메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 20, Issue 4, 2006, Pages 455-475

Killing Soldiers

(1)  Øverland, Gerhard a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 57749128208     PISSN: 08926794     EISSN: 17477093     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/j.1747-7093.2006.00045.x     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (18)

References (31)
  • 5
    • 3142682745 scopus 로고
    • Innocence, Self-Defense, and Killing in War
    • This accords with what has labeled the “Orthodox View” in
    • This accords with what Jeff McMahan has labeled the “Orthodox View” in “Innocence, Self-Defense, and Killing in War,” Journal of Political Philosophy 2, no. 3 (1994), p. 195.
    • (1994) Journal of Political Philosophy , vol.2 , Issue.3 , pp. 195
    • McMahan, J.1
  • 6
    • 0004213898 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Harvard University Press For the view that rights are claims against others, see who argues that “most cases when we say that someone has a ”right’ to do something, we imply that it would be wrong to interfere with his doing it, or at least that some special grounds are needed for justifying any interference.”
    • For the view that rights are claims against others, see Ronald Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1977), p. 188, who argues that “most cases when we say that someone has a ”right’ to do something, we imply that it would be wrong to interfere with his doing it, or at least that some special grounds are needed for justifying any interference.”
    • (1977) Taking Rights Seriously , pp. 188
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 7
    • 0003396771 scopus 로고
    • Walter Wheeler Cook, ed. For a treatment of rights as claims and privileges, see New Haven: Yale University Press
    • For a treatment of rights as claims and privileges, see Wesley Newcomb Hohfeld, Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied in Judicial Reasoning, Walter Wheeler Cook, ed. (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1966), pp. 35–50.
    • (1966) Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied in Judicial Reasoning , pp. 35-50
    • Newcomb Hohfeld, W.1
  • 10
    • 8644284846 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Ethics of Killing in War
    • Jeff McMahan, “The Ethics of Killing in War,” Ethics 114, no. 4 (2004)
    • (2004) Ethics , vol.114 , Issue.4
    • McMahan, J.1
  • 11
    • 0041340246 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Richard Norman, Ethics, Killing and War (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995)
    • (1995) Ethics, Killing and War
    • Norman, R.1
  • 12
    • 34248063309 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Innocent Attackers and Rights of Self-Defense
    • David R. Mapel, “Innocent Attackers and Rights of Self-Defense,” Ethics & International Affairs 18, no. 1 (2004).
    • (2004) Ethics & International Affairs , vol.18 , Issue.1
    • Mapel, D.R.1
  • 14
    • 33645120997 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Beyond National Defense
    • David Rodin, “Beyond National Defense,” Ethics & International Affairs 18, no. 1 (2004), p. 95.
    • (2004) Ethics & International Affairs , vol.18 , Issue.1 , pp. 95
    • Rodin, D.1
  • 15
    • 0038079242 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New Haven: Yale University Press The right to resort to armed force in the just war tradition has been defined through seven moral concepts: just cause, competent authority, right intention, reasonable hope of success, overall proportionality of good over harm, last resort, and the goal of peace (see The observation that people can form private armies indicates that the requirement of right authority should be given up. The focus on right intention on the part of the agent is misleading as well, but is not something I take up in discussion here
    • The right to resort to armed force in the just war tradition has been defined through seven moral concepts: just cause, competent authority, right intention, reasonable hope of success, overall proportionality of good over harm, last resort, and the goal of peace (see James Turner Johnson, Morality and Contemporary Warfare [New Haven: Yale University Press, 1999], pp. 27–38). The observation that people can form private armies indicates that the requirement of right authority should be given up. The focus on right intention on the part of the agent is misleading as well, but is not something I take up in discussion here.
    • (1999) Morality and Contemporary Warfare , pp. 27-38
    • Turner Johnson, J.1
  • 17
    • 84924103577 scopus 로고
    • Self-Defense and the Problem of the Innocent Attacker
    • See
    • See Jeff McMahan, “Self-Defense and the Problem of the Innocent Attacker,” Ethics 104 (1994), p. 288.
    • (1994) Ethics , vol.104 , pp. 288
    • McMahan, J.1
  • 20
    • 59149086942 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Self-Defense Among Innocent People
    • For an earlier account of this proposal, see my
    • For an earlier account of this proposal, see my “Self-Defense Among Innocent People,” Journal of Moral Philosophy 2, no. 2 (2005).
    • (2005) Journal of Moral Philosophy , vol.2 , Issue.2
  • 24
    • 33645112429 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an opposite view, see Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • For an opposite view, see David Rodin, War and Self-Defense (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002), pp. 88–99.
    • (2002) War and Self-Defense , pp. 88-99
    • Rodin, D.1
  • 26
    • 33747680463 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Ethics of Killing in War,” and “The Basis of Moral Liability to Defensive Killing
    • As for innocent threats, there might be reasons for singling out innocent threats who ultimately have become threats through responsible actions-for instance, by taking up driving and thereby taking the risk of becoming a threat to others if one's brakes fail, and those who have done nothing to become a threat to others (see
    • As for innocent threats, there might be reasons for singling out innocent threats who ultimately have become threats through responsible actions-for instance, by taking up driving and thereby taking the risk of becoming a threat to others if one's brakes fail, and those who have done nothing to become a threat to others (see Jeff McMahan, “The Ethics of Killing in War,” and “The Basis of Moral Liability to Defensive Killing,” Philosophical Issues 15 [2005]).
    • (2005) Philosophical Issues , pp. 15
    • McMahan, J.1
  • 29
    • 85022603587 scopus 로고
    • The Individualization of Excusing Conditions
    • in Michael Louis Corrado, ed. See New York: Garland Publishing
    • See George Fletcher, “The Individualization of Excusing Conditions,” in Michael Louis Corrado, ed., Justification and Excuse in the Criminal Law (New York: Garland Publishing, 1994), p. 145.
    • (1994) Justification and Excuse in the Criminal Law , pp. 145
    • Fletcher, G.1
  • 30
    • 10644279623 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Irrelevance of Responsibility
    • in Ellen F. Paul, Fred D. Miller, and Jeffrey Paul, eds. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Roderick T. Long, “The Irrelevance of Responsibility,” in Ellen F. Paul, Fred D. Miller, and Jeffrey Paul, eds., Responsibility (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), pp. 145,125.
    • (1999) Responsibility
    • Long, R.T.1
  • 31
    • 0041340246 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Be aware that accepting that soldiers have an equal right to kill does not imply that one holds that soldiers always have a right to kill other soldiers. Necessity and proportionality may very well make it impermissible to do so. Proponents of an equal right to kill may therefore also regret that “the Iraqi army disintegrated in a chaotic retreat from Kuwait, and were mown down by Allied air strikes as they retreated. Iraqi military casualties were estimated by the U.S. Defense Intelligence Agency to be between 50,000 and 150,000”
    • Be aware that accepting that soldiers have an equal right to kill does not imply that one holds that soldiers always have a right to kill other soldiers. Necessity and proportionality may very well make it impermissible to do so. Proponents of an equal right to kill may therefore also regret that “the Iraqi army disintegrated in a chaotic retreat from Kuwait, and were mown down by Allied air strikes as they retreated. Iraqi military casualties were estimated by the U.S. Defense Intelligence Agency to be between 50,000 and 150,000” (Norman, Ethics, Killing and War, p. 202).
    • Ethics, Killing and War , pp. 202
    • Norman1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.