메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 38, Issue 2, 2007, Pages 274-291

Immigrant admissions and global relations of harm

(1)  Wilcox, Shelley a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 56349099133     PISSN: 00472786     EISSN: 14679833     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/j.1467-9833.2007.00379.x     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (34)

References (41)
  • 2
    • 0001988772 scopus 로고
    • Aliens and citizens: The case for open borders
    • ed. Ronald Beiner Albany, NY: State University of New York Press
    • See Joseph Carens, "Aliens and Citizens: The Case for Open Borders," in Theorizing Citizenship, ed. Ronald Beiner (Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 1995), 229-54
    • (1995) Theorizing Citizenship , pp. 229-254
    • Carens, J.1
  • 3
    • 0012632307 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Migration and morality: A liberal egalitarian perspective
    • originally published University Park: The Pennsylvania State Press
    • (originally published in 1987) and "Migration and Morality: A Liberal Egalitarian Perspective," in Free Movement: Ethical Issues in the Transnational Migration of People and of Money, ed. Brian Barry and Robert E. Goodin (University Park: The Pennsylvania State Press, 1992), 25-47.
    • (1987) Free Movement: Ethical issues in the Transnational Migration of People and of Money , pp. 25-47
    • Barry, B.1    Goodin, R.E.2
  • 4
    • 85050412119 scopus 로고
    • The civil right we are not yet ready for: The right of free movement of people on the face of the earth
    • For alternative formulations of the freedom of movement argument, see Roger Nett, "The Civil Right We Are Not Yet Ready For: The Right of Free Movement of People on the Face of the Earth," Ethics 81, no. 3 (1970): 212-27;
    • (1970) Ethics , vol.81 , Issue.3 , pp. 212-227
    • Nett, R.1
  • 6
    • 84888634829 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • International Organization for Migration, URL: http://www.iom.int/jahia/ page254.html.
  • 8
    • 0012632307 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Carens forgoes specifically Rawlsian concepts in subsequent versions of the freedom of movement argument, arguing instead that freedom of international movement, including the right to immigrate, is entailed by general liberal egalitarian values, such as human freedom, autonomy, and equal opportunity. Carens, "Migration and Morality," 25-47. Interestingly, Article 13 of the United Nations Universal Declaration of Human Rights stipulates the right to freedom of movement and residence within the borders of one's country of citizenship, together with the right to leave and return to one's country, and Article 14 specifies the right to seek asylum in other countries. However, the Declaration includes neither a general right to freedom of international movement nor a right to immigrate to the country of one's choosing.
    • Migration and Morality , pp. 25-47
    • Carens1
  • 9
    • 77954271056 scopus 로고
    • Commentary: Liberalism and migration
    • ed. Brian Barry and Robert E. Goodin University Park: The Pennsylvania State Press
    • James Woodward, "Commentary: Liberalism and Migration," in Free Movement: Ethical Issues in the Transnational Migration of People and of Money, ed. Brian Barry and Robert E. Goodin (University Park: The Pennsylvania State Press, 1992), 61. One could object that privileging the neediest prospective immigrants is consistent with equal treatment insofar as immigration is a legitimate means for fulfilling basic subsistence rights. However, this objection is not available to the proponent of the freedom of movement argument because the argument construes the right to immigrate as a negative right.
    • (1992) Free Movement: Ethical issues in the Transnational Migration of People and of Money , pp. 61
    • Woodward, J.1
  • 10
    • 0003564681 scopus 로고
    • Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press
    • The Harm Principle originates in John Stuart Mill's On Liberty. Roughly stated, Mill argues that a state may coercively interfere in the liberty of individuals only if it can thereby prevent harm to others. While Mill provides a utilitarian justification for the Harm Principle, other liberals defend it on alternative, including deontological, grounds. For instance, see H. L. A. Hart, Law Liberty, and Morality (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1963).
    • (1963) Law Liberty, and Morality
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 14
    • 33750498195 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Applying the contribution principle
    • This account draws upon the work of philosophers engaged in the project of developing a comprehensive theory of collective responsibility, including the following. Christian Barry, "Applying the Contribution Principle," Metaphilosophy 36, no. 1/2 (2005): 210-27.
    • (2005) Metaphilosophy , vol.36 , Issue.1-2 , pp. 210-227
    • Barry, C.1
  • 16
    • 33748499961 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Severe poverty as a violation of negative duties
    • and "Severe Poverty as a Violation of Negative Duties," Ethics & International Affairs 19, no. 1 (2005): 55-83.
    • (2005) Ethics & International Affairs , vol.19 , Issue.1 , pp. 55-83
  • 19
    • 84888610036 scopus 로고
    • Harm to others
    • and H. L. A Hart and Tony Honoré 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Ialso draw upon classical work on legal causal responsibility, particularly Feinberg, Harm to Others, and H. L. A Hart and Tony Honoré, Causation in the Law, 2nd ed. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1985).
    • (1985) Causation in the Law
    • Feinberg1
  • 20
    • 84888593838 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In Barry's words, "A's conduct did not merely allow a causal sequence that had antecedently put B under threat of acute deprivation to play out, but rather initiated, facilitated, or sustained it." See Barry, "Applying the Contribution Principle," 212.
    • Applying the Contribution Principle , pp. 212
    • Barry1
  • 23
    • 34248043363 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What do we owe the global poor?
    • Although there are controversies concerning the extent to which agents are accountable for the actions of others, this general account of collective democratic accountability is widely endorsed. See also Satz, "What Do We Owe the Global Poor?" Ethics & International Affairs 19, no. 1 (2005): 50.
    • (2005) Ethics & International Affairs , vol.19 , Issue.1 , pp. 50
    • Satz1
  • 32
    • 84937380572 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A feminist critique of the alleged southern debt
    • For instance, Alison Jaggar argues that the structural adjustment policies implemented by the World Bank and WTO have foreseeably and avoidably contributed to a global feminization of poverty, producing serious human rights deficits for many women and children. See Alison Jaggar, "A Feminist Critique of the Alleged Southern Debt," Hypatia 17, no. 4 (2002): 119-42.
    • (2002) Hypatia , vol.17 , Issue.4 , pp. 119-142
    • Jaggar, A.1
  • 33
    • 0036893993 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Compensatory justice: Over time and between groups
    • This account underlies modern tort law. For a helpful discussion of this and several other accounts of compensatory justice, see Renée A. Hill, "Compensatory Justice: Over Time and Between Groups," Journal of Political Philosophy 10, no. 4 (2002): 392-415.
    • (2002) Journal of Political Philosophy , vol.10 , Issue.4 , pp. 392-415
    • Hill, R.A.1
  • 34
    • 1642433698 scopus 로고
    • Compensation and the bounds of rights
    • ed. John W. Chapman New York: New York University Press
    • Loran Lomasky defends this interpretation. See Loran Lomasky, "Compensation and the Bounds of Rights," in NOMOS XXXIII: Compensatory Justice, ed. John W. Chapman (New York: New York University Press, 1991), 13-44.
    • (1991) NOMOS XXXIII: Compensatory Justice , pp. 13-44
    • Lomasky, L.1
  • 35
    • 80054851528 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • American neo-nativism and gendered immigrant exclusions
    • ed. Barbara Andrew, Jean Keller, and Lisa Schwartzman Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield
    • See Shelley Wilcox, "American Neo-Nativism and Gendered Immigrant Exclusions," in Feminist Interventions: Feminist Ethics and Social Theory, ed. Barbara Andrew, Jean Keller, and Lisa Schwartzman (Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 2005), 213-32.
    • (2005) Feminist Interventions: Feminist Ethics and Social Theory , pp. 213-232
    • Wilcox, S.1
  • 37
    • 0342312704 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Membership and morality: Admission to citizenship in liberal democratic states
    • ed. William Brubaker Lanham, MD: University Press of America
    • Joseph Carens, "Membership and Morality: Admission to Citizenship in Liberal Democratic States," in Immigration and the Politics of Citizenship in Europe and North America, ed. William Brubaker (Lanham, MD: University Press of America, 1989), 31-50.
    • (1989) Immigration and the Politics of Citizenship in Europe and North America , pp. 31-50
    • Carens, J.1
  • 41
    • 85045161807 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Culture, national identity, and admission to citizenship
    • For a full defense of this view, see Shelley Wilcox, "Culture, National Identity, and Admission to Citizenship," Social Theory and Practice 30, no. 4 (2004): 559-83.
    • (2004) Social Theory and Practice , vol.30 , Issue.4 , pp. 559-583
    • Wilcox, S.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.