메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 76, Issue 4, 2008, Pages 914-932

Hohfeld's first amendment

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 51849091516     PISSN: 00168076     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (23)

References (84)
  • 2
    • 51849154180 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Near v. Minnesota ex rel. Olson. 283 U.S. 697, 707 (1931); Stromberg v. California, 283 U.S. 359, 368 (1931); Gitlow v. New York, 268 U.S. 652, 666 (1925).
    • Near v. Minnesota ex rel. Olson. 283 U.S. 697, 707 (1931); Stromberg v. California, 283 U.S. 359, 368 (1931); Gitlow v. New York, 268 U.S. 652, 666 (1925).
  • 3
    • 0002953848 scopus 로고
    • Some Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied in Judicial Reasoning, 23
    • See generally
    • See generally Wesley Newcomb Hohfeld, Some Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied in Judicial Reasoning, 23 YALE L.J. 16 (1913).
    • (1913) YALE L.J , vol.16
    • Newcomb Hohfeld, W.1
  • 4
    • 51849084189 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Compare, e.g., Phelps v. President of Colby Coll., 595 A.2d 403, 403 (Me. 1991) ([T]he first amendment secures only the right to be free from governmental interference . . . .). with Papish v. Bd. of Curators of Univ. of Mo., 410 U.S. 667, 670 (1973) (restricting state university's power to curtail dissemination of ideas).
    • Compare, e.g., Phelps v. President of Colby Coll., 595 A.2d 403, 403 (Me. 1991) ("[T]he first amendment secures only the right to be free from governmental interference . . . ."). with Papish v. Bd. of Curators of Univ. of Mo., 410 U.S. 667, 670 (1973) (restricting state university's power to curtail dissemination of ideas).
  • 5
    • 51849089566 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Compare George v. Pacific-CSC Work Furlough, 91 F.3d 1227, 1230 (9th Cir. 1996) (finding that employee alleging infringement of First Amendment rights by private employer must make showing of state action), with Rankin v. McPherson, 483 U.S. 378, 383 (1987) (applying First Amendment to speech in a government workplace), Connick v. Myers, 461 U.S. 138, 140 (1983) (recognizing some free speech rights in government workplace), and Pickering v. Bd. of Educ. 391 U.S. 563, 574-75 (1968) (holding that public employee has some First Amendment rights against dismissal based on the content of a public speech).
    • Compare George v. Pacific-CSC Work Furlough, 91 F.3d 1227, 1230 (9th Cir. 1996) (finding that employee alleging infringement of First Amendment rights by private employer must make showing of state action), with Rankin v. McPherson, 483 U.S. 378, 383 (1987) (applying First Amendment to speech in a government workplace), Connick v. Myers, 461 U.S. 138, 140 (1983) (recognizing some free speech rights in government workplace), and Pickering v. Bd. of Educ. 391 U.S. 563, 574-75 (1968) (holding that public employee has some First Amendment rights against dismissal based on the content of a public speech).
  • 6
    • 51849090925 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Pruneyard Shopping Ctr. v. Robins, 447 U.S. 74, 81 (1980, holding that states may impose access obligations on owners of private property, but not if those requirements would restrict the owners' own First Amendment rights, Compare Hudgens v. NLRB, 424 U.S. 507, 521 (1976, and Lloyd v. Tanner, 407 U.S. 551, 570 (1972, both finding no constitutional guarantee to freedom of expression in a privately owned shopping center, with Southeastern Promotions, Ltd. v. Conrad, 420 U.S. 546, 556 (1975, concluding that content-based denial of the use of a municipal auditorium constitutes a violation of the First Amendment, The significant exception to the statement in the text, although not especially germane here, is the so-called company town. See Marsh v. Alabama, 326 U.S. 501, 508-09 1946, holding that a resident of a company-owned town is afforded no less First Amendment protection than any other citizen, See generally Kevin Francis O'Neil
    • Cf. Pruneyard Shopping Ctr. v. Robins, 447 U.S. 74, 81 (1980) (holding that states may impose access obligations on owners of private property, but not if those requirements would restrict the owners' own First Amendment rights). Compare Hudgens v. NLRB, 424 U.S. 507, 521 (1976), and Lloyd v. Tanner, 407 U.S. 551, 570 (1972) (both finding no constitutional guarantee to freedom of expression in a privately owned shopping center), with Southeastern Promotions, Ltd. v. Conrad, 420 U.S. 546, 556 (1975) (concluding that content-based denial of the use of a municipal auditorium constitutes a violation of the First Amendment). The significant exception to the statement in the text, although not especially germane here, is the so-called company town. See Marsh v. Alabama, 326 U.S. 501, 508-09 (1946) (holding that a resident of a company-owned town is afforded no less First Amendment protection than any other citizen). See generally Kevin Francis O'Neill, Privatizing Public Forums to Eliminate Dissent. 5 FIRST AMENDMENT L. REV. 201 (2007).
  • 7
    • 51849138937 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is important to emphasize that these are two distinct choices. It is true that sometimes the grant of positive rights to one person may interfere with another's negative rights, as with the clash between Pat Tornillo's positive right to access and the corollary restriction on the Miami Herald's, negative right to control the content of its newspaper. See Miami Herald Publ'g Co. v. Tornillo, 418 U.S. 241, 247-48, 258 (1974). In most cases, however, that linkage is absent, and the decision whether to allow claims by speakers of positive rights against the state for access or funding, for example, is analytically distinct from the questions about the extent to which government may restrict the speaking or writing of nongovernmental speakers or publishers.
    • It is important to emphasize that these are two distinct choices. It is true that sometimes the grant of positive rights to one person may interfere with another's negative rights, as with the clash between Pat Tornillo's positive right to access and the corollary restriction on the Miami Herald's, negative right to control the content of its newspaper. See Miami Herald Publ'g Co. v. Tornillo, 418 U.S. 241, 247-48, 258 (1974). In most cases, however, that linkage is absent, and the decision whether to allow claims by speakers of positive rights against the state for access or funding, for example, is analytically distinct from the questions about the extent to which government may restrict the speaking or writing of nongovernmental speakers or publishers.
  • 8
    • 51849123607 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Although the public forum doctrine does, in effect, create mandatory access for purposes of speaking to streets, parks, and sidewalks, see Frisby v. Schultz, 487 U.S. 474, 481 (1988, Perry Educ. Ass'n v. Perry Local Educators' Ass'n, 460 U.S. 37, 45 (1983, Hague v. Comm. for Indus. Org, 307 U.S. 496, 515 1939, there is nothing in the cases that would require a municipality to provide streets, parks, or sidewalks if it had none. This is, of course, highly counterfactual, but it does underscore the way in which the doctrine, even here, requires the state to allow speakers to use some of the state's resources for speaking, but does not actually require the state to have such resources
    • Although the public forum doctrine does, in effect, create mandatory access for purposes of speaking to streets, parks, and sidewalks, see Frisby v. Schultz, 487 U.S. 474, 481 (1988); Perry Educ. Ass'n v. Perry Local Educators' Ass'n, 460 U.S. 37, 45 (1983); Hague v. Comm. for Indus. Org., 307 U.S. 496, 515 (1939), there is nothing in the cases that would require a municipality to provide streets, parks, or sidewalks if it had none. This is, of course, highly counterfactual, but it does underscore the way in which the doctrine, even here, requires the state to allow speakers to use some of the state's resources for speaking, but does not actually require the state to have such resources.
  • 9
    • 51849153669 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Brandenburg v. Ohio, 395 U.S. 444 (1969) (per curiam).
    • Brandenburg v. Ohio, 395 U.S. 444 (1969) (per curiam).
  • 10
    • 51849140373 scopus 로고
    • Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254
    • N.Y. Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254 (1963).
    • (1963) N.Y. Times
  • 11
    • 45249083219 scopus 로고
    • U.S. 15
    • Cohen v. California, 403 U.S. 15, 16 (1971).
    • (1971) California , vol.403 , pp. 16
    • Cohen, V.1
  • 12
    • 51849106820 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • N.Y. Times Co. v. United States, 403 U.S. 713, 714 (1971) (per curiam).
    • N.Y. Times Co. v. United States, 403 U.S. 713, 714 (1971) (per curiam).
  • 13
    • 51849152270 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Brandenburg, 395 U.S. at 445.
    • Brandenburg, 395 U.S. at 445.
  • 14
    • 51849110964 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • N.Y. Times Co. v. United States, 403 U.S. at 714; Sullivan, 376 U.S. at 256.
    • N.Y. Times Co. v. United States, 403 U.S. at 714; Sullivan, 376 U.S. at 256.
  • 15
    • 51849103647 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cohen, 403 U.S. at 16.
    • Cohen, 403 U.S. at 16.
  • 16
    • 51849146480 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Gov't of the Republic of S. Afr. v Grootboom & Others 2000 (1) SA 46 (CC) at 14 (S. Afr.).
    • See Gov't of the Republic of S. Afr. v Grootboom & Others 2000 (1) SA 46 (CC) at 14 (S. Afr.).
  • 17
    • 32144433678 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Minister of Health & Others v. Treatment Action Campaign & Others 2002 (5) SA 721 (CC) at 723 (S. Afr.); Colleen M. Flood, Lance Gable & Lawrence O. Gostin, Legislating and Litigating Health Care Rights Around the World, 33 J.L. MED. & ETHICS 636, 636, 639 (2005).
    • See Minister of Health & Others v. Treatment Action Campaign & Others 2002 (5) SA 721 (CC) at 723 (S. Afr.); Colleen M. Flood, Lance Gable & Lawrence O. Gostin, Legislating and Litigating Health Care Rights Around the World, 33 J.L. MED. & ETHICS 636, 636, 639 (2005).
  • 18
    • 77749338512 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Enforcement of Social and Economic Rights, 22
    • See generally
    • See generally Albie Sachs, Enforcement of Social and Economic Rights, 22 AM. U. INT'L L. REV. 673 (2007);
    • (2007) AM. U. INT'L L. REV , vol.673
    • Sachs, A.1
  • 19
    • 79961021475 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aspirational Principles or Enforceable Rights? The Future for Socio-Economic Rights in National Law, 22
    • Ellen Wiles, Aspirational Principles or Enforceable Rights? The Future for Socio-Economic Rights in National Law, 22 AM. U. INT'L L. REV. 35, 37-38, 48 (2006).
    • (2006) AM. U. INT'L L. REV , vol.35 , Issue.37-38 , pp. 48
    • Wiles, E.1
  • 20
    • 51849145630 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • San Antonio Indep. Sch. Dist. v. Rodriguez, 411 U.S. 1 (1973).
    • San Antonio Indep. Sch. Dist. v. Rodriguez, 411 U.S. 1 (1973).
  • 21
    • 51849137301 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 35
    • Id. at 35.
  • 22
    • 51849131905 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Sotirios A. Barber, Welfare and the Instrumental Constitution, 42 AM. J. JURIS. 159, 161 (1997).
    • See Sotirios A. Barber, Welfare and the Instrumental Constitution, 42 AM. J. JURIS. 159, 161 (1997).
  • 23
    • 51849123199 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Supreme Court's view appears to be shared by both the American people and the American political system. In a country with fewer guarantees to health care than exist in almost all other industrialized democracies, with a lower top marginal income tax rate than exists in most other industrialized countries, and with a higher education system in which private colleges and universities are very heavily represented, it would be hard to maintain that the Supreme Court's view of positive rights is out of step with longstanding, prevailing American views about the role of the state. See Frederick Schauer, The Exceptional First Amendment, in AMERICAN EXCEPTIONALISM AND HUMAN RIGHTS 29, 45 (Michael Ignatieff ed., 2005).
    • The Supreme Court's view appears to be shared by both the American people and the American political system. In a country with fewer guarantees to health care than exist in almost all other industrialized democracies, with a lower top marginal income tax rate than exists in most other industrialized countries, and with a higher education system in which private colleges and universities are very heavily represented, it would be hard to maintain that the Supreme Court's view of positive rights is out of step with longstanding, prevailing American views about the role of the state. See Frederick Schauer, The Exceptional First Amendment, in AMERICAN EXCEPTIONALISM AND HUMAN RIGHTS 29, 45 (Michael Ignatieff ed., 2005).
  • 24
    • 51849110257 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rodriguez, 411 U.S. at 35-37.
    • Rodriguez, 411 U.S. at 35-37.
  • 25
    • 51849099352 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Camps Newfound/Owatonna, Inc. v. Town of Harrison, 520 U.S. 564, 580-81 (1997); Bacchus Imports, Ltd. v. Dias, 468 U.S. 263, 276 (1984); Kassel v. Consol. Freightways Corp. of Del., 450 U.S. 662, 678 (1981); Hughes v. Oklahoma, 441 U.S. 322, 337-38 (1979).
    • See, e.g., Camps Newfound/Owatonna, Inc. v. Town of Harrison, 520 U.S. 564, 580-81 (1997); Bacchus Imports, Ltd. v. Dias, 468 U.S. 263, 276 (1984); Kassel v. Consol. Freightways Corp. of Del., 450 U.S. 662, 678 (1981); Hughes v. Oklahoma, 441 U.S. 322, 337-38 (1979).
  • 26
    • 51849126823 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Dunn v. Blumstein, 405 U.S. 330, 336 (1972); Harper v. Va. Bd. of Elections, 383 U.S. 663, 665 (1966).
    • See Dunn v. Blumstein, 405 U.S. 330, 336 (1972); Harper v. Va. Bd. of Elections, 383 U.S. 663, 665 (1966).
  • 28
    • 51849133474 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Alabama v. Shelton, 535 U.S. 654, 679 (2002) (providing an affirmative right to counsel for any defendant); Ake v. Oklahoma, 470 U.S. 68, 83 (1985) (noting an affirmative right to a psychiatrist where a criminal defendant demonstrates that his sanity at the time of the offense will be a significant factor at trial); Argesinger v. Hamlin, 407 U.S. 25, 37 (1972) (holding that no person may be imprisoned for any offense, whether classified as petty, misdemeanor, or felony, unless he was represented by counsel at his trial); Gideon v. Wainwright, 372 U.S. 335, 343-44 (1963) (recognizing an affirmative right to assistance of counsel in all criminal prosecutions).
    • See Alabama v. Shelton, 535 U.S. 654, 679 (2002) (providing an affirmative right to counsel for any defendant); Ake v. Oklahoma, 470 U.S. 68, 83 (1985) (noting an affirmative right to a psychiatrist where a criminal defendant demonstrates that his sanity at the time of the offense will be a significant factor at trial); Argesinger v. Hamlin, 407 U.S. 25, 37 (1972) (holding that "no person may be imprisoned for any offense, whether classified as petty, misdemeanor, or felony, unless he was represented by counsel at his trial"); Gideon v. Wainwright, 372 U.S. 335, 343-44 (1963) (recognizing an affirmative right to assistance of counsel in all criminal prosecutions).
  • 29
    • 51849108908 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Judicial caution about taking on potentially unbounded issues involved in recognizing and enforcing positive rights is of a piece with the same caution about judicial involvement with effects as opposed to intent. Clark v. Community for Creative Non-Violence, 468 U.S. 288 (1984, might be thought of as a First Amendment case, but it might also be understood as the First Amendment instantiation of larger concerns about judicial intrusiveness in too wide a range of governmental decisions, a concern exemplified by, for example, Washington v. Davis, 426 U.S. 229 1976
    • Judicial caution about taking on potentially unbounded issues involved in recognizing and enforcing positive rights is of a piece with the same caution about judicial involvement with effects as opposed to intent. Clark v. Community for Creative Non-Violence, 468 U.S. 288 (1984), might be thought of as a First Amendment case, but it might also be understood as the First Amendment instantiation of larger concerns about judicial intrusiveness in too wide a range of governmental decisions, a concern exemplified by, for example, Washington v. Davis, 426 U.S. 229 (1976).
  • 30
    • 51849094807 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hudgens v. NLRB, 424 U.S. 507, 520-21 (1976); see also Lloyd Corp. v. Tanner, 407 U.S. 531, 570 (1972) (holding that a privately owned shopping center not dedicated to public use was not under First Amendment obligation to allow protest on its premises).
    • Hudgens v. NLRB, 424 U.S. 507, 520-21 (1976); see also Lloyd Corp. v. Tanner, 407 U.S. 531, 570 (1972) (holding that a privately owned shopping center not dedicated to public use was not under First Amendment obligation to allow protest on its premises).
  • 31
    • 51849083727 scopus 로고
    • See Amalgamated Food Employees Union Local 590 v, U.S. 308
    • See Amalgamated Food Employees Union Local 590 v. Logan Valley Plaza, Inc., 391 U.S. 308, 325 (1968).
    • (1968) Logan Valley Plaza, Inc , vol.391 , pp. 325
  • 32
    • 51849122790 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Dist. Attorney for the Plymouth Dist. v. Coffey, 434 N.E.2d 1276, 1279 (Mass. 1982).
    • See Dist. Attorney for the Plymouth Dist. v. Coffey, 434 N.E.2d 1276, 1279 (Mass. 1982).
  • 33
    • 51849145631 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Moose Lodge No. 107 v. Irvis, 407 U.S. 163, 177 (1972).
    • See Moose Lodge No. 107 v. Irvis, 407 U.S. 163, 177 (1972).
  • 34
    • 51849151127 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Lockwood v. Killian, 375 A.2d 998, 1004 (Conn. 1977).
    • See Lockwood v. Killian, 375 A.2d 998, 1004 (Conn. 1977).
  • 35
    • 51849087607 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Jackson v. Metro, Edison Co., 419 U.S. 345, 358-59 (1974).
    • See Jackson v. Metro, Edison Co., 419 U.S. 345, 358-59 (1974).
  • 36
    • 84963456897 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • notes 16-18 and accompanying text
    • See supra notes 16-18 and accompanying text.
    • See supra
  • 37
    • 0006500960 scopus 로고
    • Foreword: On Protecting the Poor Through the Fourteenth Amendment, 83
    • E.g
    • E.g., Frank I. Michelman, Foreword: On Protecting the Poor Through the Fourteenth Amendment, 83 HARV. L. REV. 7 (1969);
    • (1969) HARV. L. REV , vol.7
    • Michelman, F.I.1
  • 38
    • 51849135357 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jessica Schultz, Economic and Social Rights in the United States: An Overview of the Domestic Legal Framework, HUM. RTS. BRIEF, Fall 2003, at 1, 1-4 (11, no. 1).
    • Jessica Schultz, Economic and Social Rights in the United States: An Overview of the Domestic Legal Framework, HUM. RTS. BRIEF, Fall 2003, at 1, 1-4 (vol. 11, no. 1).
  • 39
    • 51849137739 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DeShaney v. Winnebago County Dep't of Soc. Servs., 489 U.S. 189 (1989).
    • DeShaney v. Winnebago County Dep't of Soc. Servs., 489 U.S. 189 (1989).
  • 40
    • 51849151814 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Frequently to the annoyance of the rest of us
    • Frequently to the annoyance of the rest of us.
  • 41
    • 51849120555 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ronald Dworkin, in his analysis some years ago of the contretemps arising out of the refusal of the journalist Myron Farber to disclose confidential sources, Ronald Dworkin, The Rights of Myron Farber, N.Y. REV. BOOKS, Oct. 26, 1978, at 34, properly drew a distinction between those aspects of the First Amendment that could be said to reflect or embody deeper moral and political rights, such as the right to express one's political or religious views, and those aspects that are based on more contingent and more empirical considerations, such as the contingent empirical and instrumental relationship between certain forms of press rights and the effective operation of government, id.
    • Ronald Dworkin, in his analysis some years ago of the contretemps arising out of the refusal of the journalist Myron Farber to disclose confidential sources, Ronald Dworkin, The Rights of Myron Farber, N.Y. REV. BOOKS, Oct. 26, 1978, at 34, properly drew a distinction between those aspects of the First Amendment that could be said to reflect or embody deeper moral and political rights, such as the right to express one's political or religious views, and those aspects that are based on more contingent and more empirical considerations, such as the contingent empirical and instrumental relationship between certain forms of press rights and the effective operation of government, id.
  • 42
    • 51849100715 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also RONALD DWORKIN, A MATTER OF PRINCIPLE 373-80 (1985). Dworkin's concern, however, is not the same as mine, for his interest was primarily in the source of judicially enforceable rights, see id., and mine is in the nonjudicially enforceable policy dimensions of the First Amendment.
    • See also RONALD DWORKIN, A MATTER OF PRINCIPLE 373-80 (1985). Dworkin's concern, however, is not the same as mine, for his interest was primarily in the source of judicially enforceable rights, see id., and mine is in the nonjudicially enforceable policy dimensions of the First Amendment.
  • 43
    • 51849145456 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • JOHN MILTON, AREOPAGITICA (J.C. Suffolk ed., Univ. Tutorial Press 1968) (1644).
    • JOHN MILTON, AREOPAGITICA (J.C. Suffolk ed., Univ. Tutorial Press 1968) (1644).
  • 44
    • 51849113643 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Abrams v. United States, 250 U.S. 616, 630-31 (1919) (Holmes, J., dissenting).
    • Abrams v. United States, 250 U.S. 616, 630-31 (1919) (Holmes, J., dissenting).
  • 45
    • 51849167276 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • E.g., Dennis v. United States, 341 U.S. 494, 546-53 (1951) (Frankfurter, J., concurring); Gitlow v. New York, 268 U.S. 652, 673 (1925) (Holmes, J., dissenting); Int'l Bhd. of Elec. Workers v. NLRB, 181 F.2d 34, 40 (2d Cir. 1950) (Hand, C.J.).
    • E.g., Dennis v. United States, 341 U.S. 494, 546-53 (1951) (Frankfurter, J., concurring); Gitlow v. New York, 268 U.S. 652, 673 (1925) (Holmes, J., dissenting); Int'l Bhd. of Elec. Workers v. NLRB, 181 F.2d 34, 40 (2d Cir. 1950) (Hand, C.J.).
  • 46
    • 51849159489 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • JOHN STUART MILL, ON LIBERTY (D. Spitz ed., W.W. Norton & Co. Inc. 1975) (1859).
    • JOHN STUART MILL, ON LIBERTY (D. Spitz ed., W.W. Norton & Co. Inc. 1975) (1859).
  • 47
    • 51849104081 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There is an interesting debate in the political philosophy literature about whether Mill's defense of the liberty of thought and expression, or his defense of liberty in general, is in reality a utilitarian one, or whether it is ultimately based on deontological considerations that Mill may have failed to recognize or acknowledge. See generally FRED BERGER, HAPPINESS, JUSTICE, AND FREEDOM 41, 50, 199, 231-32 (1984) (discussing Mill's references to ethical considerations in relation to utility);
    • There is an interesting debate in the political philosophy literature about whether Mill's defense of the liberty of thought and expression, or his defense of liberty in general, is in reality a utilitarian one, or whether it is ultimately based on deontological considerations that Mill may have failed to recognize or acknowledge. See generally FRED BERGER, HAPPINESS, JUSTICE, AND FREEDOM 41, 50, 199, 231-32 (1984) (discussing Mill's references to ethical considerations in relation to utility);
  • 48
    • 51849088491 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • C.L. TEN, MILL ON LIBERTY 126-28 (1980) (providing a critique of Mill's dedication to utilitarianism based on his advocacy of freedom of expression);
    • C.L. TEN, MILL ON LIBERTY 126-28 (1980) (providing a critique of Mill's dedication to utilitarianism based on his advocacy of freedom of expression);
  • 49
    • 84927039598 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • James Bogen & Daniel M. Farrell, Freedom and Happiness in Mill's Defense of Liberty, 28 PHIL. Q. 325 (1978) (providing a critique of Mill's dedication to utilitarianism based on Mill's harm principle);
    • James Bogen & Daniel M. Farrell, Freedom and Happiness in Mill's Defense of Liberty, 28 PHIL. Q. 325 (1978) (providing a critique of Mill's dedication to utilitarianism based on Mill's harm principle);
  • 50
    • 51849156348 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • David O. Brink, Mill's Liberal Principles and Freedom of Expression, in MILL'S ON LIBERTY: A CRITICAL GUIDE (C.L. Ten ed., forthcoming);
    • David O. Brink, Mill's Liberal Principles and Freedom of Expression, in MILL'S ON LIBERTY: A CRITICAL GUIDE (C.L. Ten ed., forthcoming);
  • 51
    • 84937332756 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • David O. Brink, Million Principles, Freedom of Expression, and Hate Speech, 7 LEGAL THEORY 119 (2001);
    • David O. Brink, Million Principles, Freedom of Expression, and Hate Speech, 7 LEGAL THEORY 119 (2001);
  • 52
    • 3042740303 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Daniel Jacobsen, Mill on Liberty, Speech, and the Free Society, 29 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 276 (2000) (situating Mill's views on freedom of speech within larger Millian perspectives).
    • Daniel Jacobsen, Mill on Liberty, Speech, and the Free Society, 29 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 276 (2000) (situating Mill's views on freedom of speech within larger Millian perspectives).
  • 54
    • 51849113171 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I use the term population in its social scientific sense, to encompass any group of people or particulars, and not just the population of a city, state, or nation. Thus, we can ask the question both for the population consisting of a certain scientific community, for example, and for the population of Cleveland. It may well be that the answers in the two cases are not the same
    • I use the term "population" in its social scientific sense, to encompass any group of people (or particulars), and not just the population of a city, state, or nation. Thus, we can ask the question both for the population consisting of a certain scientific community, for example, and for the population of Cleveland. It may well be that the answers in the two cases are not the same.
  • 55
    • 51849125463 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See FREDERICK SCHAUER, FREE SPEECH: A PHILOSOPHICAL ENQUIRY 19-22 (1982).
    • See FREDERICK SCHAUER, FREE SPEECH: A PHILOSOPHICAL ENQUIRY 19-22 (1982).
  • 56
    • 51849085132 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is also an interesting question, although here a normative rather than empirical one, how a society should balance the gains from increased knowledge against the losses from greater acceptance of error. Is a society that knows n true things and x false things better or worse off than a society that knows n+1 true things and x+1 false ones?
    • It is also an interesting question, although here a normative rather than empirical one, how a society should balance the gains from increased knowledge against the losses from greater acceptance of error. Is a society that knows n true things and x false things better or worse off than a society that knows n+1 true things and x+1 false ones?
  • 57
    • 51849166380 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mill comes close to treating the increase in knowledge and the identification of truth as having a lexical priority over all other values, but it is hardly self-evident that this is the case. Once we see that it is not always a good idea to circulate true but private facts about others, once we see that it may not be wise to provide terrorists with correct information on how to make explosive or chemical agents out of readily obtainable ingredients, see United States v. Progressive, Inc, 467 F. Supp. 990, 993, 995 (W.D. Wis. 1979, appeal dismissed, 610 F.2d 819 (7th Cir. 1979, mandamus denied sub nom. Morland v. Sprecher, 443 U.S. 709 (1979, unpublished table decision, Thomas M. Scanlon, A Theory of Freedom of Expression, 1 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 203, 204, 211-12 1972, and once we see that it is not always the best course to tell our loved ones that their new dress or jacket makes them look fat, we can put truth and the possession of
    • Mill comes close to treating the increase in knowledge and the identification of truth as having a lexical priority over all other values, but it is hardly self-evident that this is the case. Once we see that it is not always a good idea to circulate true but private facts about others, once we see that it may not be wise to provide terrorists with correct information on how to make explosive or chemical agents out of readily obtainable ingredients, see United States v. Progressive, Inc., 467 F. Supp. 990, 993, 995 (W.D. Wis. 1979), appeal dismissed, 610 F.2d 819 (7th Cir. 1979), mandamus denied sub nom. Morland v. Sprecher, 443 U.S. 709 (1979) (unpublished table decision); Thomas M. Scanlon, A Theory of Freedom of Expression, 1 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 203, 204, 211-12 (1972), and once we see that it is not always the best course to tell our loved ones that their new dress or jacket makes them look fat, we can put truth and the possession of it in proper perspective.
  • 58
    • 51849163229 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally Frederick Schauer, Reflections on the Value of Truth, 41 CASE W. RES. L. REV. 699, 704, 710-11 (1991) (arguing that not every increase in knowledge will be a social good).
    • See generally Frederick Schauer, Reflections on the Value of Truth, 41 CASE W. RES. L. REV. 699, 704, 710-11 (1991) (arguing that not every increase in knowledge will be a social good).
  • 59
    • 51849128641 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To expand on the suggestion in the text, consider more closely the case of arts funding. If (realistically and not just hypothetically) increased governmental funding for museums, exhibitions, art schools, and emerging talented artists can come as a practical but unfortunate political matter only by allowing funding authorities to refuse to fund so-called indecent art, see Nat'l Endowment for the Arts v. Finley, 524 U.S. 569, 574, 585, 588-89 1998, and even if granting that power will increase the amount of serious art that is restricted or simply not produced, it is not axiomatic that the benefits to art coming from the increased funding will be outweighed by the admitted impediments to art stemming from the power of a governmental agency to refuse to fund the art it deems indecent
    • To expand on the suggestion in the text, consider more closely the case of arts funding. If (realistically and not just hypothetically) increased governmental funding for museums, exhibitions, art schools, and emerging talented artists can come as a practical but unfortunate political matter only by allowing funding authorities to refuse to fund so-called indecent art, see Nat'l Endowment for the Arts v. Finley, 524 U.S. 569, 574, 585, 588-89 (1998), and even if granting that power will increase the amount of serious art that is restricted or simply not produced, it is not axiomatic that the benefits to art coming from the increased funding will be outweighed by the admitted impediments to art stemming from the power of a governmental agency to refuse to fund the art it deems indecent.
  • 60
    • 51849147380 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A plausible example is the issue of publication in learned journals, see ALVIN I. GOLDMAN, KNOWLEDGE IN A SOCIAL WORLD 263-71 (1998), where the goals of increased knowledge and greater acceptance of truth may in fact be fostered by empowering journal editors to distinguish between knowledge and ignorance, and to base their acceptance and rejection decisions on questions of truth and falsity.
    • A plausible example is the issue of publication in learned journals, see ALVIN I. GOLDMAN, KNOWLEDGE IN A SOCIAL WORLD 263-71 (1998), where the goals of increased knowledge and greater acceptance of truth may in fact be fostered by empowering journal editors to distinguish between knowledge and ignorance, and to base their acceptance and rejection decisions on questions of truth and falsity.
  • 61
    • 51849127268 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The canonical locus for this argument is Vincent Blasi, The Checking Value in First Amendment Theory, 1977 AM. B. FOUND. RES. J. 521, 523 (1977), although, as Blasi himself recounts, it has its roots in the eighteenth century, id. at 529-44.
    • The canonical locus for this argument is Vincent Blasi, The Checking Value in First Amendment Theory, 1977 AM. B. FOUND. RES. J. 521, 523 (1977), although, as Blasi himself recounts, it has its roots in the eighteenth century, id. at 529-44.
  • 63
    • 51849142642 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • E.g., Rankin v. McPherson. 483 U.S. 378 (1987); Pickering v. Bd. of Educ., 391 U.S. 563 (1978); Watts v. United States, 394 U.S. 705 (1969).
    • E.g., Rankin v. McPherson. 483 U.S. 378 (1987); Pickering v. Bd. of Educ., 391 U.S. 563 (1978); Watts v. United States, 394 U.S. 705 (1969).
  • 64
    • 51849158198 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • E.g., Fla. Star v. B.J.F., 491 U.S. 524 (1989); N.Y. Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254 (1964).
    • E.g., Fla. Star v. B.J.F., 491 U.S. 524 (1989); N.Y. Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254 (1964).
  • 65
    • 51849134893 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • E.g., N.Y. Times Co. v. United States, 403 U.S. 713 (1971) (per curiam).
    • E.g., N.Y. Times Co. v. United States, 403 U.S. 713 (1971) (per curiam).
  • 66
    • 51849090018 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Minneapolis Star & Tribune Co. v. Minn. Comm'r of Revenue, 460 U.S. 575 (1983); Grosjean v. Am. Press Co., 297 U.S. 233 (1936).
    • See Minneapolis Star & Tribune Co. v. Minn. Comm'r of Revenue, 460 U.S. 575 (1983); Grosjean v. Am. Press Co., 297 U.S. 233 (1936).
  • 67
    • 51849088942 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Alexander Meiklejohn, Free Speech and Its Relation to Self-Government, in POLITICAL FREEDOM: THE C ONSTITUTIONAL POWERS OF THE PEOPLE 3, 27 (1965). Earlier traces of the argument can be found in the writings of Spinoza and Hume, and in Justice Brandeis's opinion in Whitney v. California, 274 U.S. 357, 372 (1927) (Brandeis, J., concurring).
    • Alexander Meiklejohn, Free Speech and Its Relation to Self-Government, in POLITICAL FREEDOM: THE C ONSTITUTIONAL POWERS OF THE PEOPLE 3, 27 (1965). Earlier traces of the argument can be found in the writings of Spinoza and Hume, and in Justice Brandeis's opinion in Whitney v. California, 274 U.S. 357, 372 (1927) (Brandeis, J., concurring).
  • 68
    • 84928223368 scopus 로고
    • Money and Politics: A Perspective on the First Amendment and Campaign Finance, 73
    • See
    • See Lillian BeVier, Money and Politics: A Perspective on the First Amendment and Campaign Finance, 73 CAL. L. REV. 1045, 1068 (1985);
    • (1985) CAL. L. REV , vol.1045 , pp. 1068
    • BeVier, L.1
  • 69
    • 77953306228 scopus 로고
    • An Informed Public, An Informing Press: The Search for a Constitutional Principle, 68
    • Lillian BeVier, An Informed Public, An Informing Press: The Search for a Constitutional Principle, 68 CAL. L. REV. 482, 502 (1980).
    • (1980) CAL. L. REV , vol.482 , pp. 502
    • BeVier, L.1
  • 70
    • 51849108020 scopus 로고
    • See
    • See ROBERT C. POST, CONSTITUTIONAL DOMAINS 179-80 (1995).
    • (1995) , vol.179 -80
    • POST, R.C.1    DOMAINS, C.2
  • 71
    • 51849096284 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See CASS R. SUNSTEIN, DEMOCRACY AND THE PROBLEM OF FREE SPEECH (1993).
    • See CASS R. SUNSTEIN, DEMOCRACY AND THE PROBLEM OF FREE SPEECH (1993).
  • 72
    • 51849105505 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Australian Capital Television v. Commonwealth (1992) 177 C.L.R. 106, 138-42 (concluding that there was an implied right to freedom of political expression situated in the Australian Constitution's guarantee of representative government).
    • See Australian Capital Television v. Commonwealth (1992) 177 C.L.R. 106, 138-42 (concluding that there was an implied right to freedom of political expression situated in the Australian Constitution's guarantee of representative government).
  • 73
    • 51849122791 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • And thus what I say here is different from the argument that strong judicial enforcement of the First Amendment may detract from other ways of promoting First Amendment values. See Robert Nagel, How Useful Is Judicial Review in Free Speech Cases, 69 CORNELL L. REV. 302, 318 1984, noting that the use of principle in judicial enforcement requires courts to protect speech even in cases in which the immediate advantages are questionable and the social disadvantages are clear
    • And thus what I say here is different from the argument that strong judicial enforcement of the First Amendment may detract from other ways of promoting First Amendment values. See Robert Nagel, How Useful Is Judicial Review in Free Speech Cases, 69 CORNELL L. REV. 302, 318 (1984) (noting that the use of principle in judicial enforcement "requires courts to protect speech even in cases in which the immediate advantages are questionable and the social disadvantages are clear").
  • 74
    • 0348047077 scopus 로고
    • The Second-Best First Amendment, 31
    • noting that freedom of speech is both underinclusive and overinclusive with respect to its background justification, See
    • See Frederick Schauer, The Second-Best First Amendment, 31 WM. & MARY L. REV. 1. 7 (1989) (noting that freedom of speech is both underinclusive and overinclusive with respect to its background justification).
    • (1989) WM. & MARY L. REV , vol.1 , pp. 7
    • Schauer, F.1
  • 75
    • 4344606135 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Especially, it seems to me, in the protection of wildly unpopular speech, such as flag desecration, child pornography, racist speech, and the like. Apart from the question of how many of the foregoing categories of speech should be protected and, if so, how much, which is not our topic here, it may nevertheless be the case that protection of speech not taking place within the forty-yard lines of contemporary political and social discourse is best entrusted to countermajoritarian institutions such as the courts. See Frederick Schauer. Judicial Supremacy and the Modest Constitution, 92 CAL. L. REV. 1045, 1057-58 (2004).
    • Especially, it seems to me, in the protection of wildly unpopular speech, such as flag desecration, child pornography, racist speech, and the like. Apart from the question of how many of the foregoing categories of speech should be protected and, if so, how much, which is not our topic here, it may nevertheless be the case that protection of speech not taking place within the "forty-yard lines" of contemporary political and social discourse is best entrusted to countermajoritarian institutions such as the courts. See Frederick Schauer. Judicial Supremacy and the Modest Constitution, 92 CAL. L. REV. 1045, 1057-58 (2004).
  • 76
    • 0005434963 scopus 로고
    • Access to the Press - A New First Amendment Right, 80
    • See generally
    • See generally Jerome Barron, Access to the Press - A New First Amendment Right, 80 HARV. L. REV. 1641 (1967).
    • (1967) HARV. L. REV , vol.1641
    • Barron, J.1
  • 77
    • 51849159960 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 1156.
    • See id. at 1156.
  • 78
    • 51849121934 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id
    • See id.
  • 79
    • 51849103648 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Communist Party of the U.S. v. Subversive Activities Control Bd., 367 U.S. 1, 121 (1961) (Douglas, J., dissenting).
    • Communist Party of the U.S. v. Subversive Activities Control Bd., 367 U.S. 1, 121 (1961) (Douglas, J., dissenting).
  • 80
    • 51849146912 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • And perhaps prior to the question of whether those against whom access rights are claimed have countervailing rights. When countervailing rights, especially countervailing First Amendment rights, do not exist, the question of access is far less constitutionally, doctrinally, and politically perilous. See Pruneyard Shopping Ctr. v. Robins, 447 U.S. 74, 83, 91 1980, As a matter of strategy, it might have been wiser first to see the case for access to government established, as with freedom of information and open meeting laws, and then to see the case for access to non-ideological private property established, as in Pruneyard, and then, and only then, take on the question of access to a press whose own understanding of the First Amendment is a powerful force. As the old saw goes, n]ever argue with the fellow who buys ink by the barrel
    • And perhaps prior to the question of whether those against whom access rights are claimed have countervailing rights. When countervailing rights, especially countervailing First Amendment rights, do not exist, the question of access is far less constitutionally, doctrinally, and politically perilous. See Pruneyard Shopping Ctr. v. Robins, 447 U.S. 74, 83, 91 (1980). As a matter of strategy, it might have been wiser first to see the case for access to government established, as with freedom of information and open meeting laws, and then to see the case for access to non-ideological private property established, as in Pruneyard, and then, and only then, take on the question of access to a press whose own understanding of the First Amendment is a powerful force. As the old saw goes, "[n]ever argue with the fellow who buys ink by the barrel."
  • 81
    • 51849090441 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Michelman, supra note 36, at 9, 11
    • Michelman, supra note 36, at 9, 11.
  • 82
    • 33846585474 scopus 로고
    • Fair Measure: The Legal Status of Underenforced Constitutional Norms, 91
    • Lawrence Gene Sager, Fair Measure: The Legal Status of Underenforced Constitutional Norms, 91 HARV. L. REV. 1212, 1221 (1978).
    • (1978) HARV. L. REV , vol.1212 , pp. 1221
    • Gene Sager, L.1
  • 83
    • 51849154179 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Miami Herald Publ'g Co. v. Tornillo, 418 U.S. 241, 257-58 (1974) (holding a Florida statute, which required newspapers to devote equal space to allowing a political candidate to respond to attacks on their record, unconstitutional on First Amendment grounds).
    • Miami Herald Publ'g Co. v. Tornillo, 418 U.S. 241, 257-58 (1974) (holding a Florida statute, which required newspapers to devote equal space to allowing a political candidate to respond to attacks on their record, unconstitutional on First Amendment grounds).


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.