메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 96, Issue 2, 1999, Pages 147-162

Other things being equal

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 52549103457     PISSN: 00318116     EISSN: 15730883     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (10)

References (26)
  • 1
    • 24944432006 scopus 로고
    • Provisos: A problem concerning the inferential function of scientific theories
    • Nancy Cartwright provides such reasons in How the laws of physics lie (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983), though her view appears to be that laws are unhedged and therefore false. See also Carl Hempel, "Provisos: a problem concerning the inferential function of scientific theories", Erkenntnis 28 (1988), pp. 147-164
    • (1988) Erkenntnis , vol.28 , pp. 147-164
    • Hempel, C.1
  • 2
    • 0002632988 scopus 로고
    • The many sciences and the one world
    • , and Geoffrey Joseph, "The many sciences and the one world", The Journal of Philosophy 77, 12 (1980), pp. 773-791.
    • (1980) The Journal of Philosophy , vol.77 , Issue.12 , pp. 773-791
    • Joseph, G.1
  • 3
    • 0040484497 scopus 로고
    • You can fool some of the people all of the time, everything else being equal; hedged laws and psychological explanations
    • Jerry Fodor, "You can fool some of the people all of the time, everything else being equal; hedged laws and psychological explanations" Mind 100 (1991), pp. 19-34;
    • (1991) Mind , vol.100 , pp. 19-34
    • Fodor, J.1
  • 4
    • 0002568780 scopus 로고
    • Celeris paribus laws
    • Steven Schiffer, "Celeris paribus laws", Mind 100 (1991), pp. 1-17.
    • (1991) Mind , vol.100 , pp. 1-17
    • Schiffer, S.1
  • 5
    • 53149117937 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • 'Rise' and 'fall' appear in mutually exclusive senses, neither term applying in case of a fluctuation. This is what makes these generalizations a contrary pair.
  • 6
    • 0003799915 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge Mass.: MIT Press
    • W.V.O. Quine, in Word and Object (Cambridge Mass.: MIT Press, 1960), claims that there is no way at all to paraphrase sentences with the modifier 'ceteris paribus' without fixing the contexts in which they are used: That the idioms involving it remain useful is due to those clues to the scope of "ceteris paribus" that are afforded by the context or other circumstances of the particular utterance. This is why the paraphrasing of such idioms into a satis- factorily explicit canonical notation is often practicable occasion by occasion and altogether hopeless idiom by idiom (p. 225). We shall see that Quine is both right and wrong about 'ceteris paribus'. The inter-pretation of this modifier is indeed sensitive to circumstances of the particular utterance, just as the interpretations of indexicals and other context-sensitive expressions are. But, as we shall see, ceteris paribus generalizations have canonical paraphrases anyway, involving other context-sensitive expressions.
    • (1960) Word and Object
    • Quine, W.V.O.1
  • 9
    • 53149127359 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • That ideal objects enter into the interpretation of certain generalizations might seem to render them vacuous, since as a matter of physical necessity these ideal objects do not exist. In section 5,1 shall consider paraphrases that do not introduce such fictions.
  • 10
    • 0004279274 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge Mass.: MIT Press
    • Elliot Sober, The nature of selection (Cambridge Mass.: MIT Press, 1984), p. 27.
    • (1984) The Nature of Selection , pp. 27
    • Sober, E.1
  • 15
    • 53149128812 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The theory-observation distinction
    • From André Kukla, "The theory-observation distinction", The Philosophical Review 105, 2(1996), p. 201.
    • (1996) The Philosophical Review , vol.105 , Issue.2 , pp. 201
    • Kukla, A.1
  • 17
    • 0037718761 scopus 로고
    • When other things aren't equal: Saving ceteris paribus laws from vacuity
    • Paul Pietroski and Georges Rey, "When other things aren't equal: saving ceteris paribus laws from vacuity", The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 46 (1995), pp. 81-110. By "vacuous" generalizations they appear tomean those that are trivially true, not those that are elliptical or fail in some other way to express propositions.
    • (1995) The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science , vol.46 , pp. 81-110
    • Pietroski, P.1    Rey, G.2
  • 18
    • 53149148198 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Which is not to say that this belief could not be adopted by someone with beliefs different from ours. Believability, in the sense I intend here, is a subjective notion; whether one can reasonably adopt a new belief depends on the beliefs he already has.
  • 19
    • 53149151932 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Though it is, of course, a reasonable way for Buridan's ass to settle on a pile of hay. Choices between piles of hay are unlike choices between beliefs in several ways that can account for the reasonableness of random choice in the one case but not in the other. The ass ought to choose one or the other pile. But there is no need for us to adopt one or the other belief. Also, unlike piles of hay, beliefs have contents, and these contents can to a greater or lesser extent be justified.
  • 20
    • 0000296665 scopus 로고
    • Studies in the logic of explanation
    • Carl Hempel and Paul Oppenheim, "Studies in the logic of explanation", Philosophy of Science 15 (1948), pp. 135-175.
    • (1948) Philosophy of Science , vol.15 , pp. 135-175
    • Hempel, C.1    Oppenheim, P.2
  • 22
    • 0009166341 scopus 로고
    • Idealizations and the testing of theories by experimentation
    • Peter Achinstein and Owen Hannaway (eds.) Cambridge Mass.: MIT Press
    • Ronald Laymon discusses a further difficulty that hedged laws bring for the covering-law model. See his "Idealizations and the testing of theories by experimentation', in Peter Achinstein and Owen Hannaway (eds.) Observation, experiment, and hypothesis in modern physical science (Cambridge Mass.: MIT Press, 1985).
    • (1985) Observation, Experiment, and Hypothesis in Modern Physical Science
    • Laymon, R.1
  • 23
    • 6544245448 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fainthearted conditionals
    • Michael Morreau, "Fainthearted conditionals", The Journal of Philosophy 94, 4 (1997), pp. 187-211.
    • (1997) The Journal of Philosophy , vol.94 , Issue.4 , pp. 187-211
    • Morreau, M.1
  • 24
    • 53149084181 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Satisfaction of this requirement does not entail that 'ceteris paribus' also expresses a provision when it appears in a generalization. Indeed, such a further requirement would not be realistic. The ceteris paribus generalization relating supply and price, for example, does not express that, conditional on some single proposition p, every increase in the supply of every product will cause an increase in price.
  • 25
    • 53149144757 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This assumption is implicit in the use of a "proviso function" to interpret conditionals with this modifier. This function determines the provision expressed by 'ceteris paribus', when a particular sentence with this modifier is interpreted in any given context. See Morreau, op. cit., pp. 198-199.
  • 26
    • 53149093672 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This assumption is implicit in the use of a "proviso function" to interpret conditionals with this modifier. This function determines the provision expressed by 'ceteris paribus', when a particular sentence with this modifier is interpreted in any given context. See Morreau, op. cit., pp. 198-199.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.