메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 30, Issue 1, 2006, Pages 194-221

On the agency of certain collective entities: An argument from "Normative Autonomy"

(1)  Copp, David a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 56749129500     PISSN: 03636550     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/j.1475-4975.2006.00135.x     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (101)

References (39)
  • 2
    • 0344756295 scopus 로고
    • What Collectives Are: Agency, Individualism and Legal Theory
    • I have discussed the nature of collective entities in a number of publications. I discuss collective entities in general in David Copp, "What Collectives Are: Agency, Individualism and Legal Theory," Dialogue 23 (1984): 249-69.
    • (1984) Dialogue , vol.23 , pp. 249-69
    • Copp, D.1
  • 3
    • 0010793315 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Idea of a Legitimate State
    • I discuss states in "The Idea of a Legitimate State," Philosophy and Public Affairs 28 (1999): 3-45.
    • (1999) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.28 , pp. 3-45
  • 4
    • 22544472843 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Groups with Minds of Their Own
    • ed. Frederick Schmidtt Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield
    • Philip Pettit, "Groups with Minds of Their Own," in Socializing Metaphysics: The Nature of Social Reality, ed. Frederick Schmidtt (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 2003), 167-93.
    • (2003) Socializing Metaphysics: The Nature of Social Reality , pp. 167-193
    • Pettit, P.1
  • 5
    • 79954138985 scopus 로고
    • Intentionality: Some Distinctions
    • Gilbert Harman, "Intentionality: Some Distinctions," Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1990): 607. For example, one can desire to have something that does not exist. Of course, a belief can take a necessary truth as its "object."
    • (1990) Behavioral and Brain Sciences , vol.13 , pp. 607
    • Harman, G.1
  • 6
    • 33744535501 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Against Collective Agency
    • ed. Georg Meggle (Frankfurt: Dr. Hansel-Hohenhausen Ag.)
    • Seumas Miller appears to favor an argument of this kind in his "Against Collective Agency," in Social Facts and Collective Intentionality, ed. Georg Meggle (Frankfurt: Dr. Hansel-Hohenhausen Ag., 2002), 273 98.
    • (2002) Social Facts and Collective Intentionality
    • Miller, S.1
  • 7
    • 0001618296 scopus 로고
    • Consciousness. Explanatory Inversion, and Cognitive Science
    • John Searle, "Consciousness. Explanatory Inversion, and Cognitive Science," Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1990): 585-96.
    • (1990) Behavioral and Brain Sciences , vol.13 , pp. 585-596
    • Searle, J.1
  • 8
    • 79954278209 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Consciousness, Explanatory Inversion, and Cognitive
    • Ibid, 588
    • Searle, "Consciousness, Explanatory Inversion, and Cognitive Science," 586. 10. Ibid., 588. The original was in italics.
    • Science , vol.586 , pp. 10
    • Searle1
  • 9
    • 79954186613 scopus 로고
    • See the peer commentary in Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1990): 596-632. Searle worries, for example, that we cannot give sense to the idea that an unconscious intentional state has a certain specific content unless the state can potentially be brought to consciousness as a state with that content, say as an intention that p, or a belief that p. But it is not clear how invoking the potential of bringing an intentional state to consciousness can solve the problem.
    • (1990) Behavioral and Brain Sciences , vol.13 , pp. 596-632
  • 10
    • 0029153450 scopus 로고
    • On a Confusion about a Function of Consciousness
    • Ned Block, "On a Confusion about a Function of Consciousness," Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (1995): 227 87. I am indebted to Kirk Ludwig for this reference.
    • (1995) Behavioral and Brain Sciences , vol.18 , pp. 227-287
    • Block, N.1
  • 12
    • 79954413707 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It appears that Gilbert Harman would agree that the bomb is in an intentional state. He says that a picture say, a picture of a unicorn - is an "intentional phenomenon." Harman, "Intentionality: Some Distinctions," 606.
    • Intentionality: Some Distinctions , pp. 606
    • Harman1
  • 13
    • 79954278210 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Searle says his usage of the term "intentional" is different from Harman's, but he docs not clarify. See Searle, "Who is Computing with the Brain?" 639. Kirk Ludwig pointed out. in personal correspondence, that Searle would say that if my bomb is in an intentional state, this is only "derived intentionality," since its "aboutness" is derived from the intentional states of its maker or user. Ludwig says that the connection principle is intended to be about states with "original intentionality," such as the intentions of the designer of the bomb.The issues here go beyond those I can address adequately. But note that, if Ludwig is correct, the argument from the connection principle can show at most that collectives do not have intentional states that are instances of original intentionality. They might still have states that are instances of derived intentionality. To support agency individualism, we would need a further argument, perhaps an argument with the major premise that an agent's intentional states must all be original. Note also that the distinction between original intentionality and derived intentionality will need to be subtle. It will have to put the states of the bomb on the side of derived intentionality even though its designers and users might not have intended it to explode at all. It might have been intended solely for use by bomb disposal squads in practice sessions and it might have been an accident that it was set to blow up.
    • Who is Computing with the Brain? , pp. 639
    • Searle1
  • 14
    • 0000589677 scopus 로고
    • What is Functionalism?
    • See, for example, ed. Ned Block Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • See, for example, Ned Block, "What is Functionalism?" in Readings in Philosophy of Psychology, vol. 1, ed. Ned Block (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1980). 171-84.
    • (1980) Readings in Philosophy of Psychology , vol.1 , pp. 171-184
    • Block, N.1
  • 17
    • 1542482955 scopus 로고
    • Collective Actions and Secondary Actions
    • I developed this point in David Copp, "Collective Actions and Secondary Actions," American Philosophical Quarterly 16 (1979): 177-86.
    • (1979) American Philosophical Quarterly , vol.16 , pp. 177-186
    • Copp, D.1
  • 18
    • 0001881453 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Logical Form of Action Sentences
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • I do not claim that (4) is fully adequate. I am assuming any theory of action will propose some analysis of (3) that we could use in place of (4). The formulation in the text takes ideas from several authors: Donald Davidson, "The Logical Form of Action Sentences," in his Essays on Actions and Events (New York: Oxford University Press, 2001), 105-21;
    • (2001) Essays on Actions and Events , pp. 105-21
    • Davidson, D.1
  • 19
    • 0003496589 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Carl Ginet. On Action (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990);
    • (1990) On Action
    • Ginet, C.1
  • 20
    • 0000557455 scopus 로고
    • Practical Reasoning
    • Gilbert Harman,"Practical Reasoning," Review of Metaphysics 29 (1976): 431-63;
    • (1976) Review of Metaphysics , vol.29 , pp. 431-463
    • Harman, G.1
  • 22
    • 79954140714 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Action
    • Summer Edition, ed. Edward N. Zalta, URL
    • George Wilson, "Action," The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2002 Edition), ed. Edward N. Zalta, URL: http://plato. stanrord.edu/archives/sum2002/entries/action/.
    • (2002) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
    • Wilson, G.1
  • 23
    • 0039680675 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What is a Philosophical Analysis?
    • Jeff King has proposed a theory of philosophical analysis that would allow us to say that (3) and (4) express distinct propositions even if (4) is the analysis of (3). See Jeffrey C. King, "What is a Philosophical Analysis?" Philosophical Studies 90 (1998): 155-79. Nothing in this paper turns on the difference between what I say in the text and what I would say if I were working with King's theory of analysis. King's theory is intended to handle the "paradox of analysis."
    • (1998) Philosophical Studies , vol.90 , pp. 155-79
    • King, J.C.1
  • 25
    • 3042685194 scopus 로고
    • Hobbes on Artificial Persons and Collective Actions
    • I discussed Thomas Hobbes's views about the authorization of agents in David Copp, "Hobbes on Artificial Persons and Collective Actions," The Philosophical Review 89 (1980): 579-606. I ignore cases in which a collective acts but its action is not constituted by the actions of individual persons with authority so to act on its behalf. An example might be a case in which a government acts illegally. There are various other complications that I cannot pause here to discuss.
    • (1980) The Philosophical Review , vol.89 , pp. 579-606
    • Copp, D.1
  • 26
    • 44649197264 scopus 로고
    • Theory of the Firm: Managerial Behaviour, Agency Costs and Ownership Structure
    • An argument of this kind is suggested by Michael Jensen and William Meckling, "Theory of the Firm: Managerial Behaviour, Agency Costs and Ownership Structure," Journal of Financial Economics 3 (1976): 305-60. Jensen and Meckling speak of the firm as a "legal fiction," but their argument seems rather to support the idea that although firms exist, it is gratuitous, for reasons similar to those given in the text, to suppose that they are agents. I owe this reference to David Gindis.
    • (1976) Journal of Financial Economics , vol.3 , pp. 305-60
    • Jensen, M.1    Meckling, W.2
  • 28
    • 79954166047 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Here and in what follows, I follow 43 52
    • Here and in what follows, I follow Pettit, The Common Mind, 24 32, 43 52.
    • The Common Mind , vol.24 , pp. 32
    • Pettit1
  • 30
    • 0003742241 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Blackwell
    • For an explanation and defense of nonreductive analysis, see Michael Smith, The Moral Problem (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994), 44-54.
    • (1994) The Moral Problem , pp. 44-54
    • Smith, M.1
  • 31
    • 33749315326 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Conceptual Analysis, Circularity, and the Commitments of Fhysiclism
    • Gene Witmer has defended "the possibility and fruit-fulness" of certain kinds of circular conceptual analyses. See his "Conceptual Analysis, Circularity, and the Commitments of Fhysiclism." Acta Analytica 16 (2001): 119-33.
    • (2001) Acta Analytica , vol.16 , pp. 119-33
  • 32
    • 79954263571 scopus 로고
    • Persons as Corporate Entities and Corporations as Persons
    • See John I. Biro, "Persons as Corporate Entities and Corporations as Persons," Nature and System 3 (1981): 173-80.
    • (1981) Nature and System , vol.3 , pp. 173-180
    • Biro, J.I.1
  • 33
    • 22544472843 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and throughout
    • For the distinction between premise-centered and conclusion-centered procedures, see Pettit, "Groups with Minds of Their Own," 168 and throughout.
    • Groups with Minds of Their Own , pp. 168
    • Pettit1
  • 34
    • 33644764311 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Discursive Dilemma and Public Reason
    • The example is from Christian List, "The Discursive Dilemma and Public Reason," Ethics 116 (2006): 352-402.
    • (2006) Ethics , vol.116 , pp. 352-402
    • List, C.1
  • 36
    • 61049413796 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Collectivist Approach to Collective Moral Responsibility
    • 51
    • Pettit's argument has been criticized by Seumas Miller and Pekka Makela in "The Collectivist Approach to Collective Moral Responsibility," Metaphilosophy 36 (2005): 634 51. Their objections appear to turn on arguments of the kind I discussed in section 2.1.
    • (2005) Metaphilosophy , vol.36 , pp. 634
    • Miller, S.1    Makela, P.2
  • 37
    • 0003729213 scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • Russell Hardin presents an example of collective normative autonomy in Morality within the Limits of Reason (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988), 156-58.
    • (1988) Morality within the Limits of Reason , pp. 156-58
    • Hardin, R.1
  • 38
    • 79954329134 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • have argued
    • His example concerns an unorganized group that fails to do something-in his example, a group of people riding on a bus fail to help someone - rather than an institutional group with a collective decision procedure. He does not explicitly take account of excuses that the individuals on the bus might have had for failing to act. Miller and Makela have argued, in "The Collectivist Approach to Collective Moral Responsibility," that Hardin's example is not successful. But they do not consider slightly modified examples in which each of the bus riders has an excuse or justification for failing to act.
    • The Collectivist Approach to Collective Moral Responsibility
    • Miller1    Makela2
  • 39
    • 79954089345 scopus 로고
    • Individuals
    • PhD dissertation, Cornell University 80
    • I present additional examples of collective normative autonomy in David Copp, Individuals, Collectives and Moral Agency (PhD dissertation, Cornell University, 1976), 166 80.
    • (1976) Collectives and Moral Agency , pp. 166
    • Copp, D.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.