메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 3, Issue 1, 1997, Pages 61-80

On behalf of "the participation of the people": A radical theory of democracy

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 53249117790     PISSN: 13564765     EISSN: 15728692     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1007/bf02336639     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (5)

References (33)
  • 1
    • 85080745615 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I would nevertheless suggest that the very idea of democracy is based on the recognition of a plurality of wills, which cannot be gathered into one will.
    • I would nevertheless suggest that the very idea of democracy is based on the recognition of a plurality of wills, which cannot be gathered into one will.
  • 2
    • 0000454866 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Market and the forum: Three varieties of political theory
    • J. Elster and A Holland, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986)
    • J. Elster, "The Market and the forum: three varieties of political theory", in J. Elster and A Holland, The Foundations of Social Choice Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986), 103-32.
    • The Foundations of Social Choice Theory , pp. 103-132
    • Elster, J.1
  • 3
    • 85080777428 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Or a revised version of it, because Schumpeter may seem to assume that people are largely incapable of knowing their own interests.
    • Or a revised version of it, because Schumpeter may seem to assume that people are largely incapable of knowing their own interests.
  • 4
    • 0001992170 scopus 로고
    • Three normative models of democracy
    • J. Habermas, "Three normative models of democracy", Constellation 1 (1994), 1-11.
    • (1994) Constellation , vol.1 , pp. 1-11
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 5
    • 0002161865 scopus 로고
    • Deliberation and democratic legitimacy
    • A. Hamlin and P. Pettit, eds., Oxford: Blaclkwell
    • But see also J. Cohen, "Deliberation and democratic legitimacy", in A. Hamlin and P. Pettit, eds., The Good Polity (Oxford: Blaclkwell, 1989), 17-34;
    • (1989) The Good Polity , pp. 17-34
    • Cohen, A.J.1
  • 6
    • 0002959322 scopus 로고
    • Deliberative democracy and social choice
    • Special Issue, (Miller argues that deliberative democracy is a decision-making system, which, compared to liberal democracy, is less vulnerable to the arbitrariness of decisionmaking rules and strategic voting)
    • D. Miller, "Deliberative democracy and social choice", Political Studies XL (1992), Special Issue, 54-67 (Miller argues that deliberative democracy is a decision-making system, which, compared to liberal democracy, is less vulnerable to the arbitrariness of decisionmaking rules and strategic voting);
    • (1992) Political Studies XL , pp. 54-67
    • Miller, D.1
  • 7
    • 0041181585 scopus 로고
    • Deliberative rationality and models of democratic legitimacy
    • (Benhabib can sometimes be read as if she considers discourse rather than decision-making to be the main idea of democracy; on the other hand, she claims that the deliberative model of democracy is procedural, and therefore -I believe -she regards it as instrumental: "The more conflictsof interests there are, the more it is important to have procedural solutions" (at 34): so the deliberation is a procedure for reaching a decision which allows cooperation; it is not a good in itself.)
    • S. Benhabib, "Deliberative rationality and models of democratic legitimacy", Constellation 1 (1994), 26-52. (Benhabib can sometimes be read as if she considers discourse rather than decision-making to be the main idea of democracy; on the other hand, she claims that the deliberative model of democracy is procedural, and therefore -I believe -she regards it as instrumental: "The more conflictsof interests there are, the more it is important to have procedural solutions" (at 34): so the deliberation is a procedure for reaching a decision which allows cooperation; it is not a good in itself.)
    • (1994) Constellation , vol.1 , pp. 26-52
    • Benhabib, S.1
  • 9
    • 85080763756 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The first regards politics as a procedure for achieving public priorities based on those of individuals; the second as a way of arriving at decisions by means of rational public debate.
    • The first regards politics as a procedure for achieving public priorities based on those of individuals; the second as a way of arriving at decisions by means of rational public debate.
  • 10
    • 84928441681 scopus 로고
    • Elster on self-realization in politics: A critical note
    • Elster, supra n.2. Elster's critique of this model is challenged by Joseph Chan and David Miller, in their "Elster on self-realization in politics: a critical note", Ethics 102 (1991), 96-102.
    • (1991) Ethics , vol.102 , pp. 96-102
    • Chan, J.1    Miller, D.2
  • 11
    • 85080653853 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Elsewhere, however, David Miller argues in support of internal instrumentalism (what he and Chan call "side-effects"), i.e. educative potential and the status that democracy confers on participants. See Chan and Miller, supra n.7.
    • Elsewhere, however, David Miller argues in support of internal instrumentalism (what he and Chan call "side-effects"), i.e. educative potential and the status that democracy confers on participants. See Chan and Miller, supra n.7.
  • 12
    • 84971766238 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Notice that I am not relating these sorts of relation to the questions of how preferences are shaped and whether they are manipulated, nor to how one measures preferences. For these two questions one may consult I. Ajzen and M. Fishbein, Understanding Attitudes and Predicting Social Behaviour (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1980). On the first one may also consult the theory put forward by R. Ingelhart in his The Silent Revolution: Changing Values and Political Styles Among Western Publics (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1977). For a rather conservative answer to the second question one may refer to W. Riker, Liberalism Against Populism; a Confrontation Between the Theory of Democracy and the Theory of Social Choice (San Francisco: W.H. Freeman, 1982) and to the responses of I. MacLean, Public Choice (Oxford: Blackwell, 1987), 187ff. and A. Weale, "Social choice versus populism? an interpretation of Riker's political theory", British Journal of Political Science 14 (1984), 369-85.
  • 13
    • 0040477281 scopus 로고
    • London: Routledge
    • I elaborate on this in my Why Posterity Matters (London: Routledge, 1995).
    • (1995) Why Posterity Matters
  • 14
    • 85080789552 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course, the system he offered was more complicated, but its details are beyond the scope of this article
    • Of course, the system he offered was more complicated, but its details are beyond the scope of this article.
  • 16
    • 0348064032 scopus 로고
    • Three fallacies concerning majorities, minorities, and democratic politics
    • J.W. Chapman and A. Wertheimer, eds., New York: New York University Press
    • See the discussion of this argument in I. Shapiro, "Three fallacies concerning majorities, minorities, and democratic politics", in J.W. Chapman and A. Wertheimer, eds., Majorities and Minorities (Nomos XXXII) (New York: New York University Press, 1990), 79-125.
    • (1990) Majorities and Minorities (Nomos XXXII) , pp. 79-125
    • Shapiro, I.1
  • 17
    • 84936526619 scopus 로고
    • Berkeley: University of California Press, "In a strong democratic community ... the individual members are transformed, through their participation in common seeing and common work, into citizens."
    • He actually thought that this internal instrumentalism - and the educative effect -would, in tending to make people more altruistic, produce both a more moral participation and better decisions. For a similar view, see B. Barber, Strong Democracy (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984), 42: "In a strong democratic community ... the individual members are transformed, through their participation in common seeing and common work, into citizens."
    • (1984) Strong Democracy , pp. 42
    • Barber, B.1
  • 18
    • 85080635091 scopus 로고
    • Chicago: Chicago University Press
    • Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1958.
    • (1958)
  • 19
    • 85080729165 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Chan and Miller's argument is perhaps a more sophisticated version of this sort of position, because they distinguish between the level at which one decides to join the political process and the level at which one is already involved. The motivation for political activities in the latter isinstrumental, they argue, whereas "in the context of constitutional debate, where citizens ask themselves what institutions to adopt or what changes ought to be made to their present institutions ... it would be relevant to cite psychological by-products ... [for choosing A rather than B]". See Chan and Miller, supra n.7, at 97.
  • 20
    • 0005169178 scopus 로고
    • Hannah Arendt and the idea of Citizenship
    • C. Mouffe, ed., London: Verso, 146
    • M.P. d'Entrèves. "Hannah Arendt and the idea of Citizenship", in C. Mouffe, ed., Dimensions of Radical Democracy (London: Verso, 1992), 145-68, at 146.
    • (1992) Dimensions of Radical Democracy , pp. 145-168
    • D'Entrèves, M.P.1
  • 22
    • 0003973918 scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • Interesting comments on the "professionals" in the history of politics can be found in C. Castoriadis, Philosophy, Politics, Autonomy (New York: Oxford University Press, 1991), 108-109.
    • (1991) Philosophy, Politics, Autonomy , pp. 108-109
    • Castoriadis, C.1
  • 23
    • 85080774019 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Elster makes this claim: supra n.2, at 126-7
    • Elster makes this claim: supra n.2, at 126-7.
  • 24
    • 84905064138 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Public choice versus democracy
    • in Chapman and Wertheimer
    • See supra n.4. On the other hand, see R. Hardin, "Public choice versus democracy", in Chapman and Wertheimer, supra n.12, at 184-203.
    • Supra N.12 , pp. 184-203
    • Hardin, R.1
  • 25
    • 84935895107 scopus 로고
    • Rationality, Morality and Collective Choice
    • Elster argues that the enjoyment of politics is simply a by-product of decision-making, and that, finally, one enjoys politics more if one is successful (at 147).
    • See, for example, Elster's "Rationality, Morality and Collective Choice", Ethics 86 (1985), 136-55. Elster argues that the enjoyment of politics is simply a by-product of decision-making, and that, finally, one enjoys politics more if one is successful (at 147).
    • (1985) Ethics , vol.86 , pp. 136-155
    • Elster's1
  • 26
    • 0003573418 scopus 로고
    • New Haven: Yale University Press
    • Habermas, Benhabib and Miller may still reply that the computer example does not apply to their model, which consists in reaching the best decision through deliberation. But to see why it does apply, imagine a more sophisticated computer which weighs the different arguments and even develops by itself the various possible answers each side can raise to the others' arguments, in such a way that it eventually reaches the best decisions. It seems to me that we would still resent such a system because what we value is that we participate actively in the democratic game. Notice also that the computer model is different from the model put forward by James Fishkin in his Democracy and Deliberation: New Directions for Democratic Reform (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1991).
    • (1991) Democracy and Deliberation: New Directions for Democratic Reform
    • Fishkin, J.1
  • 27
    • 85080732309 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Michael Walzer makes this sort of claim: see his "The civil society", in Mouffe, supra n.16, at 89-97.
    • Michael Walzer makes this sort of claim: see his "The civil society", in Mouffe, supra n.16, at 89-97.
  • 28
    • 0003827327 scopus 로고
    • Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1993, originally published
    • See B. Crick, In Defence of Politics (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1993, originally published 1962), 56.
    • (1962) In Defence of Politics , pp. 56
    • Crick, B.1
  • 29
    • 0007192268 scopus 로고
    • An epistemic conception of democracy
    • See J. Cohen, "An epistemic conception of democracy", Ethics 97 (1986), 27-40.
    • (1986) Ethics , vol.97 , pp. 27-40
    • Cohen, J.1
  • 30
    • 0344499022 scopus 로고
    • Voting and democracy
    • For a critique of this view see T. Christian, "Voting and democracy", Canadian Journal of Philosophy 25 (1995), 395-414.
    • (1995) Canadian Journal of Philosophy , vol.25 , pp. 395-414
    • Christian, T.1
  • 31
    • 85080769288 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the face of it, these decisions are indeed bureaucratic and hence the question of whether they are democratic or not is irrelevant. But, in fact, these decisions affect or are based on the budget, which is debated and voted on in parliament, and has the status of legislation.
    • On the face of it, these decisions are indeed bureaucratic and hence the question of whether they are democratic or not is irrelevant. But, in fact, these decisions affect or are based on the budget, which is debated and voted on in parliament, and has the status of legislation.
  • 32
    • 84977216964 scopus 로고
    • Secondary associations and democratic governance
    • See J. Cohen and J. Rogers, "Secondary associations and democratic governance", Politics and Society 20 (1992), 393-471;
    • (1992) Politics and Society , vol.20 , pp. 393-471
    • Cohen, J.1    Rogers, J.2


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.