메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 93, Issue 6, 2008, Pages 1413-1436

Legal ethics as "political moralism" or the morality of politics

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 54549113362     PISSN: 00108847     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (16)

References (158)
  • 1
    • 54549101948 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DAVID LUBAN, LAWYERS AND JUSTICE: AN ETHICAL STUDY (1988) [hereinafter LUBAN, LAWYERS AND JUSTICE].
    • DAVID LUBAN, LAWYERS AND JUSTICE: AN ETHICAL STUDY (1988) [hereinafter LUBAN, LAWYERS AND JUSTICE].
  • 2
    • 54549083051 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 125.
    • See id. at 125.
  • 3
    • 54549083047 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 186, 233.
    • See id. at 186, 233.
  • 4
    • 84929732990 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DAVID LUBAN, LEGAL ETHICS AND HUMAN DIGNITY 9 (2007) [hereinafter LUBAN, LEGAL ETHICS AND HUMAN DIGNITY].
    • DAVID LUBAN, LEGAL ETHICS AND HUMAN DIGNITY 9 (2007) [hereinafter LUBAN, LEGAL ETHICS AND HUMAN DIGNITY].
  • 5
    • 54549104527 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 9-11.
    • See id. at 9-11.
  • 6
    • 54549101950 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 7-8.
    • See id. at 7-8.
  • 8
    • 54549104531 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See DAVID LUBAN, Contrived Ignorance, in LUBAN, LEGAL ETHICS AND HUMAN DIGNITY, supra note 4, at 209, 209 [hereinafter LUBAN, Contrived Ignorance].
    • See DAVID LUBAN, Contrived Ignorance, in LUBAN, LEGAL ETHICS AND HUMAN DIGNITY, supra note 4, at 209, 209 [hereinafter LUBAN, Contrived Ignorance].
  • 9
    • 54549083048 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See DAVID LUBAN, The Ethics of Wrongful Obedience, in LUBAN, LEGAL ETHICS AND HUMAN DIGNITY, supra note 4, at 237, 238-39 [hereinafter LUBAN, Wrongful Obedience].
    • See DAVID LUBAN, The Ethics of Wrongful Obedience, in LUBAN, LEGAL ETHICS AND HUMAN DIGNITY, supra note 4, at 237, 238-39 [hereinafter LUBAN, Wrongful Obedience].
  • 10
    • 54549084249 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See DAVID LUBAN, The Torture Lawyers of Washington, in LUBAN, LEGAL ETHICS AND HUMAN DIGNITY, supra note 4, at 162, 162, 172-73 [hereinafter LUBAN, Torture Lawyers].
    • See DAVID LUBAN, The Torture Lawyers of Washington, in LUBAN, LEGAL ETHICS AND HUMAN DIGNITY, supra note 4, at 162, 162, 172-73 [hereinafter LUBAN, Torture Lawyers].
  • 11
    • 54549104528 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., MILTON C. REGAN, JR., EAT WHAT YOU KILL: THE FALL OF A WALL STREET LAWYER (2004); Donald C. Langevoort, Where Were the Lawyers? A Behavioral Inquiry into Lawyers' Responsibility for Clients' Fraud, 46 VAND. L. REV. 75 (1993);
    • See, e.g., MILTON C. REGAN, JR., EAT WHAT YOU KILL: THE FALL OF A WALL STREET LAWYER (2004); Donald C. Langevoort, Where Were the Lawyers? A Behavioral Inquiry into Lawyers' Responsibility for Clients' Fraud, 46 VAND. L. REV. 75 (1993);
  • 12
    • 69649104879 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Discovery Process as a Circle of Blame: Institutional, Professional, and Socio-Economic Factors that Contribute to Unreasonable, Inefficient, and Amoral Behavior in Corporate Litigation, 67
    • Robert L. Nelson, The Discovery Process as a Circle of Blame: Institutional, Professional, and Socio-Economic Factors that Contribute to Unreasonable, Inefficient, and Amoral Behavior in Corporate Litigation, 67 FORDHAM L. REV. 773 (1998);
    • (1998) FORDHAM L. REV , vol.773
    • Nelson, R.L.1
  • 13
    • 33749854621 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wrongs of Ignorance and Ambiguity: Lawyer Responsibility for Collective Misconduct, 22
    • William H. Simon, Wrongs of Ignorance and Ambiguity: Lawyer Responsibility for Collective Misconduct, 22 YALE J. ON REG. 1 (2005).
    • (2005) YALE J. ON REG , vol.1
    • Simon, W.H.1
  • 14
    • 54549101947 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For moral philosophers considering the implications of experimental psychology for ethics, see, for example
    • For moral philosophers considering the implications of experimental psychology for ethics, see, for example, JOHN M. DORIS, LACK OF CHARACTER: PERSONALITY AND MORAL BEHAVIOR (2002);
    • (2002)
    • DORIS, J.M.1    OF CHARACTER, L.2    AND, P.3    BEHAVIOR, M.4
  • 15
    • 54549104529 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • OWEN FLANAGAN, VARIETIES OF MORAL PERSONALITY: ETHICS AND PSYCHOLOGICAL REALISM (1991); JONATHAN GLOVER, HUMANITY: A MORAL HISTORY OF THE TWENTIETH CENTURY (1999);
    • OWEN FLANAGAN, VARIETIES OF MORAL PERSONALITY: ETHICS AND PSYCHOLOGICAL REALISM (1991); JONATHAN GLOVER, HUMANITY: A MORAL HISTORY OF THE TWENTIETH CENTURY (1999);
  • 16
    • 0001217243 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gilbert Harman, Moral Philosophy Meets Social Psychology: Virtue Ethics and the Fundamental Attribution Error, 99 PROC. ARISTOTELIAN SOC'Y 315 (1999).
    • Gilbert Harman, Moral Philosophy Meets Social Psychology: Virtue Ethics and the Fundamental Attribution Error, 99 PROC. ARISTOTELIAN SOC'Y 315 (1999).
  • 17
    • 54549083046 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., LUBAN, Contrived Ignorance, supra note 8, at 254, 259-60 (explaining that various factors may undermine an actor's judgment in ways that mitigate the blameworthiness of the actor's conduct).
    • See, e.g., LUBAN, Contrived Ignorance, supra note 8, at 254, 259-60 (explaining that various factors may undermine an actor's judgment in ways that mitigate the blameworthiness of the actor's conduct).
  • 18
    • 54549101946 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See LUBAN, LEGAL ETHICS AND HUMAN DIGNITY, supra note 4, at 7-8
    • See LUBAN, LEGAL ETHICS AND HUMAN DIGNITY, supra note 4, at 7-8.
  • 19
    • 54549105133 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id
    • See id.
  • 20
    • 54549120101 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Professor Luban cites an anonymous reviewer's negative comment that the book should take a clearer stance on the lawyer's proper role. Id. at 12. I am not chiding Professor Luban for inconsistency, as this reviewer seems to be doing. The point I develop here is that there are political implications for Professor Luban's belief that moral philosophy has difficulty delivering crisp principles to resolve difficult moral dilemmas in ambiguous situations where values collide. Id. I very much share the belief that moral life, particularly in public roles, is necessarily messy and requires sensitivity and judgment rather than the algorithmic application of bright-line principles. I would go further than Professor Luban, however, and orient legal ethics around distinctively political values that recognize the complexity of moral decision making
    • Professor Luban cites an anonymous reviewer's negative comment that the book should take a clearer stance on the lawyer's proper role. Id. at 12. I am not chiding Professor Luban for inconsistency, as this reviewer seems to be doing. The point I develop here is that there are political implications for Professor Luban's belief that moral philosophy has difficulty delivering "crisp principles to resolve difficult moral dilemmas in ambiguous situations where values collide." Id. I very much share the belief that moral life, particularly in public roles, is necessarily messy and requires sensitivity and judgment rather than the algorithmic application of bright-line principles. I would go further than Professor Luban, however, and orient legal ethics around distinctively political values that recognize the complexity of moral decision making.
  • 21
    • 54549101945 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See BERNARD WILLIAMS, Realism and Moralism in Political Theory, in IN THE BEGINNING WAS THE DEED: REALISM AND MORALISM IN POLITICAL ARGUMENT 1, 1-2, 5 (Geoffrey Hawthorn ed., 2005). I am using the phrase inner morality of politics to invoke Fuller's inner morality of law and connect this critique with Professor Luban's discussion of Fuller in Legal Ethics and Human Dignity.
    • See BERNARD WILLIAMS, Realism and Moralism in Political Theory, in IN THE BEGINNING WAS THE DEED: REALISM AND MORALISM IN POLITICAL ARGUMENT 1, 1-2, 5 (Geoffrey Hawthorn ed., 2005). I am using the phrase "inner morality of politics" to invoke Fuller's "inner morality of law" and connect this critique with Professor Luban's discussion of Fuller in Legal Ethics and Human Dignity.
  • 22
    • 54549105132 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See LON L. FULLER, THE MORALITY OF LAW 42-43 (2d ed. 1969) [hereinafter FULLER, MORALITY OF LAW].
    • See LON L. FULLER, THE MORALITY OF LAW 42-43 (2d ed. 1969) [hereinafter FULLER, MORALITY OF LAW].
  • 23
    • 54549095671 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The expression fidelity to law also comes from Fuller. See Lon L. Fuller, Positivism and Fidelity to Law - A Reply to Professor Hart, 71 HARV. L. REV. 630, 632, 642-43 (1957). As the remainder of this Essay should make clear, the Fullerian discussions in Legal Ethics and Human Dignity are some of the most interesting parts of the book.
    • The expression "fidelity to law" also comes from Fuller. See Lon L. Fuller, Positivism and Fidelity to Law - A Reply to Professor Hart, 71 HARV. L. REV. 630, 632, 642-43 (1957). As the remainder of this Essay should make clear, the Fullerian discussions in Legal Ethics and Human Dignity are some of the most interesting parts of the book.
  • 24
    • 54549104530 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See WILLIAMS, supra note 16, at 2-3
    • See WILLIAMS, supra note 16, at 2-3.
  • 25
    • 54549109913 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 3, 5
    • Id. at 3, 5.
  • 27
    • 54549113016 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • JEREMY WALDRON, LAW AND DISAGREEMENT 112 (1999) (On any plausible account, human life engages multiple values and it is natural that people will disagree about how to balance or prioritize them.);
    • JEREMY WALDRON, LAW AND DISAGREEMENT 112 (1999) ("On any plausible account, human life engages multiple values and it is natural that people will disagree about how to balance or prioritize them.");
  • 28
    • 54549104526 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • THOMAS NAGEL, The Fragmentation of Value, in MORTAL QUESTIONS 128, 131, 138 (1979).
    • THOMAS NAGEL, The Fragmentation of Value, in MORTAL QUESTIONS 128, 131, 138 (1979).
  • 29
    • 54549107572 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., ISAIAH BERLIN, The Pursuit of the Ideal, in THE CROOKED TIMBER OF HUMANITY 1, 10-11 (Henry Hardy ed., 1990).
    • See, e.g., ISAIAH BERLIN, The Pursuit of the Ideal, in THE CROOKED TIMBER OF HUMANITY 1, 10-11 (Henry Hardy ed., 1990).
  • 30
    • 54449102485 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See STUART HAMPSHIRE, MORALITY AND CONFLICT 146-47 (1983).
    • See STUART HAMPSHIRE, MORALITY AND CONFLICT 146-47 (1983).
  • 31
    • 54549094576 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id
    • See id.
  • 32
    • 54549103066 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • THE PROPER STUDY OF MANKIND 191, 239
    • & eds, Farrar Straus & Giroux
    • ISAIAH BERLIN, Two Concepts of Liberty, in THE PROPER STUDY OF MANKIND 191, 239 (Henry Hardy & Roger Hausheer eds., Farrar Straus & Giroux 1998) (1997).
    • (1997) Two Concepts of Liberty, in
    • ISAIAH, B.1
  • 33
    • 54549126939 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • LUBAN, LEGAL ETHICS AND HUMAN DIGNITY, supra note 4, at 3
    • LUBAN, LEGAL ETHICS AND HUMAN DIGNITY, supra note 4, at 3.
  • 34
    • 54549095672 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DAVID LUBAN, Natural Law as Professional Ethics: A Reading of Fuller, in LUBAN, LEGAL ETHICS AND HUMAN DIGNITY, supra note 4, at 99, 100 [hereinafter LUBAN, Natural Law];
    • DAVID LUBAN, Natural Law as Professional Ethics: A Reading of Fuller, in LUBAN, LEGAL ETHICS AND HUMAN DIGNITY, supra note 4, at 99, 100 [hereinafter LUBAN, Natural Law];
  • 35
    • 54549089665 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also DAVID LUBAN, A Different Nightmare and a Different Dream, in LUBAN, LEGAL ETHICS AND HUMAN DIGNITY, supra note 4, at 131, 131 [hereinafter LUBAN, Nightmare and Dream] (The lawyer-client consultation is the primary point of intersection between 'The Law' and the people it governs . . . .).
    • see also DAVID LUBAN, A Different Nightmare and a Different Dream, in LUBAN, LEGAL ETHICS AND HUMAN DIGNITY, supra note 4, at 131, 131 [hereinafter LUBAN, Nightmare and Dream] ("The lawyer-client consultation is the primary point of intersection between 'The Law' and the people it governs . . . .").
  • 37
    • 54549112923 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 105
    • Id. at 105.
  • 38
    • 54549090779 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See LUBAN, Nightmare and Dream, supra note 25, at 132 ([T]heir obligation is simply to explain the law in books. . . . as mediated through the interpretive community of law-yers.); LUBAN, Torture Lawyers, supra note 10, at 193 (No formula or algorithm exists for sorting out the plausible-but-wrong arguments from the silly . . . . Legal plausibility is a matter for case-by-case judgment by the interpretive community . . . .). I have argued that the craft of lawyering requires lawyers to base their advice to clients on legal positions that they could, in principle, defend before an interpretive community of their peers.
    • See LUBAN, Nightmare and Dream, supra note 25, at 132 ("[T]heir obligation is simply to explain the law in books. . . . as mediated through the interpretive community of law-yers."); LUBAN, Torture Lawyers, supra note 10, at 193 ("No formula or algorithm exists for sorting out the plausible-but-wrong arguments from the silly . . . . Legal plausibility is a matter for case-by-case judgment by the interpretive community . . . ."). I have argued that the craft of lawyering requires lawyers to base their advice to clients on legal positions that they could, in principle, defend before an interpretive community of their peers.
  • 39
    • 23844434692 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See W. Bradley Wendel, Professionalem as Interpretation, 99 NW. U. L. REV. 1167, 1169-70, 1210 (2005). The tricky part of reliance on the tacit norms of an interpretive community is that one must specify the makeup of the community. See id. at 1215-16. In the text I used the term reasonable lawyers, aware that reasonableness must be fleshed out with respect to criteria external to the community. Otherwise the argument will become a vicious circle. See id. at 1216-17.
    • See W. Bradley Wendel, Professionalem as Interpretation, 99 NW. U. L. REV. 1167, 1169-70, 1210 (2005). The tricky part of reliance on the tacit norms of an interpretive community is that one must specify the makeup of the community. See id. at 1215-16. In the text I used the term "reasonable" lawyers, aware that reasonableness must be fleshed out with respect to criteria external to the community. Otherwise the argument will become a vicious circle. See id. at 1216-17.
  • 40
    • 54549098928 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Professor Luban avoids circularity by appealing to consensus: [T]he legal mainstream defines the concept of plausibility. LUBAN, Torture Lawyers, supra note 10, at 194. I believe, on the other hand, that reliance on the notion of a legal mainstream raises the problem of plural, competing interpretive communities. See Wendel, supra at 1216. This is familiar in constitutional law, in the form of the debate among textualists, originalists, interpretivists, popular constitutionalists, and so on. Each of these theoretical approaches to constitutional interpretation has attracted a substantial community of adherents among lawyers, judges, and scholars. A fractured Supreme Court decision is likely to divide along exactly these lines separating different interpretive communities
    • Professor Luban avoids circularity by appealing to consensus: "[T]he legal mainstream defines the concept of plausibility." LUBAN, Torture Lawyers, supra note 10, at 194. I believe, on the other hand, that reliance on the notion of a legal mainstream raises the problem of plural, competing interpretive communities. See Wendel, supra at 1216. This is familiar in constitutional law, in the form of the debate among textualists, originalists, interpretivists, popular constitutionalists, and so on. Each of these theoretical approaches to constitutional interpretation has attracted a substantial community of adherents among lawyers, judges, and scholars. A fractured Supreme Court decision is likely to divide along exactly these lines separating different interpretive communities.
  • 41
    • 54549117820 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moving further out on the bell curve [of plausibility, we find the kind of arguments that lawyers euphemistically call 'creative, See, at
    • See LUBAN, Torture Lawyers, supra note 10, at 193 ("Moving further out on the bell curve [of plausibility], we find the kind of arguments that lawyers euphemistically call 'creative' . . . .").
    • Torture Lawyers, supra note , vol.10 , pp. 193
    • LUBAN1
  • 42
    • 54549114105 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 198, 201.
    • See id. at 198, 201.
  • 43
    • 54549107573 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 197-98, 200-02.
    • See id. at 197-98, 200-02.
  • 44
    • 54549111018 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 198
    • Id. at 198.
  • 45
    • 54549104525 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 200-02
    • Id. at 200-02.
  • 46
    • 84888494968 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • text accompanying notes 16-18
    • See supra text accompanying notes 16-18.
    • See supra
  • 47
    • 54549104456 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The notion of the internal point of view is central to Hart's jurisprudence. See H.L.A. HART, THE CONCEPT OF LAW 88-89 (2d ed. 1994, According to Hart, law creates reasons for action that are acknowledged by citizens using the language of obligation, such as ought must and should, and right and wrong. Id. at 57 (internal quotation marks omitted, In order for there to be a legal system, it is conceptually necessary that certain officials (namely, judges) regard the law from the internal point of view when deliberating. See id. at 102-03. If judges did not acknowledge the rule of recognition as a legitimate reason for deciding cases on some grounds and not others, then there would be no way to differentiate an authoritative legal command from the demand of a mugger. See id. at 116. Professor Luban takes up the interesting question of whether lawyers are also required to adopt the internal point of view toward t
    • The notion of the internal point of view is central to Hart's jurisprudence. See H.L.A. HART, THE CONCEPT OF LAW 88-89 (2d ed. 1994). According to Hart, law creates reasons for action that are acknowledged by citizens using the language of obligation, such as "ought must and should, and right and wrong." Id. at 57 (internal quotation marks omitted). In order for there to be a legal system, it is conceptually necessary that certain officials (namely, judges) regard the law from the internal point of view when deliberating. See id. at 102-03. If judges did not acknowledge the rule of recognition as a legitimate reason for deciding cases on some grounds and not others, then there would be no way to differentiate an authoritative legal command from the demand of a mugger. See id. at 116. Professor Luban takes up the interesting question of whether lawyers are also required to adopt the internal point of view toward the rule of recognition and concludes that this, too, is a requirement of a rule-of-law regime.
  • 49
    • 54549104524 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See ALASDAIR MACINTYRE, AFTER VIRTUE: A STUDY IN MORAL THEORY 187 (Univ. Notre Dame Press 3d ed. 2007) (1981) (defining a practice as any coherent and complex form of socially established cooperative human activity through which goods internal to that form of activity are realized in the course of trying to achieve those standards of excellence which are appropriate to, and partially definitive of, that form of activity).
    • See ALASDAIR MACINTYRE, AFTER VIRTUE: A STUDY IN MORAL THEORY 187 (Univ. Notre Dame Press 3d ed. 2007) (1981) (defining a practice as "any coherent and complex form of socially established cooperative human activity through which goods internal to that form of activity are realized in the course of trying to achieve those standards of excellence which are appropriate to, and partially definitive of, that form of activity").
  • 50
    • 0002921553 scopus 로고
    • Two Concepts of Rules, 64
    • See
    • See John Rawls, Two Concepts of Rules, 64 PHIL. REV. 3, 16, 24-26 (1955).
    • (1955) PHIL. REV , vol.3 , Issue.16 , pp. 24-26
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 51
    • 54549125541 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • WILLIAMS, supra note 16, at 11
    • WILLIAMS, supra note 16, at 11.
  • 52
    • 54549087526 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • JOHN RAWLS, Reply to Habermas, in POLITICAL LIBERALISM 372, 380 (1996).
    • JOHN RAWLS, Reply to Habermas, in POLITICAL LIBERALISM 372, 380 (1996).
  • 53
    • 54549124337 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See JOSEPH RAZ, The Politics of the Rule of Law, in ETHICS IN THE PUBLIC DOMAIN: ESSAYS IN THE MORALITY OF LAW AND POLITICS 354, 354 (1994).
    • See JOSEPH RAZ, The Politics of the Rule of Law, in ETHICS IN THE PUBLIC DOMAIN: ESSAYS IN THE MORALITY OF LAW AND POLITICS 354, 354 (1994).
  • 54
    • 54549115776 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 358
    • Id. at 358.
  • 56
    • 54549084173 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See DAVID LUBAN, The Adversary System Excuse, in LUBAN, LEGAL ETHICS AND HUMAN DIGNITY, supra note 4, at 19, 63 [hereinafter LUBAN, Adversary System Excuse].
    • See DAVID LUBAN, The Adversary System Excuse, in LUBAN, LEGAL ETHICS AND HUMAN DIGNITY, supra note 4, at 19, 63 [hereinafter LUBAN, Adversary System Excuse].
  • 57
    • 54549125546 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 23, 57-62.
    • See id. at 23, 57-62.
  • 58
    • 54549091906 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 61-62.
    • See id. at 61-62.
  • 59
    • 65149083012 scopus 로고
    • The Lawyer as Friend: The Moral Foundations of the Lawyer-Client Relation, 85
    • Charles Fried, The Lawyer as Friend: The Moral Foundations of the Lawyer-Client Relation, 85 YALE L.J. 1060, 1060 (1976).
    • (1976) YALE L.J , vol.1060 , pp. 1060
    • Fried, C.1
  • 60
    • 54549109820 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Hidden Bodies Case, also known as the Lake Pleasant Bodies Case, is a staple of professional responsibility casebooks and academic scholarship. For excellent summaries of the case, see LISA G. LERMAN & PHILIP G. SCHRAG, ETHICAL PROBLEMS IN THE PRACTICE OF LAW 121-28 (2005),
    • The Hidden Bodies Case, also known as the Lake Pleasant Bodies Case, is a staple of professional responsibility casebooks and academic scholarship. For excellent summaries of the case, see LISA G. LERMAN & PHILIP G. SCHRAG, ETHICAL PROBLEMS IN THE PRACTICE OF LAW 121-28 (2005),
  • 61
    • 54549117821 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and RICHARD ZITRIN & CAROL M. LANGFORD, THE MORAL COMPASS OF THE AMERICAN LAWYER: TRUTH, JUSTICE, POWER, AND GREED 7-26 (1999).
    • and RICHARD ZITRIN & CAROL M. LANGFORD, THE MORAL COMPASS OF THE AMERICAN LAWYER: TRUTH, JUSTICE, POWER, AND GREED 7-26 (1999).
  • 62
    • 54549083040 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See ZITRIN & LANGFORD, supra note 47, at 13
    • See ZITRIN & LANGFORD, supra note 47, at 13.
  • 63
    • 54549106506 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As a statement about the duty of confidentiality, this is incomplete; lawyers in most jurisdictions have discretion to disclose confidential information to prevent, rectify, or mitigate certain types of harm. See MODEL RULES OF PROF'L CONDUCT R. 1.6(b) (2007). In the Hidden Bodies Case, however, it remains an accurate statement to say that the lawyer had no discretion to reveal the location of the bodies to the authorities or the parents.
    • As a statement about the duty of confidentiality, this is incomplete; lawyers in most jurisdictions have discretion to disclose confidential information to prevent, rectify, or mitigate certain types of harm. See MODEL RULES OF PROF'L CONDUCT R. 1.6(b) (2007). In the Hidden Bodies Case, however, it remains an accurate statement to say that the lawyer had no discretion to reveal the location of the bodies to the authorities or the parents.
  • 64
    • 54549105123 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 47, at, quoting an interview by PBS with Frank Armani, one of the lawyers in the Hidden Bodies Case
    • ZITRIN & LANGFORD, supra note 47, at 19 (quoting an interview by PBS with Frank Armani, one of the lawyers in the Hidden Bodies Case).
    • supra , pp. 19
    • ZITRIN1    LANGFORD2
  • 65
    • 54549118962 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Professor Luban formerly referred to neutral partisanship as the standard conception, LUBAN, LEGAL ETHICS AND HUMAN DIGNITY, supra note 4, at 9, and that term continues to be widely used in the legal ethics literature.
    • Professor Luban formerly referred to neutral partisanship as the "standard conception," LUBAN, LEGAL ETHICS AND HUMAN DIGNITY, supra note 4, at 9, and that term continues to be widely used in the legal ethics literature.
  • 66
    • 2442546606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See W. Bradley Wendel, Civil Obedience, 104 COLUM. L. REV. 363, 364 n.4 (2004) [hereinafter Wendel, Civil Obedience].
    • See W. Bradley Wendel, Civil Obedience, 104 COLUM. L. REV. 363, 364 n.4 (2004) [hereinafter Wendel, Civil Obedience].
  • 67
    • 54549101941 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See LUBAN, LEGAL ETHICS AND HUMAN DIGNITY, supra note 4, at 9
    • See LUBAN, LEGAL ETHICS AND HUMAN DIGNITY, supra note 4, at 9.
  • 68
    • 54549105131 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id
    • See id.
  • 69
    • 54549084246 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For this formulation of the standard conception, see Murray L. Schwartz, The Zeal of the Civil Advocate, in THE GOOD LAWYER 150, 151 (David Luban ed., 1984);
    • For this formulation of the standard conception, see Murray L. Schwartz, The Zeal of the Civil Advocate, in THE GOOD LAWYER 150, 151 (David Luban ed., 1984);
  • 70
    • 0039343483 scopus 로고
    • Moral Responsibility in Professional Ethics, 55
    • Gerald J. Postema, Moral Responsibility in Professional Ethics, 55 N.Y.U. L. REV. 63, 73-81 (1980).
    • (1980) N.Y.U. L. REV , vol.63 , pp. 73-81
    • Postema, G.J.1
  • 71
    • 54549083045 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ZITRIN & LANGFORD, supra note 47, at 19
    • ZITRIN & LANGFORD, supra note 47, at 19.
  • 72
    • 54549101943 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 17-18.
    • See id. at 17-18.
  • 73
    • 54549101944 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 19 (quoting Frank Armani, one of the lawyers in the Hidden Bodies Case, as saying that if a principle doesn't belong to the worst of us, then it can't belong to the best (internal quotation marks omitted)).
    • See id. at 19 (quoting Frank Armani, one of the lawyers in the Hidden Bodies Case, as saying that "if a principle doesn't belong to the worst of us, then it can't belong to the best" (internal quotation marks omitted)).
  • 75
    • 54549104522 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See NICHOLAS PILEGGI, WISEGUY: LIFE IN A MAFIA FAMILY 36-37 (1985).
    • See NICHOLAS PILEGGI, WISEGUY: LIFE IN A MAFIA FAMILY 36-37 (1985).
  • 78
    • 54549105128 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See DAVID LUBAN, Lawyers as Upholders of Human Dignity (When They Aren't Busy Assaulting It), in LUBAN, LEGAL ETHICS AND HUMAN DIGNITY, supra note 4, at 65, 71 [hereinafter LUBAN, Upholders of Human Dignity].
    • See DAVID LUBAN, Lawyers as Upholders of Human Dignity (When They Aren't Busy Assaulting It), in LUBAN, LEGAL ETHICS AND HUMAN DIGNITY, supra note 4, at 65, 71 [hereinafter LUBAN, Upholders of Human Dignity].
  • 79
    • 54549084245 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ARTHUR ISAK APPLBAUM, ETHICS FOR ADVERSARIES: THE MORALITY OF ROLES IN PUBLIC AND PROFESSIONAL LIFE 45 (1999).
    • ARTHUR ISAK APPLBAUM, ETHICS FOR ADVERSARIES: THE MORALITY OF ROLES IN PUBLIC AND PROFESSIONAL LIFE 45 (1999).
  • 80
    • 54549105122 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Professor Luban has previously endorsed this nexus or shorthand view of the normative status of roles. See LUBAN, LAWYERS AND JUSTICE, supra note 1, at 125 ([T]he appeal to a role in moral justification is simply a shorthand method of appealing to the moral reasons incorporated in that role.). He has modified some aspects of his position, while reaffirming the shorthand view.
    • Professor Luban has previously endorsed this "nexus" or "shorthand" view of the normative status of roles. See LUBAN, LAWYERS AND JUSTICE, supra note 1, at 125 ("[T]he appeal to a role in moral justification is simply a shorthand method of appealing to the moral reasons incorporated in that role."). He has modified some aspects of his position, while reaffirming the "shorthand" view.
  • 81
    • 54549105127 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See David Luban, Freedom and Constraint in Legal Ethics: Some Mid-Course Corrections to Lawyers and Justice, 49 MD. L. REV. 424, 434 (1990) [hereinafter Luban, Freedom and Constraint].
    • See David Luban, Freedom and Constraint in Legal Ethics: Some Mid-Course Corrections to Lawyers and Justice, 49 MD. L. REV. 424, 434 (1990) [hereinafter Luban, Freedom and Constraint].
  • 82
    • 54549105125 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DAVID LUBAN, Integrity: Its Causes and Cures, in LUBAN, LEGAL ETHICS AND HUMAN DIGNITY, supra note 4, at 267, 281 [hereinafter LUBAN, Integrity].
    • DAVID LUBAN, Integrity: Its Causes and Cures, in LUBAN, LEGAL ETHICS AND HUMAN DIGNITY, supra note 4, at 267, 281 [hereinafter LUBAN, Integrity].
  • 83
    • 54549101942 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id
    • See id.
  • 85
    • 54549113015 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • LUBAN, LAWYERS AND JUSTICE, supra note 1, at 129-33
    • LUBAN, LAWYERS AND JUSTICE, supra note 1, at 129-33.
  • 86
    • 54549120100 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. The fourfold root argument gets boiled down to two steps in the first essay of the present book. Justification of role-acts requires both that the institution as a whole be justified and that the institution require a role-actor to do the act. See LUBAN, Adversary System Excuse, supra note 43, at 57
    • Id. The fourfold root argument gets boiled down to two steps in the first essay of the present book. Justification of role-acts requires both that the institution as a whole be justified and that the institution require a role-actor to do the act. See LUBAN, Adversary System Excuse, supra note 43, at 57.
  • 87
    • 54549083043 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • LUBAN, LAWYERS AND JUSTICE, supra note 1, at 132
    • LUBAN, LAWYERS AND JUSTICE, supra note 1, at 132.
  • 88
    • 54549096692 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra notes 59-60 and accompanying text Note, however, that the first three steps of the justification may hold: (1) the duties of wiseguys may require whacking Remo; (2) imposing obligations of violent retribution on wiseguys may be necessary in order to instill fear in those of them who might be tempted to rat a money-making scheme out to the police; and (3) the role of wiseguy may be necessary for the effective functioning of the family. Conversely, within an otherwise-justified institutional context, the moral excuse promised by the role and its associated obligations may fail at an earlier step in the fourfold root process. For example, one might argue that a lawyer may not assert a genuine role obligation to resist legitimate requests for discoverable information. A purported obligation to play hide-the-ball in discovery is inconsistent with the ends of the discovery regime and the rivil litigation system generally. A great advantage of the fourfold root argument is it
    • See supra notes 59-60 and accompanying text Note, however, that the first three steps of the justification may hold: (1) the duties of wiseguys may require whacking Remo; (2) imposing obligations of violent retribution on wiseguys may be necessary in order to instill fear in those of them who might be tempted to rat a money-making scheme out to the police; and (3) the role of wiseguy may be necessary for the effective functioning of the family. Conversely, within an otherwise-justified institutional context, the moral excuse promised by the role and its associated obligations may fail at an earlier step in the fourfold root process. For example, one might argue that a lawyer may not assert a genuine role obligation to resist legitimate requests for discoverable information. A purported obligation to play hide-the-ball in discovery is inconsistent with the ends of the discovery regime and the rivil litigation system generally. A great advantage of the fourfold root argument is its ability to structure this kind of fine-grained analysis of institutional excuses.
  • 89
    • 54549083042 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Professor Luban reaches the same conclusion, albeit with some reservations. See LUBAN, LAWYERS AND JUSTICE, supra note 1, at 149;
    • Professor Luban reaches the same conclusion, albeit with some reservations. See LUBAN, LAWYERS AND JUSTICE, supra note 1, at 149;
  • 93
    • 8844253761 scopus 로고
    • The Sources of Legal Ethics: A German-American Comparison of Lawyers' Professional Duties
    • For a comparative analysis of adversarial practices in the German and American legal systems, see, 245
    • For a comparative analysis of adversarial practices in the German and American legal systems, see David Luban, The Sources of Legal Ethics: A German-American Comparison of Lawyers' Professional Duties, 48 RABELS ZEITSCHRIFT FÜR AUSLÄNDISCHES UND INTERNATIONALES PRIVATRECHT 245 (1984).
    • (1984) RABELS ZEITSCHRIFT FÜR AUSLÄNDISCHES UND INTERNATIONALES PRIVATRECHT , vol.48
    • Luban, D.1
  • 94
    • 54549123247 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See LUBAN, LAWYERS AND JUSTICE, supra note 1, at 160-61, 173-74
    • See LUBAN, LAWYERS AND JUSTICE, supra note 1, at 160-61, 173-74.
  • 96
    • 54549101886 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Professor Luban does not disagree with the characterization of the argument as conservative but prefers the term pragmatic because his argument proceeds in a piecemeal, nonideological way. Id. at 57. In the present political climate 1 suppose it is wise to distinguish small-c-conservatism from the highly ideological Conservatism of the religious right or foreign policy neoconservatives. In political theory terms, the more important distinction is between piecemeal, pragmatic conservatism and a Burkean defense of the adversary system as an integral part of our public culture. Professor Luban disclaims any Burkean basis for NP, rightly noting that even wholesale abolition of NP would amount to only marginal tinkering with the overall political culture of the United States. See id. at 54-55
    • Professor Luban does not disagree with the characterization of the argument as conservative but prefers the term "pragmatic" because his argument proceeds "in a piecemeal, nonideological way." Id. at 57. In the present political climate 1 suppose it is wise to distinguish small-c-conservatism from the highly ideological Conservatism of the religious right or foreign policy neoconservatives. In political theory terms, the more important distinction is between piecemeal, pragmatic conservatism and a Burkean defense of the adversary system as an integral part of our public culture. Professor Luban disclaims any Burkean basis for NP, rightly noting that even wholesale abolition of NP would amount to only marginal tinkering with the overall political culture of the United States. See id. at 54-55.
  • 97
    • 54549106507 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., WILLIAM H. SIMON, THE PRACTICE OF JUSTICE: A THEORY OF LAWYERS' ETHICS (1998);
    • See, e.g., WILLIAM H. SIMON, THE PRACTICE OF JUSTICE: A THEORY OF LAWYERS' ETHICS (1998);
  • 98
    • 0042337187 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moral Pluck: Legal Ethics in Popular Culture, 101
    • William H. Simon, Moral Pluck: Legal Ethics in Popular Culture, 101 COLUM. L. REV. 421 (2001).
    • (2001) COLUM. L. REV , vol.421
    • Simon, W.H.1
  • 99
    • 54549104241 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See DAVID LUBAN, A Midrash on Rabbi Shaffer and Rabbi Trollope, in LUBAN, LEGAL ETHICS AND HUMAN DIGNITY, supra note 4, at 301, 307 [hereinafter LUBAN, Shaffer and Trollope] (I read Shaffer's language about the thief on the cross with his advocate hanging at his side quite seriously and literally. It means, I think, that if ministering to the client requires a lawyer to break a Model Rule, or a law, and undergo punishment for it, then the Christian who is a lawyer will break the Model Rule and the law - not because doing so is in the larger public interest but because doing so is what faithful ministry demands.).
    • See DAVID LUBAN, A Midrash on Rabbi Shaffer and Rabbi Trollope, in LUBAN, LEGAL ETHICS AND HUMAN DIGNITY, supra note 4, at 301, 307 [hereinafter LUBAN, Shaffer and Trollope] ("I read Shaffer's language about the thief on the cross with his advocate hanging at his side quite seriously and literally. It means, I think, that if ministering to the client requires a lawyer to break a Model Rule, or a law, and undergo punishment for it, then the Christian who is a lawyer will break the Model Rule and the law - not because doing so is in the larger public interest but because doing so is what faithful ministry demands.").
  • 101
    • 54549118960 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 57
    • Id. at 57.
  • 102
    • 54549105061 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 59
    • Id. at 59.
  • 103
    • 54549091902 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 61 (An institution anchors a moral excuse only to the extent that it has moral heft. If the institution is justified only because it is there, it possesses only the minutest quantum of force to excuse an otherwise immoral act).
    • Id. at 61 ("An institution anchors a moral excuse only to the extent that it has moral heft. If the institution is justified only because it is there, it possesses only the minutest quantum of force to excuse an otherwise immoral act").
  • 104
    • 54549093469 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at 59 (analyzing the Hidden Bodies Case as an instance of a strong institutional justification and a genuine role-specific duty); cf. Luban
    • W]e cannot resolve all conflicts between common morality and role morality in favor of the former, See, at
    • See id. at 59 (analyzing the Hidden Bodies Case as an instance of a strong institutional justification and a genuine role-specific duty); cf. Luban, Freedom and Constraint, supra note 63, at 445 ("[W]e cannot resolve all conflicts between common morality and role morality in favor of the former.").
    • Freedom and Constraint, supra note , vol.63 , pp. 445
  • 106
    • 54549084172 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 107
    • 54549089670 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 329
    • Id. at 329.
  • 108
    • 54549126941 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • LUBAN, Integrity, supra note 64, at 269-81; see also id. at 288-89 (It seems very likely that before too long you will find yourself believing that a special professional morality, distinct from the morality of your extra-professional life, justifies what you do - and this belief will be no transitory thing, but rather a fixed part of your moral personality.).
    • LUBAN, Integrity, supra note 64, at 269-81; see also id. at 288-89 ("It seems very likely that before too long you will find yourself believing that a special professional morality, distinct from the morality of your extra-professional life, justifies what you do - and this belief will be no transitory thing, but rather a fixed part of your moral personality.").
  • 109
    • 54549093468 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • LUBAN, LEGAL ETHICS AND HUMAN DIGNITY, supra note 4, at 13 n.20 (It is simply impossible to maintain coherency in the role without giving some, defeasible, priority to its demands. (citing Luban, Freedom and Constraint, supra note 63, at 434-52)).
    • LUBAN, LEGAL ETHICS AND HUMAN DIGNITY, supra note 4, at 13 n.20 ("It is simply impossible to maintain coherency in the role without giving some, defeasible, priority to its demands." (citing Luban, Freedom and Constraint, supra note 63, at 434-52)).
  • 110
    • 54549098931 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Wendel, Civil Obedience, supra note 51
    • See Wendel, Civil Obedience, supra note 51.
  • 111
    • 54549112922 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • concluding that the normative situation facing lawyers is a presumption in favor of professional obligation, but one that any serious and countervailing moral obligation rebuts, at
    • LUBAN, Adversary System Excuse, supra note 43, at 63 (concluding that the normative situation facing lawyers is "a presumption in favor of professional obligation, but one that any serious and countervailing moral obligation rebuts");
    • Adversary System Excuse, supra note , vol.43 , pp. 63
    • LUBAN1
  • 112
    • 54549120097 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf. Luban, Freedom and Constraint, supra note 63, at 451 (If . . . we regard the demands of role morality . . . as defeasible presumptions, then stability becomes possible once more. . . . [O]nly in exceptional circumstances concerning the distress of others should we step out of the duties of our station . . . .).
    • cf. Luban, Freedom and Constraint, supra note 63, at 451 ("If . . . we regard the demands of role morality . . . as defeasible presumptions, then stability becomes possible once more. . . . [O]nly in exceptional circumstances concerning the distress of others should we step out of the duties of our station . . . .").
  • 113
    • 54549108663 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • O]ne fails to respect [a person's] dignity as a human being if on any serious matter one refuses even provisionally to treat his or her testimony about it as being in good faith, See, e.g, at
    • See, e.g., LUBAN, Upholders of Human Dignity, supra note 62, at 68 ("'[O]ne fails to respect [a person's] dignity as a human being if on any serious matter one refuses even provisionally to treat his or her testimony about it as being in good faith.'"
    • Upholders of Human Dignity, supra note , vol.62 , pp. 68
    • LUBAN1
  • 114
    • 54549111014 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (quoting Alan Donagan, Justifying Legal Practice in the Adversary System, in THE GOOD LAWYER, supra note 54, at 130)); id. at 79 (criticizing the lawyers who represented the Unabomber, Ted Kacyznski, for using evidence of his mental status that made nonsense of his deepest commitments).
    • (quoting Alan Donagan, Justifying Legal Practice in the Adversary System, in THE GOOD LAWYER, supra note 54, at 130)); id. at 79 (criticizing the lawyers who represented the Unabomber, Ted Kacyznski, for using evidence of his mental status that "made nonsense of his deepest commitments").
  • 115
    • 54549100060 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 73
    • Id. at 73.
  • 116
    • 54549123246 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 80-88.
    • See id. at 80-88.
  • 117
    • 54549109815 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 83
    • Id. at 83.
  • 118
    • 54549125543 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See LUBAN, LAWYERS AND JUSTICE, supra note 1, at 232
    • See LUBAN, LAWYERS AND JUSTICE, supra note 1, at 232.
  • 119
    • 54549115780 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 220-33. Professor Luban has made this argument in connection with the corporate attorney-client privilege, and he has concluded that the value of human dignity does not justify the privilege in an organizational context See id.
    • See id. at 220-33. Professor Luban has made this argument in connection with the corporate attorney-client privilege, and he has concluded that the value of human dignity does not justify the privilege in an organizational context See id.
  • 121
    • 54549086358 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 35-36.
    • See id. at 35-36.
  • 122
    • 54549121204 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 63
    • Id. at 63.
  • 123
    • 54549126942 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 59
    • See id. at 59.
  • 124
    • 54549095606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id
    • See id.
  • 125
    • 54549120094 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • S]trongly differentiated role-obligations, can be defended only within narrow contexts such as criminal defense, See, at
    • See LUBAN, Natural Law, supra note 25, at 120 ("[S]trongly differentiated role-obligations . . . can be defended only within narrow contexts such as criminal defense.").
    • Natural Law, supra note , vol.25 , pp. 120
    • LUBAN1
  • 126
    • 54549120099 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 99-130.
    • See id. at 99-130.
  • 127
    • 54549088615 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pedigree is Dworkin's term. See RONALD DWORKIN, TAKING RIGHTS SERIOUSLY 40 (1977).
    • "Pedigree" is Dworkin's term. See RONALD DWORKIN, TAKING RIGHTS SERIOUSLY 40 (1977).
  • 128
    • 54549124335 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Raz articulates the same point in terms of the social thesis - that is, what is law and what is not is a matter of social fact. . . . JOSEPH RAZ, Legal Positivism and the Sources of Law, in THE AUTHORITY OF LAW 37, 37 (1979).
    • Raz articulates the same point in terms of the "social thesis" - that is, "what is law and what is not is a matter of social fact. . . ." JOSEPH RAZ, Legal Positivism and the Sources of Law, in THE AUTHORITY OF LAW 37, 37 (1979).
  • 129
    • 54549109818 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • LUBAN, Natural Law, supra note 25, at 102 (quoting FULLER, MORALITY OF LAW, supra note 16, at 91).
    • LUBAN, Natural Law, supra note 25, at 102 (quoting FULLER, MORALITY OF LAW, supra note 16, at 91).
  • 130
    • 54549107575 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 102-03.
    • See id. at 102-03.
  • 131
    • 54549094577 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id
    • See id.
  • 132
    • 54549087525 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 106-09. In a very nice passage, Professor Luban gives as clear and concise an explanation of the Aristotelian idea of the internal normativity of some object or practice as I have seen: [T]o recognize something as a steam engine or a light switch is already to recognize what it ought to do, to recognize a built-in standard of success or failure. Success or failure at what? At being a steam engine or a light switch - at being what it is, one might say. Purposive concepts are aspirational concepts - and now we recognize that Fuller's morality of aspiration is intimately connected with his analysis of purposive concepts, and hence with the is/ought distinction. Id. at 109.
    • See id. at 106-09. In a very nice passage, Professor Luban gives as clear and concise an explanation of the Aristotelian idea of the internal normativity of some object or practice as I have seen: [T]o recognize something as a steam engine or a light switch is already to recognize what it ought to do, to recognize a built-in standard of success or failure. Success or failure at what? At being a steam engine or a light switch - at being what it is, one might say. Purposive concepts are aspirational concepts - and now we recognize that Fuller's morality of aspiration is intimately connected with his analysis of purposive concepts, and hence with the is/ought distinction. Id. at 109.
  • 133
    • 54549111020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 110, 112.
    • See id. at 110, 112.
  • 134
    • 54549120098 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 118.
    • See id. at 118.
  • 135
    • 54549100062 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 136
    • 54549088600 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra pp. 1418-19.
    • See infra , pp. 1418-1419
  • 138
    • 84900051927 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • quoting FULLER, MORALITY OF LAW, note 16, at
    • Id. (quoting FULLER, MORALITY OF LAW, supra note 16, at 207).
    • supra , pp. 207
    • LUBAN1
  • 139
    • 84963456897 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 62 and accompanying text
    • See supra note 62 and accompanying text.
    • See supra
  • 141
    • 54549085292 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id
    • See id.
  • 142
    • 54549118957 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • WALDRON, supra note 19, at 282
    • WALDRON, supra note 19, at 282.
  • 143
    • 54549109817 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id
    • See id.
  • 145
    • 54549111016 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See JACK GOLDSMITH, THE TERROR PRESIDENCY: LAW AND JUDGMENT INSIDE THE BUSH ADMINISTRATION 72-76 (2007).
    • See JACK GOLDSMITH, THE TERROR PRESIDENCY: LAW AND JUDGMENT INSIDE THE BUSH ADMINISTRATION 72-76 (2007).
  • 146
    • 54549089668 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id
    • See id.
  • 147
    • 54549090776 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 103-08.
    • See id. at 103-08.
  • 148
    • 54549104457 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 106-07.
    • See id. at 106-07.
  • 149
    • 54549088614 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 106-09.
    • See id. at 106-09.
  • 150
    • 54549118956 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • LUBAN, Torture Lawyers, supra note 10, at 165-68, 190-92
    • LUBAN, Torture Lawyers, supra note 10, at 165-68, 190-92.
  • 151
    • 54549109816 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 169-92.
    • See id. at 169-92.
  • 152
    • 54549122257 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id
    • See id.
  • 153
    • 54549085291 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 172-92.
    • See id. at 172-92.
  • 154
    • 54549101186 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 198
    • Id. at 198.
  • 155
    • 54549087529 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 203.
    • See id. at 203.
  • 156
    • 54549126943 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 205
    • Id. at 205.
  • 158
    • 54549088612 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • LUBAN, LEGAL ETHICS AND HUMAN DIGNITY, supra note 4, at 13
    • LUBAN, LEGAL ETHICS AND HUMAN DIGNITY, supra note 4, at 13.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.