-
3
-
-
0004002174
-
-
Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
David Miller, On Nationality, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995).
-
(1995)
On Nationality
-
-
Miller, D.1
-
6
-
-
0010396625
-
Constitutional Patriotism
-
Cf.
-
Cf. Atracta Ingram, ‘Constitutional Patriotism’, Philosophy & Social Criticism 22(6) (1996): 1–18
-
(1996)
Philosophy & Social Criticism
, vol.22
, Issue.6
, pp. 1-18
-
-
Ingram, A.1
-
7
-
-
0034407486
-
Making Affect Safe for Democracy? On “Constitutional Patriotism”
-
Patchen Markell, ‘Making Affect Safe for Democracy? On “Constitutional Patriotism”’, Political Theory 28(1) (2000): 38–63.
-
(2000)
Political Theory
, vol.28
, Issue.1
, pp. 38-63
-
-
Markell, P.1
-
8
-
-
1642598506
-
-
Plato, Gorgias, 462b–465c.
-
Gorgias
, pp. 462b-465c
-
-
Plato1
-
9
-
-
84923605190
-
De Inventione
-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
Cicero, ‘De Inventione’, in De Inventione, De Optimo Genere Oratorum, Topica (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1949), 6/7.
-
(1949)
De Inventione, De Optimo Genere Oratorum, Topica
, pp. 6/7
-
-
Cicero1
-
11
-
-
0346042227
-
Introduction
-
In Thucydides' History only one Athenian regularly uses oratory effectively, and that is Pericles, who needs it precisely because he wields power through democratic institutions.’, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
‘In Thucydides' History only one Athenian regularly uses oratory effectively, and that is Pericles, who needs it precisely because he wields power through democratic institutions.’ Michael Gagarin and Paul Woodruff, ‘Introduction’, in Early Greek Political Thought from Homer to the Sophists (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), p. xxx.
-
(1995)
Early Greek Political Thought from Homer to the Sophists
, pp. xxx
-
-
Gagarin, M.1
Woodruff, P.2
-
12
-
-
0003475466
-
-
See, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, for the link between free political speech and democratic ideology for the ancient Greeks
-
See Harvey Yunis, Taming Democracy: Models of Political Rhetoric in Classical Athens (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1996), p. 49 for the link between free political speech and democratic ideology for the ancient Greeks.
-
(1996)
Taming Democracy: Models of Political Rhetoric in Classical Athens
, pp. 49
-
-
Yunis, H.1
-
13
-
-
0007208638
-
Eloquence and Liberty
-
For the ubiquity of this theme in France and Britain by the 18th century, see
-
For the ubiquity of this theme in France and Britain by the 18th century, see Jean Starobinski, ‘Eloquence and Liberty’, Journal of the History of Ideas 38 (1977): 195–210
-
(1977)
Journal of the History of Ideas
, vol.38
, pp. 195-210
-
-
Starobinski, J.1
-
15
-
-
0000852286
-
Rhetoric, Consensus, and the Law in Rousseau's Social Contract
-
See, who shows why in order ‘effectively to take the place of the public force wielded by an absolute monarch, persuasion must exercise an equivalent force’ (p. 743)
-
See Neil Saccamano, ‘Rhetoric, Consensus, and the Law in Rousseau's Social Contract’, Modern Language Notes 107(4) (1992): 730–51, who shows why in order ‘effectively to take the place of the public force wielded by an absolute monarch, persuasion must exercise an equivalent force’ (p. 743).
-
(1992)
Modern Language Notes
, vol.107
, Issue.4
, pp. 730-751
-
-
Saccamano, N.1
-
19
-
-
0035535576
-
Banishing the Particular: Rousseau on Rhetoric, Patrie, and the Passions
-
for Rousseau, see
-
for Rousseau, see Arash Abizadeh, ‘Banishing the Particular: Rousseau on Rhetoric, Patrie, and the Passions’, Political Theory 29(4) (2001): 556–82.
-
(2001)
Political Theory
, vol.29
, Issue.4
, pp. 556-582
-
-
Abizadeh, A.1
-
21
-
-
61049472155
-
-
Of great relevance for the transmission of the Roman militaristic imagery to modern thinkers in France is, B. Timmermans, Paris: Presses universitaires de France
-
Of great relevance for the transmission of the Roman militaristic imagery to modern thinkers in France is Bernard Lamy's La rhétorique ou l'art de parler, ed. B. Timmermans (Paris: Presses universitaires de France, 1998).
-
(1998)
La rhétorique ou l'art de parler
-
-
Lamy, B.1
-
22
-
-
84870837418
-
-
719e–724b
-
Plato, Laws, 690c, 719e–724b.
-
Laws
, pp. 690c
-
-
Plato1
-
23
-
-
71049128924
-
-
At 722c, Plato now starkly contrasts ‘two means of giving laws, persuasion and violence’. For a full discussion see, ch. 8
-
At 722c, Plato now starkly contrasts ‘two means of giving laws, persuasion and violence’. For a full discussion see Yunis, Taming Democracy, ch. 8.
-
Taming Democracy
-
-
Yunis1
-
25
-
-
0004088235
-
-
David F. Norton and Mary J. Norton, Oxford: Oxford University Press, (section 2.3.3)
-
David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. David F. Norton and Mary J. Norton (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), p. 265 (section 2.3.3).
-
(2000)
A Treatise of Human Nature
, pp. 265
-
-
Hume, D.1
-
26
-
-
84997971194
-
-
As Rousseau says in Emile, ‘il n'y a que la passion qui nous fasse agir’, B. Gangebin and M. Raymond, Paris: Bibliothèque de la Pléiade
-
As Rousseau says in Emile, ‘il n'y a que la passion qui nous fasse agir’. Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Oeuvres complètes, vol. 4, ed. B. Gangebin and M. Raymond (Paris: Bibliothèque de la Pléiade, 1969), p. 453.
-
(1969)
Oeuvres complètes
, vol.4
, pp. 453
-
-
Rousseau, J.-J.1
-
28
-
-
0004002174
-
-
David Miller uses similar vocabulary, to similar effect. Contrasting reason to sentiment, he argues that impartialist moral theories, which on his reading fail to give to the nation the independent ethical weight it deserves, are unviable because they rest ‘upon an implausible account of ethical motivation. When I act on moral principle, I am supposed to act simply out of a rational conviction … I am not to be influenced by my sentiments … But it seems unlikely that rational conviction can carry the weight required of it.’, emphasis added. According to Miller, ‘If we look at actual cases in which people identify with their community … we see that they identify with it as a concrete and distinct object’
-
David Miller uses similar vocabulary, to similar effect. Contrasting reason to sentiment, he argues that impartialist moral theories, which on his reading fail to give to the nation the independent ethical weight it deserves, are unviable because they rest ‘upon an implausible account of ethical motivation. When I act on moral principle, I am supposed to act simply out of a rational conviction … I am not to be influenced by my sentiments … But it seems unlikely that rational conviction can carry the weight required of it.’ Miller, On Nationality, pp. 57–8; emphasis added. According to Miller, ‘If we look at actual cases in which people identify with their community … we see that they identify with it as a concrete and distinct object’.
-
On Nationality
, pp. 57-58
-
-
Miller1
-
29
-
-
0004168529
-
-
Oxford: Clarendon Press, The nation is indispensable, he argues, because under modern conditions it is the only viable candidate that could serve as the ‘concrete’ object for an affective identity capable of solving the twin problems of motivation and social integration
-
David Miller, Market, State, and Community: Theoretical Foundations of Market Socialism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989), p. 231. The nation is indispensable, he argues, because under modern conditions it is the only viable candidate that could serve as the ‘concrete’ object for an affective identity capable of solving the twin problems of motivation and social integration.
-
(1989)
Market, State, and Community: Theoretical Foundations of Market Socialism
, pp. 231
-
-
Miller, D.1
-
30
-
-
0003926427
-
-
Maurizio Viroli uses similar rhetoric against constitutional patriotism: ‘contrary to Habermas … civic virtue is not sustained by universalistic political values but by identification with values that are part of the particular culture of a people … [The] political values of democratic citizenship that citizens share are not universalistic constructions of impersonal reason, but are or are perceived and lived as cultural values. They are not attached to an abstract liberty or an abstract justice, but to a way of life informed by those principles. They are attached to a liberty and a justice that is a part of their culture, that has for them a particular beauty, a particular warmth, a particular colour that is connected with particular memories and particular histories.’, Oxford: Clarendon Press, emphasis added
-
Maurizio Viroli uses similar rhetoric against constitutional patriotism: ‘contrary to Habermas … civic virtue is not sustained by universalistic political values but by identification with values that are part of the particular culture of a people … [The] political values of democratic citizenship that citizens share are not universalistic constructions of impersonal reason, but are or are perceived and lived as cultural values. They are not attached to an abstract liberty or an abstract justice, but to a way of life informed by those principles. They are attached to a liberty and a justice that is a part of their culture, that has for them a particular beauty, a particular warmth, a particular colour that is connected with particular memories and particular histories.’ Maurizio Viroli, For Love of Country: An Essay on Patriotism and Nationalism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995), pp. 174–5; emphasis added.
-
(1995)
For Love of Country: An Essay on Patriotism and Nationalism
, pp. 174-175
-
-
Viroli, M.1
-
31
-
-
84997922722
-
-
Schnapper, of course, is not oblivious to this point: she herself cites Anderson's phrase and notes that many have accused the nation of being abstract ‘dans la mesure justement où elle est construite par la volonté des hommes, où elle ne se mesure ni ne se perçoit directement’, 106, emphasis added
-
Schnapper, of course, is not oblivious to this point: she herself cites Anderson's phrase and notes that many have accused the nation of being abstract ‘dans la mesure justement où elle est construite par la volonté des hommes, où elle ne se mesure ni ne se perçoit directement’. Schnapper, Communauté des citoyens, p. 104, 106, emphasis added.
-
Communauté des citoyens
, pp. 104
-
-
Schnapper1
-
32
-
-
0003232364
-
-
Boston, MA: Beacon Press, cf. p. 86
-
Jürgen Habermas, The Theory of Communicative Action, vol. 1 (Boston, MA: Beacon Press, 1984), pp. 285–6, cf. p. 86
-
(1984)
The Theory of Communicative Action
, vol.1
, pp. 285-286
-
-
Habermas, J.1
-
41
-
-
71549170592
-
-
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, demonstrates that Habermas' ‘parasitic’ language thesis does not provide an argument here
-
Maeve Cooke, Language and Reason: A Study of Habermas' Pragmatics (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1997), pp. 22–7 demonstrates that Habermas' ‘parasitic’ language thesis does not provide an argument here.
-
(1997)
Language and Reason: A Study of Habermas' Pragmatics
, pp. 22-27
-
-
Cooke, M.1
-
43
-
-
84998190746
-
-
See, for example, Habermas' reference to
-
See, for example, Habermas' reference to Durkheim and Parsons, in Between Facts and Norms, p. 26.
-
Between Facts and Norms
, pp. 26
-
-
Durkheim1
Parsons2
-
45
-
-
84965797721
-
-
“How are synthetic judgments a priori possible?” Kant asked himself — and what really is his answer? … “By virtue of a faculty” — he had said, or at least meant. But is that — an answer? An explanation? Or is it not rather merely a repetition of the question? How does opium induce sleep? “By virtue of a faculty,” namely the virtus dormitiva, replies the doctor in Molière.’, trans. W. Kaufmann, New York: Vintage, # 11. Hobbes and Hume had both made a similar criticism of the scholastics
-
‘“How are synthetic judgments a priori possible?” Kant asked himself — and what really is his answer? … “By virtue of a faculty” — he had said, or at least meant. But is that — an answer? An explanation? Or is it not rather merely a repetition of the question? How does opium induce sleep? “By virtue of a faculty,” namely the virtus dormitiva, replies the doctor in Molière.’ Friedrich Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil: Prelude to a Philosophy of the Future, trans. W. Kaufmann (New York: Vintage, 1966), pp. 18–19, # 11. Hobbes and Hume had both made a similar criticism of the scholastics.
-
(1966)
Beyond Good and Evil: Prelude to a Philosophy of the Future
, pp. 18-19
-
-
Nietzsche, F.1
-
46
-
-
84879428896
-
-
See, Richard Tuck, rev. student edn, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
See Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, ed. Richard Tuck, rev. student edn (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), p. 468
-
(1996)
Leviathan
, pp. 468
-
-
Hobbes, T.1
-
48
-
-
84905920547
-
-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, disputes this, but only by packing everything into his definition of ‘rationality’. The question then could simply be rephrased: How is Scanlonian rationality possible?
-
Thomas M. Scanlon (What We Owe Each Other [Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998]) disputes this, but only by packing everything into his definition of ‘rationality’. The question then could simply be rephrased: How is Scanlonian rationality possible?
-
(1998)
What We Owe Each Other
-
-
Scanlon, T.M.1
-
50
-
-
0007340651
-
L'ancienne rhétorique
-
See
-
See Roland Barthes, ‘L'ancienne rhétorique’, Communications 16 (1970): 172–229.
-
(1970)
Communications
, vol.16
, pp. 172-229
-
-
Barthes, R.1
-
52
-
-
0011258949
-
Impartiality and the Civic Public: Some Implications of Feminist Critiques of Moral and Political Theory
-
Seyla Benhabib and Drucilla Cornell, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press
-
Iris Marion Young, ‘Impartiality and the Civic Public: Some Implications of Feminist Critiques of Moral and Political Theory’, in Feminism as Critique, ed. Seyla Benhabib and Drucilla Cornell (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1987), p. 69.
-
(1987)
Feminism as Critique
, pp. 69
-
-
Marion Young, I.1
-
59
-
-
0003497542
-
-
For discussion see, Albany: State University of New York Press, p., 99
-
For discussion see Kenneth Baynes, The Normative Grounds of Social Criticism: Kant, Rawls and Habermas (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1992), p. 94ff, 99.
-
(1992)
The Normative Grounds of Social Criticism: Kant, Rawls and Habermas
, pp. 94ff
-
-
Baynes, K.1
-
62
-
-
0039887066
-
A Reply
-
Habermas has revised his account slightly in, trans. J. Gaines and D. L. Jones, Axel Honneth and Hans Joas, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
-
Habermas has revised his account slightly in Jürgen Habermas, ‘A Reply’, trans. J. Gaines and D. L. Jones, in Communicative Action: Essays on Jürgen Habermas' The Theory of Communicative Action, ed. Axel Honneth and Hans Joas (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1991), p. 239ff.
-
(1991)
Communicative Action: Essays on Jürgen Habermas' The Theory of Communicative Action
, pp. 239ff
-
-
Habermas, J.1
-
67
-
-
0003976110
-
-
This worry is on full display in Habermas' response to Horkheimer's and Adorno's insinuation that the ‘modern, fully rationalized world is only seemingly disenchanted’, that the dream of an ‘Enlightenment [which] contradicts myth and thereby escapes its violence’ is self-defeating, and that ‘this process of gaining mastery over mythic forces … [calls] forth, in fateful fashion, the return of myth at each new stage’, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 107, 109
-
This worry is on full display in Habermas' response to Horkheimer's and Adorno's insinuation that the ‘modern, fully rationalized world is only seemingly disenchanted’, that the dream of an ‘Enlightenment [which] contradicts myth and thereby escapes its violence’ is self-defeating, and that ‘this process of gaining mastery over mythic forces … [calls] forth, in fateful fashion, the return of myth at each new stage’. Jürgen Habermas, The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity: Twelve Lectures (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1987), pp. 110, 107, 109.
-
(1987)
The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity: Twelve Lectures
, pp. 110
-
-
Habermas, J.1
-
69
-
-
84971863055
-
-
178, 207, 180, emphasis added; cf. pp. 178–80, emphasis added
-
Habermas, Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action, p. 121; 178, 207, 180, emphasis added; cf. pp. 178–80, emphasis added.
-
Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action
, pp. 121
-
-
Habermas1
-
70
-
-
84975515506
-
-
E.g., 2nd edn, Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press
-
E.g. Aglasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue, 2nd edn (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1984).
-
(1984)
After Virtue
-
-
MacIntyre, A.1
-
71
-
-
84966575331
-
-
1356a1–20
-
Aristotle, Rhetoric 1355b10–12, 1356a1–20.
-
Rhetoric
, pp. 1355b10-1355b12
-
-
Aristotle1
-
72
-
-
84997933809
-
-
For an extensive discussion of rhetoric as an art in Aristotle, see, Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, ch. 1, especially
-
For an extensive discussion of rhetoric as an art in Aristotle, see Eugene Garver, Aristotle's Rhetoric: An Art of Character (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1994), ch. 1, especially pp. 28–33.
-
(1994)
Aristotle's Rhetoric: An Art of Character
, pp. 28-33
-
-
Garver, E.1
-
73
-
-
0011539463
-
An Anthropological Approach to the Contemporary Significance of Rhetoric
-
This broadening is, arguably, what recent accounts of rhetoric have attempted to do. See, in particular, Kenneth Baynes, James Bohman and Thomas McCarthy, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
-
This broadening is, arguably, what recent accounts of rhetoric have attempted to do. See, in particular, Hans Blumenburg, ‘An Anthropological Approach to the Contemporary Significance of Rhetoric’, in After Philosophy: End or Transformation?, ed. Kenneth Baynes, James Bohman and Thomas McCarthy (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1987), pp. 429–58
-
(1987)
After Philosophy: End or Transformation?
, pp. 429-458
-
-
Blumenburg, H.1
-
74
-
-
0041153795
-
Reason and Rhetoric in Habermas' Theory of Argumentation
-
Walter Jost and Michael J. Hyde, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press
-
William Rehg, ‘Reason and Rhetoric in Habermas' Theory of Argumentation’, in Rhetoric and Hermeneutics in Our Time, ed. Walter Jost and Michael J. Hyde (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1997)
-
(1997)
Rhetoric and Hermeneutics in Our Time
-
-
Rehg, W.1
-
75
-
-
0036956103
-
The Passions of the Wise: Phronêsis, Rhetoric and Aristotle's Passionate Practical Deliberation
-
Arash Abizadeh, ‘The Passions of the Wise: Phronêsis, Rhetoric and Aristotle's Passionate Practical Deliberation’, The Review of Metaphysics 56(2) (2002): 267–96.
-
(2002)
The Review of Metaphysics
, vol.56
, Issue.2
, pp. 267-296
-
-
Abizadeh, A.1
|