메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 97, Issue 2, 2000, Pages 131-136

Prosaic possibilism

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 52849135176     PISSN: 00318116     EISSN: 15730883     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1023/A:1008349904432     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (13)

References (15)
  • 2
    • 18144428656 scopus 로고
    • Oughts, Options, and Actualism
    • 1 take the example of Procrastinate from this article
    • See Frank Jackson and Robert Pargetter, "Oughts, Options, and Actualism", Philosophical Review 95 (1986) pp. 233-255.1 take the example of Procrastinate from this article.
    • (1986) Philosophical Review , vol.95 , pp. 233-255
    • Jackson, F.1    Pargetter, R.2
  • 3
    • 52849092225 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Consult the numerous references cited in the two works mentioned above
    • Consult the numerous references cited in the two works mentioned above.
  • 4
    • 84960589853 scopus 로고
    • Contrary-to-Duty Imperatives and Deontic Logic
    • Roderick Chisholm, "Contrary-to-Duty Imperatives and Deontic Logic", Analysis 24 (1963) pp. 33-36.
    • (1963) Analysis , vol.24 , pp. 33-36
    • Chisholm, R.1
  • 5
    • 84925141413 scopus 로고
    • Conditional Obligation and Detachment
    • "Conditional Obligation and Detachment", Canadian Journal of Philosophy 16 (1986) pp. 11-26.
    • (1986) Canadian Journal of Philosophy , vol.16 , pp. 11-26
  • 6
    • 52849089225 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This ranking (structurally similar to the Procrastinate case) most effectively highlights the debate between actualists and possibilists, since it commits actualists to asserting that at T1 Smith has an obligation not to tell at T2 that he will help at T3.
  • 7
    • 52849088214 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Zimmerman endorses not only deontic detachment but also (what he calls) "necessity detachment" (p. 121). According to the latter rule, S has an unconditional obligation to do A whenever (i) S has an obligation to do A, on the condition that B is true, and (ii) S cannot make B not true. As I explain in (1986), necessity detachment follows as a special case from (RD).
  • 8
    • 34250127938 scopus 로고
    • Subsidiary Obligation
    • The counterexample which Zimmerman offers in (1996, p. 130) unfortunately is based upon a typographical error. Employing Zimmerman's nomenclature, (4.54) does not follow by (RD) from (4.18a), (4.52) and (4.53), since (4.53) fails to assert the requisite claim that the condition of the relevant conditional obligation is satisfied
    • This example is taken from Zimmerman, "Subsidiary Obligation", Philosophical Studies 50 (1986) p. 68. The counterexample which Zimmerman offers in (1996, p. 130) unfortunately is based upon a typographical error. Employing Zimmerman's nomenclature, (4.54) does not follow by (RD) from (4.18a), (4.52) and (4.53), since (4.53) fails to assert the requisite claim that the condition of the relevant conditional obligation is satisfied.
    • (1986) Philosophical Studies , vol.50 , pp. 68
  • 9
    • 52849108602 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • An analogous case, related to Chisholm's paradox, may be constructed as follows. Suppose that it is true at T1 that Smith will help at T3, that telling-andhelping and not-telling-and-not-helping are the two best outcomes, and that the remaining outcomes are equally bad. Then (2) and (3) are true on Zimmerman's semantics, (1) is false, and there is no obligation at T1 not to help at T3. (See (1996, pp. 118-119) for the relevant truth conditions.) An obligation at T1 to tell at T2 follows by (RD). Yet that final claim is not true on possibilist semantics.
  • 10
    • 52849098495 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Zimmerman (1996, p. 97). The obligation is remote because T1 is earlier than T3
    • Zimmerman (1996, p. 97). The obligation is remote because T1 is earlier than T3.
  • 11
    • 52849089839 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Zimmerman (1996, p. 133) for his distinction between primary and subsidiary obligation
    • See Zimmerman (1996, p. 133) for his distinction between primary and subsidiary obligation.
  • 12
    • 52849131629 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is transparent in Zimmerman's writings. For proof that some actualists too make this assumption, see Jackson and Pargetter (1986, p. 241)
    • This is transparent in Zimmerman's writings. For proof that some actualists too make this assumption, see Jackson and Pargetter (1986, p. 241).
  • 13
    • 52849129478 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Zimmerman articulates this possibilist worry in (1996, p. 193)
    • Zimmerman articulates this possibilist worry in (1996, p. 193).
  • 14
    • 52849107115 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The second clause covers situations in which either S would act in a non-ideal manner, or there is no fact of the matter as to how S would act
    • The second clause covers situations in which either S would act in a non-ideal manner, or there is no fact of the matter as to how S would act.
  • 15
    • 52849124943 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I thank Michael Zimmerman for some very helpful comments on a draft of this paper
    • I thank Michael Zimmerman for some very helpful comments on a draft of this paper.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.