메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 28, Issue 1, 1998, Pages 21-32

Disjunction and disjunctive syllogism

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 52849132052     PISSN: 00455091     EISSN: 19110820     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1080/00455091.1998.10715969     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (1)

References (15)
  • 1
    • 85063699861 scopus 로고
    • The Lewis argument might better be attributed to Albert of Saxony, who had it all essentials some six centuries before Lewis, or perhaps to William of Soissons the twelfth century. For the former see, e.g., J.M. Bochenski, second edition (Freiburg and Munich: Karl Alber for the latter, Christopher Martin, ‘Williams Machine,’ Journal of Philosophy83 (1986) 564–72 (I owe this reference to Stephen Read
    • 1962. Formale Logik 237–8. The Lewis argument might better be attributed to Albert of Saxony, who had it in all essentials some six centuries before Lewis, or perhaps to William of Soissons in the twelfth century. For the former see, e.g., J.M. Bochenski, second edition (Freiburg and Munich: Karl Alber for the latter, Christopher Martin, ‘William's Machine,’ Journal of Philosophy83 (1986) 564–72 (I owe this reference to Stephen Read).
    • (1962) Formale Logik , pp. 237-238
  • 2
    • 1842305105 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Ma: The MIT Press, Colin Allen and Michael Hand, xii and 18–19
    • 1992. Logic Primer Cambridge, Ma: The MIT Press. Colin Allen and Michael Hand, xii and 18–19
    • (1992) Logic Primer
  • 3
    • 84979113117 scopus 로고
    • Meaning and Proofs: On the Conflict between Classical and Intuitionist Logic
    • See and ‘Proofs and the Meaning and Completeness of the Logical Constants,’ J. Hintikka, I. Niiniluoto, and E. Saarinen, Essays on Mathematical and Philosophical Logic (Dordrecht: Reidel 1979) 25–40
    • Prawitz, Dag. 1977. ‘Meaning and Proofs: On the Conflict between Classical and Intuitionist Logic,’. Theoria, 43: 2–40. See and ‘Proofs and the Meaning and Completeness of the Logical Constants,’ in J. Hintikka, I. Niiniluoto, and E. Saarinen, Essays on Mathematical and Philosophical Logic (Dordrecht: Reidel 1979) 25–40.
    • (1977) Theoria , vol.43 , pp. 2-40
    • Prawitz, D.1
  • 5
    • 84941949267 scopus 로고
    • Tonk, Plonk and Plink
    • reprinted P.F. Strawson, Philosophical Logic (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1967) 132–7
    • Belnap, Nuel. 1962. ‘Tonk, Plonk and Plink,’. Analysis, 22: 130–4. reprinted in P.F. Strawson, Philosophical Logic (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1967) 132–7
    • (1962) Analysis , vol.22 , pp. 130-134
    • Belnap, N.1
  • 6
    • 0004361638 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Blackwell, and Thinking About Logic (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1994), 60, 160, 163
    • Read, Stephen. 1988. Relevant Logic 31–4. Oxford: Blackwell. and Thinking About Logic (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1994), 60, 160, 163
    • (1988) Relevant Logic , pp. 31-34
    • Read, S.1
  • 7
    • 61949266858 scopus 로고
    • ‘The Source of the Concept of Truth,’ in
    • Boolos G., (ed), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, at 7–8,. Edited by
    • Dummett, Michael. 1990. “ ‘The Source of the Concept of Truth,’ in ”. In Meaning and Method: Essays in Honor of Hilary Putnam Edited by: Boolos, George. 1–15. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. at 7–8
    • (1990) Meaning and Method: Essays in Honor of Hilary Putnam , pp. 1-15
    • Dummett, M.1
  • 8
    • 0003398488 scopus 로고
    • London: Duckworth, It should perhaps be noted that Dummett does describe DS as a fundamental form of argument, The Logical Basis, 293
    • Dummett, Michael. 1991. The Logical Basis of Metaphysics 256London: Duckworth. It should perhaps be noted that Dummett does describe DS as a fundamental form of argument, The Logical Basis, 293.
    • (1991) The Logical Basis of Metaphysics , pp. 256
    • Dummett, M.1
  • 9
    • 85063705375 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ‘The Source,’ 7–8
    • Dummett. ‘The Source,’ 7–8
    • Dummett1
  • 10
    • 33646148548 scopus 로고
    • Classical Harmony: Rules of Inference and the Meaning of the Logical Constants
    • See at 90, n. 31, for a proof that a conditional containing the Sasaki hook is locally weakest the sense given the text. As is well known, adding an intuitionist conditional to quantum logic collapses it to classical logic
    • Milne, Peter. 1994. ‘Classical Harmony: Rules of Inference and the Meaning of the Logical Constants,’. Synthese, 100: 49–94. See at 90, n. 31, for a proof that a conditional containing the Sasaki hook is locally weakest in the sense given in the text. As is well known, adding an intuitionist conditional to quantum logic collapses it to classical logic.
    • (1994) Synthese , vol.100 , pp. 49-94
    • Milne, P.1
  • 11
    • 33644701914 scopus 로고
    • Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, second edition
    • Tennant, Neil. 1990. Natural Logic Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. second edition
    • (1990) Natural Logic
    • Tennant, N.1
  • 12
    • 85063698613 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ‘Classical Harmony,’ 76
    • Milne. ‘Classical Harmony,’ 76
    • Milne1
  • 13
    • 85063697352 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I mean this comparison of strength quite strictly, so that, for example, logics that contain DNE but lack other principles of intuitionist logic and may therefore intuitively be regarded as quite weak are neither stronger nor weaker than intuitionist logic. One is, of course, entitled to view the absence of DNE as a weakness of intuitionist logic. Discussion with Stephen Read prompted this footnote
    • I mean this comparison of strength quite strictly, so that, for example, logics that contain DNE but lack other principles of intuitionist logic and may therefore intuitively be regarded as quite weak are neither stronger nor weaker than intuitionist logic. One is, of course, entitled to view the absence of DNE as a weakness of intuitionist logic. Discussion with Stephen Read prompted this footnote.
  • 15
    • 85063698675 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • + , Segerbergs JX, rather than intuitionist logic, would have played a much more prominent role here had Allen and Hand chosen +-introduction and orthodox v-elimination as the rules governing their disjunction, admittedly a most unlikely event
    • + , Segerberg's JX, rather than intuitionist logic, would have played a much more prominent role here had Allen and Hand chosen +-introduction and orthodox v-elimination as the rules governing their disjunction, admittedly a most unlikely event.
    • Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic , pp. 353


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.