메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 123, Issue 1-2, 2005, Pages 149-173

Harming in context

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 55449133318     PISSN: 00318116     EISSN: 15730883     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1007/s11098-004-5220-3     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (63)

References (16)
  • 1
    • 55449121488 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I owe the example to Frances Howard-Snyder.
  • 2
    • 55449100632 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • An asymmetry between reasons not to harm and reasons to benefit is also implausible from a non-consequentialist perspective that treats harms in certain respects as more basic than overall harms. Consider an approach to harm that classifies causing pain (among other things) as harming, and preventing pain as benefiting, and that claims that our reasons not to harm are stronger than our reasons to benefit. Such an approach may well, depending on the size of the supposed asymmetry between reasons, judge that Doctor has stronger reason not to administer the pain-relieving drugs than to administer them. This should clearly be unacceptable to non-consequentialists as well as consequentialists.
  • 4
    • 55449091009 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Parfit doesn't use the term 'preemption'.
  • 6
    • 55449109025 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • It might be objected that my elaboration of the example prevents Y's true belief in the actual world that X has poisoned me from being knowledge. If the closest world in which X doesn't poison me is one in which Y believes that X has poisoned me, it seems that Y's actual belief doesn't track the truth in the right way to be knowledge. This objection relies on a controversial theory of knowledge. It's not even clear that it succeeds in the context of that theory. Given that the contexts in which we consider whether Y has knowledge and in which we consider whether Y is a member of the group that harms me are different, different possible worlds may be relevant to each. Furthermore, if we simply changed Case Three to specify either that Y simply believes that I am about to die painfully, or that Y knows that it is almost certain that I am about to die painfully, our intuitive judgements of Y's behavior would remain unchanged.
  • 7
    • 33645862084 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Which Effects?
    • ed. Jonathan Dancy, Blackwell
    • Frank Jackson makes a similar point in his "Which Effects?", in Reading Parfit, ed. Jonathan Dancy, Blackwell 1997.
    • (1997) Reading Parfit
    • Jackson, F.1
  • 8
    • 0012286960 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Comparing Harms: Headaches and Human Lives
    • Spring
    • See my "Comparing Harms: Headaches and Human Lives", Philosophy and Public Affairs, Spring 1997, for arguments against this view.
    • (1997) Philosophy and Public Affairs
  • 9
    • 55449109880 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This approach can be subject to many variations. For example, do we compare (C1) and (C2) with respect to a particular person, a particular type of person, the "average" person, etc.? Do we compare propensities with respect to the circumstances a particular individual is likely to encounter, given what we know about her, given her social position, given "normal" circumstances, etc.?
  • 10
    • 34547508544 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Consequentialism and Commitment
    • December
    • For discussion of this point see my "Consequentialism and Commitment", Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, December 1997.
    • (1997) Pacific Philosophical Quarterly
  • 11
    • 55449098899 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, for example, the accounts of counterfactuals developed by David Lewis and Robert Stalnaker
    • See, for example, the accounts of counterfactuals developed by David Lewis and Robert Stalnaker.
  • 12
    • 55449084080 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The problem here is both that the proposal makes character relevant to whether actions harm or benefit, and that it does so in a particularly counterintuitive way. For a consequentialist, the former problem is more significant.
  • 13
    • 55449106432 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I mean by salience, roughly, the degree to which the participants in a conversational context consciously focus on an alternative. There may be more sophisticated accounts of salience, but this is certainly a common one.
  • 14
    • 55449089582 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I owe at least the general idea of this example, though not the details, to Ben Bradley. He suggested something like this in discussion as a problem for my account.
  • 15
    • 55449090437 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I owe thes suggestion to Julia Driver.
  • 16
    • 55449093037 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I am grateful for comments on various versions of this paper by Jonathan Bennett, Ben Bradley, Julia Driver, Doug Ehring, Mark Heller, Frances Howard-Snyder, Elinor Mason, Stuart Rachels, George Sher, Steve Sverdlik, and an anonymous referee for this journal.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.