • At the legislative stage, however, citizens might make adjustments for excusable envy, which undermines self-respect, as something along with wealth and income to be taken into account in applying the difference principle)
    • At the legislative stage, however, citizens might make adjustments for excusable envy, which undermines self-respect, as something along with wealth and income to be taken into account in applying the difference principle (TJ, 546).
    • TJ , pp. 546
  • 24
    • 0003465228 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • G. A. Cohen, like Nozick, largely rejects the distinction in order to recommend a conclusion that is almost the distributional mirror image of Nozick's., (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)
    • G. A. Cohen, like Nozick, largely rejects the distinction in order to recommend a conclusion that is almost the distributional mirror image of Nozick's. G. A. Cohen, If You're an Egalitarian, How Come You're So Rich? (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000).
    • (2000) If You're an Egalitarian, How Come You're So Rich?
    • Cohen, G.A.1
  • 26
    • 0344885684 scopus 로고
    • Rawls on Liberty and Its Priority
    • Although my argument is structurally similar at many points to that made by Hart, it derives from a 1972 conversation with Andreas Eshete who explained the possible rationality of a distribution more egalitarian than that created by the difference principle
    • H. L. A. Hart, ‘Rawls on Liberty and Its Priority’, University of Chicago Law Review 40 (1973): 534–55. Although my argument is structurally similar at many points to that made by Hart, it derives from a 1972 conversation with Andreas Eshete who explained the possible rationality of a distribution more egalitarian than that created by the difference principle.
    • (1973) University of Chicago Law Review , vol.40 , pp. 534-555
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 27
    • 84944260367 scopus 로고
    • Contractarianism and the Scope of Justice
    • Andreas Eshete, ‘Contractarianism and the Scope of Justice’, Ethics 85 (1974): 38–49.
    • (1974) Ethics , vol.85 , pp. 38-49
    • Eshete, A.1
  • 28
    • 84925924475 scopus 로고
    • The Happy Worker: an Analysis of Educational and Occupational Differences in Determination of Job Satisfaction
    • Gruenberg argues that intrinsic rewards are more satisfying for workers than are extrinsic rewards. Although no evidence shows that workers must learn to appreciate the intrinsic satisfaction of work, they apparently often need to learn to like extrinsic rewards, learning that reduces dissonance if intrinsic rewards are not available
    • Barry Gruenberg, ‘The Happy Worker: an Analysis of Educational and Occupational Differences in Determination of Job Satisfaction’, American Journal of Sociology 86 (1980): 247–71. Gruenberg argues that intrinsic rewards are more satisfying for workers than are extrinsic rewards. Although no evidence shows that workers must learn to appreciate the intrinsic satisfaction of work, they apparently often need to learn to like extrinsic rewards, learning that reduces dissonance if intrinsic rewards are not available.
    • (1980) American Journal of Sociology , vol.86 , pp. 247-271
    • Gruenberg, B.1
  • 29
    • 51149095135 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, The matter deserves more attention but I find this development best described either as Rawls interpreting the demands of the difference principle (e.g. his engagement in the epistemic effort of determining the principle's application) or as a modification of the content or role of his two principles. It may be that he thought he was doing the first while actually doing the second
    • See Freeman, Justice and the Social Contract, pp. 102–9. The matter deserves more attention but I find this development best described either as Rawls interpreting the demands of the difference principle (e.g. his engagement in the epistemic effort of determining the principle's application) or as a modification of the content or role of his two principles. It may be that he thought he was doing the first while actually doing the second.
    • Justice and the Social Contract , pp. 102-109
    • Freeman1
  • 30
    • 0041873227 scopus 로고
    • Counting Preferences in Collective Choice Situations
    • C. Edwin Baker, ‘Counting Preferences in Collective Choice Situations’, UCLA Law Review 25 (1978): 381–416.
    • (1978) UCLA Law Review , vol.25 , pp. 381-416
    • Baker, C.E.1
  • 31
    • 0004040001 scopus 로고
    • This assertion puts aside the important difference in standards for measurement, what Sen calls the ‘space’ of equality, under the two approaches: utility in one, an index of primary goods in the other. See, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)
    • This assertion puts aside the important difference in standards for measurement, what Sen calls the ‘space’ of equality, under the two approaches: utility in one, an index of primary goods in the other. See Amartya Sen, Inequality Reexamined (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1992).
    • (1992) Inequality Reexamined
    • Sen, A.1
  • 36
    • 0003442441 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls' argument with cosmopolitans could be reconsidered if justice requires a culturally sensitive (local) just wants guarantee rather than the difference principle, whose application on a worldwide basis Freeman shows is inconsistent with Rawls' enterprise. Freeman emphasized, however, that Rawls did advocate worldwide provision of basic needs
    • Nussbaum, Women and Human Development, 2000. Rawls' argument with cosmopolitans could be reconsidered if justice requires a culturally sensitive (local) just wants guarantee rather than the difference principle, whose application on a worldwide basis Freeman shows is inconsistent with Rawls' enterprise. Freeman emphasized, however, that Rawls did advocate worldwide provision of basic needs.
    • (2000) Women and Human Development
    • Nussbaum1
  • 37
    • 0004168076 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)
    • John Rawls, The Law of Peoples (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999).
    • (1999) The Law of Peoples
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 39
    • 84997900147 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • U.S. 98
    • Bush v. Gore, 531 U.S. 98 (2000).
    • (2000) , vol.531
    • V. Gore, B.1
  • 40
    • 84997980541 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Grounded Universal Commitments
    • Baker, ‘Grounded Universal Commitments’.
    • Baker1
  • 41
    • 84998097741 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Foundations of the Possibility of Legitimate Law
    • (MS, September 2006; obtainable from the author at University of Pennsylvania School of Law [ebaker@law.upenn. edu])
    • Baker, ‘Foundations of the Possibility of Legitimate Law’ (MS, September 2006; obtainable from the author at University of Pennsylvania School of Law [ebaker@law.upenn. edu]).
    • Baker1
  • 42
    • 84998173638 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Michelman on Constitutional Democracy
    • C. Edwin Baker, ‘Michelman on Constitutional Democracy’, Tulsa L. Rev. 39 (2004): 511–46.
    • (2004) Tulsa L. Rev , vol.39 , pp. 511-546
    • Baker, C.E.1
  • 43
    • 84897726810 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Injustice and the Normative Nature of Meaning
    • C. Edwin Baker, ‘Injustice and the Normative Nature of Meaning’, Maryland Law Review 60 (2001): 578–606.
    • (2001) Maryland Law Review , vol.60 , pp. 578-606
    • Baker, C.E.1
  • 45
    • 72449122327 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)
    • Ronald Dworkin, Sovereign Virtue (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000).
    • (2000) Sovereign Virtue
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 46
    • 84997864795 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • now obviously no one can obtain everything he wants; the mere existence of other people prevents this
    • Only this restricted, hypothetical, constructed context allows the statement:, In the real world, Rawls emphasizes that ‘among our final ends are the attachments we have for persons, the interests we take in the realization of their interests, and the sense of justice’ (TJ, 494; see also 522–3; 570–1; 573), ends for which the existence of others is crucial
    • Only this restricted, hypothetical, constructed context allows the statement: ‘now obviously no one can obtain everything he wants; the mere existence of other people prevents this’ (TJ, 119). In the real world, Rawls emphasizes that ‘among our final ends are the attachments we have for persons, the interests we take in the realization of their interests, and the sense of justice’ (TJ, 494; see also 522–3; 570–1; 573), ends for which the existence of others is crucial.
    • TJ , pp. 119
  • 47
    • 84998187097 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Realm of Ends
    • nicely describes how Rawls' intense democratic sentiments lead him to substitute, for Kant's phrase. Freeman, Justice and the Social Contract
    • Samuel Freeman nicely describes how Rawls' intense democratic sentiments lead him to substitute ‘Realm of Ends’ for Kant's phrase. Freeman, Justice and the Social Contract, p. 5.
    • Freeman, S.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.