-
2
-
-
0004048289
-
-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), 26-27.
-
(1971)
A Theory of Justice
, pp. 26-27
-
-
Rawls, J.1
-
4
-
-
0003992022
-
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
Thomas Nagel, The Possibility of Altruism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1970), 134.
-
(1970)
The Possibility of Altruism
, pp. 134
-
-
Nagel, T.1
-
6
-
-
0003740191
-
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
Derek Parfit, Reasons and Persons (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984), 346.
-
(1984)
Reasons and Persons
, pp. 346
-
-
Parfit, D.1
-
7
-
-
56749147695
-
Against Maximizing Act Consequentialism
-
James Dreier, ed, Oxford: Blackwell, emphasis in the original
-
Peter Vallentyne, "Against Maximizing Act Consequentialism," in James Dreier, ed., Contemporary Debates in Moral Theory (Oxford: Blackwell, 2006), 29; emphasis in the original.
-
(2006)
Contemporary Debates in Moral Theory
, pp. 29
-
-
Vallentyne, P.1
-
8
-
-
56749127406
-
-
For those unfamiliar with the Promise Keeper phenomenon in the United States, a little explanation is in order. The Promise Keepers is an evangelical Christian organization for men. It teaches, among other things, that within marriage the man should be the head of the household and the woman should willingly submit to his leadership. The organization has been criticized by feminist groups in the U.S., such as the National Organization for Women, for (allegedly) encouraging inequality within marriages and teaching male superiority. Such, doctrines rarely receive a sympathetic hearing in Women's Studies classes.
-
For those unfamiliar with the Promise Keeper phenomenon in the United States, a little explanation is in order. The Promise Keepers is an evangelical Christian organization for men. It teaches, among other things, that within marriage the man should be the head of the household and the woman should willingly submit to his leadership. The organization has been criticized by feminist groups in the U.S., such as the National Organization for Women, for (allegedly) encouraging inequality within marriages and teaching male superiority. Such, doctrines rarely receive a sympathetic hearing in Women's Studies classes.
-
-
-
-
9
-
-
0017502091
-
Should the Numbers Count?
-
See
-
See John Taurek, "Should the Numbers Count?" Philosophy and Public Affairs 6 (1977): 293-316.
-
(1977)
Philosophy and Public Affairs
, vol.6
, pp. 293-316
-
-
Taurek, J.1
-
10
-
-
0007279324
-
Utilitarianism and the Virtues
-
See
-
See Philippa Foot, "Utilitarianism and the Virtues," Mind 94 (1985): 196-209.
-
(1985)
Mind
, vol.94
, pp. 196-209
-
-
Foot, P.1
-
11
-
-
4243348188
-
The Right and the Good
-
See
-
See Judith Jarvis Thomson, "The Right and the Good," The Journal of Philosophy 94, no. 6 (1997): 273-98.
-
(1997)
The Journal of Philosophy
, vol.94
, Issue.6
, pp. 273-298
-
-
Jarvis Thomson, J.1
-
12
-
-
56749135696
-
-
Taurek argues for the radical thesis that there is no moral reason to prefer the death of one person over the deaths of five persons (or even of five million persons, Foot argues that no sense can be made of one state of affairs being overall better than another from the perspective of morality. Foot's position seems to be in agreement with Taurek's in the following sense: it rejects the claim that I have a moral reason to prefer the death of one to the deaths of five, if that reason is supposed to be grounded in the claim that it is overall better that only one person dies than that five persons die. Thomson's position is less clear. She criticizes utilitarianism for its reliance on comparative judgments of the goodness of states of affairs, and in this respect seems to be sympathetic to Foot's position. However, a charitable reading of her essay (which she would no doubt reject) renders it as a defense of rule utilitarianism
-
Taurek argues for the radical thesis that there is no moral reason to prefer the death of one person over the deaths of five persons (or even of five million persons). Foot argues that no sense can be made of one state of affairs being overall better than another from the perspective of morality. Foot's position seems to be in agreement with Taurek's in the following sense: it rejects the claim that I have a moral reason to prefer the death of one to the deaths of five, if that reason is supposed to be grounded in the claim that it is overall better that only one person dies than that five persons die. Thomson's position is less clear. She criticizes utilitarianism for its reliance on comparative judgments of the goodness of states of affairs, and in this respect seems to be sympathetic to Foot's position. However, a charitable reading of her essay (which she would no doubt reject) renders it as a defense of rule utilitarianism.
-
-
-
-
13
-
-
56749124496
-
-
I leave the reader to fill in the details of this and other examples involving the endlessly fascinating inhabitants of Springfield
-
I leave the reader to fill in the details of this and other examples involving the endlessly fascinating inhabitants of Springfield.
-
-
-
-
14
-
-
0003867020
-
-
See, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
See Thomas Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998).
-
(1998)
What We Owe to Each Other
-
-
Scanlon, T.1
-
15
-
-
85050789732
-
Contractualism and Aggregation
-
For a more comprehensive critique of Scanlon's attempts to accommodate limited aggregation, see
-
For a more comprehensive critique of Scanlon's attempts to accommodate limited aggregation, see Alastair Norcross, "Contractualism and Aggregation," Social Theory and Practice 28, no. 2 (2002): 303-14.
-
(2002)
Social Theory and Practice
, vol.28
, Issue.2
, pp. 303-314
-
-
Norcross, A.1
-
17
-
-
56749124497
-
-
For examples of the attempt to deny transitivity for all-things- considered better than, see Larry Temkin, Intransitivity and the Mere Addition Paradox, Philosophy and Public Affairs 16 1987, 138-87;
-
For examples of the attempt to deny transitivity for "all-things- considered better than," see Larry Temkin, "Intransitivity and the Mere Addition Paradox," Philosophy and Public Affairs 16 (1987): 138-87;
-
-
-
-
18
-
-
1042287762
-
A Continuum Argument for Intransitivity
-
Larry Temkin, "A Continuum Argument for Intransitivity," Philosophy and Public Affairs 25 (1.996): 175-210;
-
Philosophy and Public Affairs
, vol.25
, Issue.1 .996
, pp. 175-210
-
-
Temkin, L.1
-
19
-
-
0346763532
-
The Puzzle of the Self-Torturer
-
Warren Quinn, "The Puzzle of the Self-Torturer," Philosophical Studies 59 (1990): 79-90;
-
(1990)
Philosophical Studies
, vol.59
, pp. 79-90
-
-
Quinn, W.1
-
20
-
-
22544472841
-
Counterexamples to the Transitivity of 'Better Than', Australasian
-
and Stuart Rachels, "Counterexamples to the Transitivity of 'Better Than'," Australasian Journal of Philosophy 76, no. 1 (1998): 71-83.
-
(1998)
Journal of Philosophy
, vol.76
, Issue.1
, pp. 71-83
-
-
Rachels, S.1
-
21
-
-
56749113777
-
-
Temkin's 1996 article uses the same central example as Rachels's article, but Temkin's explanation for the supposed intransitivity is the same as the one he provides in his 1987 article. Quinn does not explicitly claim that better than is intransitive, but his arguments, if successful, entail that a utilitarian should deny the transitivity of better than. I discuss Temkin's 1987 article in Alastair Norcross, Intransitivity and the Person-Affecting Principle, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 59, no. 3 (1999): 769-761
-
Temkin's 1996 article uses the same central example as Rachels's article, but Temkin's explanation for the supposed intransitivity is the same as the one he provides in his 1987 article. Quinn does not explicitly claim that "better than" is intransitive, but his arguments, if successful, entail that a utilitarian should deny the transitivity of "better than." I discuss Temkin's 1987 article in Alastair Norcross, "Intransitivity and the Person-Affecting Principle," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 59, no. 3 (1999): 769-761
-
-
-
-
22
-
-
0012286960
-
-
discuss Temkin's 1996 article and Quinn's 1990 article in Alastair Norcross, Comparing Harms: Headaches and Human Lives, Philosophy and Public Affairs 26 (1997): 135-67.
-
discuss Temkin's 1996 article and Quinn's 1990 article in Alastair Norcross, "Comparing Harms: Headaches and Human Lives," Philosophy and Public Affairs 26 (1997): 135-67.
-
-
-
-
23
-
-
56749135697
-
-
Confusingly, deontology is also the catch-all name for the most common family of anticonsequentialist moral theories. This is confusing because, understood as the study of duty, deontology also encompasses most versions of consequentialism, which do, after all, provide an account of moral duty.
-
Confusingly, "deontology" is also the catch-all name for the most common family of anticonsequentialist moral theories. This is confusing because, understood as the study of duty, deontology also encompasses most versions of consequentialism, which do, after all, provide an account of moral duty.
-
-
-
-
24
-
-
56749140222
-
Aggregating Harms-Should We Kill to Avoid Headaches?
-
See
-
See Erik Carlson, "Aggregating Harms-Should We Kill to Avoid Headaches?" Theoria 66, no. 3 (2000): 246-55.
-
(2000)
Theoria
, vol.66
, Issue.3
, pp. 246-255
-
-
Carlson, E.1
-
25
-
-
53249095716
-
Rights Violations and Distributive Constraints: Three Scenarios
-
See
-
See Alastair Norcross, "Rights Violations and Distributive Constraints: Three Scenarios," The Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 76, no. 2 (1995): 159-67.
-
(1995)
The Pacific Philosophical Quarterly
, vol.76
, Issue.2
, pp. 159-167
-
-
Norcross, A.1
-
26
-
-
56749087308
-
-
Thomson's argument appears in Judith Jarvis Thomson, The Realm of Rights (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990), 166-67. Thomson claims that we may be justified in violating certain rights, if the violation produces enough good, but only so long as the good produced is distributed appropriately. In particular, the good cannot be the sum of very tiny increments of good for a large number of people. Thomson describes this as the thesis that where claims are concerned, the sum of goods across people does not count.... In still shorter form, where claims are concerned, the numbers do not count.
-
Thomson's argument appears in Judith Jarvis Thomson, The Realm of Rights (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990), 166-67. Thomson claims that we may be justified in violating certain rights, if the violation produces enough good, but only so long as the good produced is distributed appropriately. In particular, the good cannot be the sum of very tiny increments of good for a large number of people. Thomson describes this as the thesis that "where claims are concerned, the sum of goods across people does not count.... In still shorter form, where claims are concerned, the numbers do not count."
-
-
-
-
27
-
-
56749171928
-
-
For detailed discussion of both these points, see
-
For detailed discussion of both these points, see Norcross, "Comparing Harms."
-
Comparing Harms
-
-
Norcross1
-
28
-
-
0013116949
-
Killing and Letting Die
-
reprinted in and, eds, 2d ed, New York: Fordham University Press
-
philippa Foot, "Killing and Letting Die," reprinted in Bonnie Steinbock and Alastair Norcross, eds., Killing and Letting Die, 2d ed. (New York: Fordham University Press, 1994), 280-89.
-
(1994)
Killing and Letting Die
, pp. 280-289
-
-
philippa Foot1
-
29
-
-
56749119373
-
-
For insomniacs, Foot's versions are titled Rescue I and Rescue II. In Rescue I, we can save either five people in danger of drowning in one place or one person drowning somewhere else. In Rescue II, we can save the five drowning people only by driving over and killing someone who is trapped on the road. They appear in Foot, Killing and Letting Die.
-
For insomniacs, Foot's versions are titled "Rescue I" and "Rescue II." In Rescue I, we can save either five people in danger of drowning in one place or one person drowning somewhere else. In Rescue II, we can save the five drowning people only by driving over and killing someone who is trapped on the road. They appear in Foot, "Killing and Letting Die."
-
-
-
-
31
-
-
0009389322
-
-
See, for example, New York: Clarendon Press
-
See, for example, Jonathan Bennett, The Act Itself (New York: Clarendon Press, 1995);
-
(1995)
The Act Itself
-
-
Bennett, J.1
-
32
-
-
0006798433
-
-
Steinbock and Norcross, eds
-
Steinbock and Norcross, eds., Killing and Letting Die;
-
Killing and Letting Die
-
-
-
33
-
-
84958614163
-
-
and Alastair Norcross, Killing and Letting Die, in R. G. Frey and C. H. Wellman, eds., The Blackwell Companion to Applied Ethics (Maiden, MA: Blackwell Publishing, 2003), 451-63.
-
and Alastair Norcross, "Killing and Letting Die," in R. G. Frey and C. H. Wellman, eds., The Blackwell Companion to Applied Ethics (Maiden, MA: Blackwell Publishing, 2003), 451-63.
-
-
-
-
34
-
-
56749121479
-
-
See my The Road to Hell, unpublished manuscript, latest draft available on my Web site (http://spot.colorado.edu/~norcross/).
-
See my "The Road to Hell," unpublished manuscript, latest draft available on my Web site (http://spot.colorado.edu/~norcross/).
-
-
-
-
35
-
-
56749090198
-
-
To say that a distinction is aretaically relevant is to say that it is relevant to a moral evaluation of character. The Greek word arete is usually translated as virtue
-
To say that a distinction is aretaically relevant is to say that it is relevant to a moral evaluation of character. The Greek word "arete" is usually translated as "virtue."
-
-
-
-
36
-
-
34249760616
-
-
It may be possible to construct a consequentialist theory that is sensitive to this distinction see Alastair Norcross, Should Utilitarianism Accommodate Moral Dilemmas? Philosophical Studies 79, no. 1 [1995, 59-83, but I know of no one who embraces such a theory
-
It may be possible to construct a consequentialist theory that is sensitive to this distinction (see Alastair Norcross, "Should Utilitarianism Accommodate Moral Dilemmas?" Philosophical Studies 79, no. 1 [1995]: 59-83), but I know of no one who embraces such a theory.
-
-
-
-
37
-
-
84921353862
-
-
There are, of course, other suggested nonconsequentialist constraints on maximizing the good. For impressively intricate examples, see, Oxford: Oxford University Press, esp. chap. 5;
-
There are, of course, other suggested nonconsequentialist constraints on maximizing the good. For impressively intricate examples, see Frances Kamm, Intricate Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007), esp. chap. 5;
-
(2007)
Intricate Ethics
-
-
Kamm, F.1
-
38
-
-
56749117270
-
-
and for criticisms of some of them, see Alastair Norcross, Off Her Trolley? Frances Kamm and the Metaphysics of Morality, Utilitas 20, no. 1 (2008): 65-80. I do not mean to suggest in the current essay that the two (or three, if we include the putative deontic significance of intentions) dogmas that I have focused on exhaust the disagreement between consequentialists and their opponents. My claim is that the dogmas I have discussed are the most central to the separateness of persons dogma.
-
and for criticisms of some of them, see Alastair Norcross, "Off Her Trolley? Frances Kamm and the Metaphysics of Morality," Utilitas 20, no. 1 (2008): 65-80. I do not mean to suggest in the current essay that the two (or three, if we include the putative deontic significance of intentions) dogmas that I have focused on exhaust the disagreement between consequentialists and their opponents. My claim is that the dogmas I have discussed are the most central to the separateness of persons dogma.
-
-
-
|