메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 34, Issue 7, 2008, Pages 799-824

Republican confusion and liberal clarification

Author keywords

Freedom; John Rawls; Liberalism; Philip Pettit; Quentin Skinner; Republicanism

Indexed keywords


EID: 49749094785     PISSN: 01914537     EISSN: 1461734X     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1177/0191453708094728     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (15)

References (161)
  • 3
    • 84922630491 scopus 로고
    • Machiavelli on the Maintenance of Liberty
    • Quentin Skinner, 'Machiavelli on the Maintenance of Liberty', Politics 18 (1983): 3-15;
    • (1983) Politics , vol.18 , pp. 3-15
    • Skinner, Q.1
  • 4
    • 0001996443 scopus 로고
    • The Idea of Negative Liberty: Philosophical and Historical Perspectives
    • ed. Richard Rorty, Jerome Schneewind and Quentin Skinner New York: Cambridge University Press
    • Quentin Skinner, 'The Idea of Negative Liberty: Philosophical and Historical Perspectives', in Philosophy in History, ed. Richard Rorty, Jerome Schneewind and Quentin Skinner (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1984), pp. 193-221;
    • (1984) Philosophy in History , pp. 193-221
    • Skinner, Q.1
  • 5
    • 0346171505 scopus 로고
    • The Paradoxes of Political Liberty
    • ed. S. McMurrin New York: Cambridge University Press
    • Quentin Skinner, 'The Paradoxes of Political Liberty', in The Tanner Lectures on Human Values, vol. III, ed. S. McMurrin (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1986), pp. 225-50;
    • (1986) The Tanner Lectures on Human Values , vol.3 , pp. 225-250
    • Skinner, Q.1
  • 6
    • 0005292975 scopus 로고
    • The Republican Ideal of Political Liberty
    • ed. Gisela Bock, Quentin Skinner and Maurizio Viroli New York: Cambridge University Press
    • Quentin Skinner, 'The Republican Ideal of Political Liberty', in Machiavelli and Republicanism, ed. Gisela Bock, Quentin Skinner and Maurizio Viroli (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1990), pp. 293-310;
    • (1990) Machiavelli and Republicanism , pp. 293-310
    • Skinner, Q.1
  • 7
    • 0000751846 scopus 로고
    • On Justice, the Common Good and the Priority of Liberty
    • ed. Chantal Mouffe New York: Verso
    • Quentin Skinner, 'On Justice, the Common Good and the Priority of Liberty', in Dimensions of Radical Democracy: Pluralism, Citizenship, Community, ed. Chantal Mouffe (New York: Verso, 1992), pp. 211-25;
    • (1992) Dimensions of Radical Democracy: Pluralism, Citizenship, Community , pp. 211-225
    • Skinner, Q.1
  • 9
    • 84883904828 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Classical Liberty and the Coming of the English Civil War
    • ed. Martin Van Gelderen and Quentin Skinner New York: Cambridge University Press
    • Quentin Skinner, 'Classical Liberty and the Coming of the English Civil War', in Republicanism: A Shared European Heritage, vol. II, ed. Martin Van Gelderen and Quentin Skinner (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2002), pp. 9-28;
    • (2002) Republicanism: A Shared European Heritage , vol.2 , pp. 9-28
    • Skinner, Q.1
  • 14
    • 0142006304 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Hill and Wang
    • Maurizio Viroli, Republicanism (New York: Hill and Wang, 2002).
    • (2002) Republicanism
    • Viroli, M.1
  • 15
    • 0003218407 scopus 로고
    • The Politics of Virtue Today: A Critique and a Proposal
    • In this regard, Shelley Burtt points out that the attempt to make republicanism compatible with pluralism is characteristic of 'instrumental' rather than 'Aristotelian' republicanism; see, 360
    • In this regard, Shelley Burtt points out that the attempt to make republicanism compatible with pluralism is characteristic of 'instrumental' rather than 'Aristotelian' republicanism; see Shelley Burtt, 'The Politics of Virtue Today: a Critique and a Proposal', American Political Science Review 87 (1993): 360-8 (360).
    • (1993) American Political Science Review , vol.87 , pp. 360-368
    • Burtt, S.1
  • 16
    • 0002068898 scopus 로고
    • Two Concepts of Liberty
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • Isaiah Berlin, 'Two Concepts of Liberty', in Four Essays on Liberty (New York: Oxford University Press, 1969[1958]), p. 122;
    • (1958) Four Essays on Liberty , pp. 122
    • Berlin, I.1
  • 17
    • 49749103058 scopus 로고
    • Negative and Positive Liberty
    • ed. David Miller New York: Oxford University Press
    • cf. Gerald MacCallum, 'Negative and Positive Liberty', in Liberty, ed. David Miller (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993), pp. 100-23 (102).
    • (1993) Liberty , Issue.102 , pp. 100-123
    • cf1    MacCallum, G.2
  • 18
    • 0004287799 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Penguin
    • Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan (New York: Penguin, 1968[1651]), p. 261.
    • (1651) Leviathan , pp. 261
    • Hobbes, T.1
  • 24
    • 49749127914 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Skinner has developed and modified his account of republicanism in a number of different articles since the early 1980s. For the most part he has used the language of freedom as non-interference, arguing that liberals and republicans agree on what freedom is but disagree on what conditions are needed to maintain it Skinner, Machiavelli, pp. 3-15;
    • Skinner has developed and modified his account of republicanism in a number of different articles since the early 1980s. For the most part he has used the language of freedom as non-interference, arguing that liberals and republicans agree on what freedom is but disagree on what conditions are needed to maintain it (Skinner, 'Machiavelli', pp. 3-15;
  • 26
    • 21844491148 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This argument has been effectively challenged; see Alan Patten, The Republican Critique of Liberalism, British Journal of Political Science 261, 1996, 25-44
    • This argument has been effectively challenged; see Alan Patten, 'The Republican Critique of Liberalism', British Journal of Political Science 26(1) (1996): 25-44.
  • 27
    • 49749113657 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Most recently, however, Skinner has argued, along with Pettit, that what is at issue between republicans and liberals is a completely different conception of freedom altogether Skinner, Liberty, p. 70, n. 27, p. 37 n. 114;
    • Most recently, however, Skinner has argued, along with Pettit, that what is at issue between republicans and liberals is a completely different conception of freedom altogether (Skinner, Liberty, p. 70, n. 27, p. 37 n. 114;
  • 28
    • 49749142916 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For that reason, it is safe to argue that Skinner's and Pettit's views are the same and any differences are of no important consequence for purposes of this article unless otherwise noted. For the most part I will refer to the most recent of Skinner's writings
    • Skinner, 'Classical Liberty', pp. 9-28). For that reason, it is safe to argue that Skinner's and Pettit's views are the same and any differences are of no important consequence for purposes of this article unless otherwise noted. For the most part I will refer to the most recent of Skinner's writings.
    • Classical Liberty , pp. 9-28
    • Skinner1
  • 29
    • 0003402019 scopus 로고
    • For those that have considered the distinction in passing see:, Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press
    • For those that have considered the distinction in passing see: Stephen Holmes, Passions and Constraint: On the Theory of Liberal Democracy (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1995), p. 28;
    • (1995) Passions and Constraint: On the Theory of Liberal Democracy , pp. 28
    • Holmes, S.1
  • 30
    • 49749104733 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Cambridge University Press
    • Charles Larmore, The Morals of Modernity (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1997), p. 124, n. 3;
    • (1997) The Morals of Modernity , Issue.3 , pp. 124
    • Larmore, C.1
  • 31
    • 0003777393 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press
    • Duncan Ivison, The Self at Liberty (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1997), pp. 77, 80;
    • (1997) The Self at Liberty
    • Ivison, D.1
  • 32
    • 84998044359 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thinking About Freedom
    • 861-5
    • Roger Boesche, 'Thinking About Freedom', Political Theory 26 (1998): 855-73 (861-5).
    • (1998) Political Theory , vol.26 , pp. 855-873
    • Boesche, R.1
  • 33
    • 84928838891 scopus 로고
    • Liberalism and Republicanism
    • For those that question the viability of republicanism as an alternative to liberalism see
    • For those that question the viability of republicanism as an alternative to liberalism see: Jeffrey Isaac, 'Liberalism and Republicanism', History of Political Thought 9 (1988): 349-77;
    • (1988) History of Political Thought , vol.9 , pp. 349-377
    • Isaac, J.1
  • 34
    • 0345660634 scopus 로고
    • Quentin Skinner on the Idea of Freedom
    • John Charvet, 'Quentin Skinner on the Idea of Freedom', Studies in Political Thought 2 (1993): 5-16;
    • (1993) Studies in Political Thought , vol.2 , pp. 5-16
    • Charvet, J.1
  • 36
    • 84929760673 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In pursuing this line of inquiry, I bracket whether contemporary republicans have accurately described the tradition to which they belong from a historical perspective. For at least two recent accounts that cast doubt on the description of the tradition and whether it ought to be distinguished from liberalism see:, New York: Cambridge University Press
    • In pursuing this line of inquiry, I bracket whether contemporary republicans have accurately described the tradition to which they belong from a historical perspective. For at least two recent accounts that cast doubt on the description of the tradition and whether it ought to be distinguished from liberalism see: Vickie B. Sullivan, Machiavelli, Hobbes, and the Formation of a Liberal Republicanism in England (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2004), pp. 1-27;
    • (2004) Machiavelli, Hobbes, and the Formation of a Liberal Republicanism in England , pp. 1-27
    • Sullivan, V.B.1
  • 38
    • 0141707726 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In a very different way, John McCormick encourages us to resist the revival of republicanism. As he writes in a passage worth quoting: 'Scholars of republican political thought associated with the Cambridge School, often use insights derived from their historical and theoretical research in an attempt to inform, enhance, and broaden contemporary political theory and practice. They admirably show us what contemporary liberal democracy, whatever commonalties it shares with republicanism, lacks in contrast with the latter tradition: for example, the expression of a non-xenophobic patriotism, attention to the common good, emphasis on duties as opposed to rights, and the importance of more substantive political participation. However, on the basis of what follows, I implore these scholars to desist in such endeavors. Because of the traditional oligarchic tendencies of republicanism I plead with them, and those influenced by them, to reconsider the use of the term and cease in the attem
    • In a very different way, John McCormick encourages us to resist the revival of republicanism. As he writes in a passage worth quoting: 'Scholars of republican political thought associated with the Cambridge School . . . often use insights derived from their historical and theoretical research in an attempt to inform, enhance, and broaden contemporary political theory and practice. They admirably show us what contemporary liberal democracy, whatever commonalties it shares with republicanism, lacks in contrast with the latter tradition: for example, the expression of a non-xenophobic patriotism, attention to the common good, emphasis on duties as opposed to rights, and the importance of more substantive political participation. However, on the basis of what follows, I implore these scholars to desist in such endeavors. Because of the traditional oligarchic tendencies of republicanism I plead with them, and those influenced by them, to reconsider the use of the term and cease in the attempt to supplement contemporary democracy with insights from that tradition. I am convinced that republicanism, unless reconstructed almost beyond the point of recognition, can only reinforce what is worst about contemporary liberal democracy: the free hand that socioeconomic and political elites enjoy at the expense of the general populace'. See John McCormick, 'Machiavelli Against Republicanism: On the Cambridge School's "Guicciardinian Moments"', Political Theory 31 (2003): 615-43 (616-17). I am not willing to go this far with McCormick largely because it reifies republicanism in ways that ignore historical developments within the tradition.
  • 39
    • 77951897375 scopus 로고
    • Theoretical Foundations of Liberalism
    • 127
    • Jeremy Waldron, 'Theoretical Foundations of Liberalism', Philosophical Quarterly 37 (1987): 127-50 (127).
    • (1987) Philosophical Quarterly , vol.37 , pp. 127-150
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 40
    • 49749091957 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Two Concepts
    • Berlin, 'Two Concepts', pp. 121-2.
    • Berlin1
  • 41
  • 42
    • 49749147411 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ibid., pp. 141-61.
    • Berlin1
  • 43
    • 12944277995 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Liberty: One Concept Too Many
    • He makes a similar point about negative liberty, although without extensive discussion. And to be fair to the characterization, Berlin's point is not that positive liberty is necessarily totalitarian or hostile to liberal politics, but rather that the theory has promoted ideals that have been put to ill-liberal ends. For a recent argument on the incoherence of positive liberty see
    • He makes a similar point about negative liberty, although without extensive discussion. And to be fair to the characterization, Berlin's point is not that positive liberty is necessarily totalitarian or hostile to liberal politics, but rather that the theory has promoted ideals that have been put to ill-liberal ends. For a recent argument on the incoherence of positive liberty see: Eric Nelson, 'Liberty: One Concept Too Many', Political Theory 33 (2005): 58-78.
    • (2005) Political Theory , vol.33 , pp. 58-78
    • Nelson, E.1
  • 44
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Columbia University Press
    • John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996), p. 206.
    • (1996) Political Liberalism , pp. 206
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 45
    • 49749127018 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Skinner, Liberty, p. x;
    • Skinner, Liberty, p. x;
  • 60
  • 63
    • 49749147410 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ibid., pp. 5, 87.
    • Pettit1
  • 64
    • 0142006304 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Indeed, Viroli uses these examples, once again, to emphasize precisely the distinction between republicanism and liberalism he intended to reject. See, ch. 2
    • Indeed, Viroli uses these examples, once again, to emphasize precisely the distinction between republicanism and liberalism he intended to reject. See Viroli, Republicanism, ch. 2.
    • Republicanism
    • Viroli1
  • 75
  • 82
    • 49749093317 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Here a difference emerges between Skinner and Pettit. Skinner argues that republicans do not 'wish to deny that the exercise of force or the coercive threat of it must be listed among the forms of constraint that interfere with individual liberty, He goes on to say that 'Pettit imputes to defenders of republican freedom the view that, since it is only arbitrary domination that limits individual liberty, the act of obeying a law to which you have given your consent is entirely consistent with freedom. The writers I am discussing never deal in such paradoxes. For them the difference between the rule of law and government by personal prerogative is not that the former leaves you in full possession of your liberty while the latter does not; it is rather that the former only coerces you while the latter additionally leave you in a state of dependence, Skinner, Liberty, p. 83, n. 54;
    • Here a difference emerges between Skinner and Pettit. Skinner argues that republicans do not 'wish to deny that the exercise of force or the coercive threat of it must be listed among the forms of constraint that interfere with individual liberty'. He goes on to say that 'Pettit imputes to defenders of "republican" freedom the view that, since it is only arbitrary domination that limits individual liberty, the act of obeying a law to which you have given your consent is "entirely consistent with freedom." The writers I am discussing never deal in such paradoxes. For them the difference between the rule of law and government by personal prerogative is not that the former leaves you in full possession of your liberty while the latter does not; it is rather that the former only coerces you while the latter additionally leave you in a state of dependence' (Skinner, Liberty, p. 83, n. 54;
  • 83
    • 49749092584 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf. Pettit, Republicanism, pp. 66, 55, 56, n. 3.
    • cf. Pettit, Republicanism, pp. 66, 55, 56, n. 3).
  • 84
    • 49749147063 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • However, in his essay, 'Machiavelli on the Maintenance of Liberty', Skinner says that for Machiavelli 'the law can - and must - be used to force us to be free' (Skinner, 'Machiavelli', p. 10).
    • However, in his essay, 'Machiavelli on the Maintenance of Liberty', Skinner says that for Machiavelli 'the law can - and must - be used to force us to be free' (Skinner, 'Machiavelli', p. 10).
  • 85
    • 0036280967 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This expresses agreement with Pettit in that the force of law is not a constraint on one's freedom but rather allows for freedom to exist; cf. Philip Pettit, Keeping Republican Freedom Simple: On a Difference with Quentin Skinner, Political Theory 30 2002, 339-56. Perhaps this difference here has less to do with an evolution of Skinner's thoughts than with the differences between English republicans whom Skinner is primarily concerned with in the first text and Machiavelli who is central to the essay just cited
    • This expresses agreement with Pettit in that the force of law is not a constraint on one's freedom but rather allows for freedom to exist; cf. Philip Pettit, 'Keeping Republican Freedom Simple: On a Difference with Quentin Skinner', Political Theory 30 (2002): 339-56. Perhaps this difference here has less to do with an evolution of Skinner's thoughts than with the differences between English republicans whom Skinner is primarily concerned with in the first text and Machiavelli who is central to the essay just cited.
  • 88
    • 49749135656 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In one of her classic works, Carole Pateman worries that 'contemporary consent theory presents our institutions as if they were actually as consent demands, as if they were actually constituted through the free agreement of equal persons': Carole Pateman, The Disorder of Women: Democracy, Feminism and Political Theory (New York: Blackwell, 1989), p. 83.
    • In one of her classic works, Carole Pateman worries that 'contemporary consent theory presents our institutions as if they were actually as consent demands, as if they were actually constituted through the free agreement of equal persons': Carole Pateman, The Disorder of Women: Democracy, Feminism and Political Theory (New York: Blackwell, 1989), p. 83.
  • 89
    • 49749106928 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pateman makes this point by highlighting that 'even a fairly cursory reflection on the empirical evidence about voting behavior casts immediate doubt on the simple identification of consent with liberal-democratic voting' (Pateman, Disorder, p. 65).
    • Pateman makes this point by highlighting that 'even a fairly cursory reflection on the empirical evidence about voting behavior casts immediate doubt on the simple identification of consent with liberal-democratic voting' (Pateman, Disorder, p. 65).
  • 90
    • 49749111926 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The problem with Pateman's criticism is that she misunderstands the relationship between theory and practice. The point Waldron is making along with other contemporary consent theorists, as I will highlight, is not whether consent actually happens through voting or some other mechanism, but whether the laws that organize society can be represented as laws to which rational agents would agree. When framed in this light, liberal regimes provide ground for contesting 'arrangements or institutions inasmuch as one can show that it has not secured, or perhaps could not secure, the consent of the people': Waldron, 'Liberalism', p. 140.
    • The problem with Pateman's criticism is that she misunderstands the relationship between theory and practice. The point Waldron is making along with other contemporary consent theorists, as I will highlight, is not whether consent actually happens through voting or some other mechanism, but whether the laws that organize society can be represented as laws to which rational agents would agree. When framed in this light, liberal regimes provide ground for contesting 'arrangements or institutions inasmuch as one can show that it has not secured, or perhaps could not secure, the consent of the people': Waldron, 'Liberalism', p. 140.
  • 91
    • 0003687286 scopus 로고
    • For more on this distinction see the following works:, 2nd edn New York: Oxford University Press, 198;
    • For more on this distinction see the following works: William Connolly, The Terms of Political Discourse, 2nd edn (New York: Oxford University Press, 1983), pp. 22-34, 198;
    • (1983) The Terms of Political Discourse , pp. 22-34
    • Connolly, W.1
  • 92
    • 49749121373 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf. Stephen Toulmin and Kurt Baier, 'On Describing', in Ordinary Language, ed. Charles Caton (Chicago, IL: University of Illinois Press, 1953), pp. 20-46.
    • cf. Stephen Toulmin and Kurt Baier, 'On Describing', in Ordinary Language, ed. Charles Caton (Chicago, IL: University of Illinois Press, 1953), pp. 20-46.
  • 94
    • 49749131106 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course, in chapter 21 of Leviathan, Hobbes has a discussion of the 'Liberty of Subjects' in which agents retain certain self-defense rights against the sovereign. However, this is an issue that is never taken into prominent consideration when republicans connect Hobbes' views of freedom to liberalism; Hobbes, Leviathan, pp. 261-74
    • Of course, in chapter 21 of Leviathan, Hobbes has a discussion of the 'Liberty of Subjects' in which agents retain certain self-defense rights against the sovereign. However, this is an issue that is never taken into prominent consideration when republicans connect Hobbes' views of freedom to liberalism; Hobbes, Leviathan, pp. 261-74.
  • 95
    • 0003649180 scopus 로고
    • For a good discussion of Hobbes' notion of the liberty of the subjects see, New York: Cambridge University Press
    • For a good discussion of Hobbes' notion of the liberty of the subjects see Jean Hampton, Hobbes and the Social Contract Tradition (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1986), pp. 198-207, 239-55.
    • (1986) Hobbes and the Social Contract Tradition
    • Hampton, J.1
  • 97
    • 49749091957 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Two Concepts
    • Berlin, 'Two Concepts', p. 129.
    • Berlin1
  • 98
    • 0040155638 scopus 로고
    • What's Wrong With Negative Liberty
    • ed. David Miller New York: Oxford University Press
    • Charles Taylor, 'What's Wrong With Negative Liberty', in Liberty, ed. David Miller (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993), pp. 141-62.
    • (1993) Liberty , pp. 141-162
    • Taylor, C.1
  • 100
    • 0003101980 scopus 로고
    • Liberalism of Fear
    • ed. Nancy Rosenblum Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • Judith Shklar, 'Liberalism of Fear', in Liberalism and the Moral Life, ed. Nancy Rosenblum (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989), p. 24;
    • (1989) Liberalism and the Moral Life , pp. 24
    • Shklar, J.1
  • 102
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), p. 10, n. 4.
    • (1971) A Theory of Justice , Issue.4 , pp. 10
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 104
    • 0001457823 scopus 로고
    • Being Free to Act, and Being a Free Man
    • S. I. Benn and W. L. Weinstein, 'Being Free to Act, and Being a Free Man', Mind 80 (1971): 194-211;
    • (1971) Mind , vol.80 , pp. 194-211
    • Benn, S.I.1    Weinstein, W.L.2
  • 105
    • 84926271343 scopus 로고
    • Constraints on Freedom
    • 70
    • cf. David Miller, 'Constraints on Freedom', Ethics 94 (1983): 66-86 (70).
    • (1983) Ethics , vol.94 , pp. 66-86
    • cf1    Miller, D.2
  • 107
    • 0003275369 scopus 로고
    • The Liberty of the Ancients Compared with that of the Moderns
    • ed. Biancamaria Fontana New York: Cambridge University Press
    • Benjamin Constant, 'The Liberty of the Ancients Compared with that of the Moderns', in Political Writings, ed. Biancamaria Fontana (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1988[1819]), pp. 326-7;
    • (1819) Political Writings , pp. 326-327
    • Constant, B.1
  • 108
    • 0003348607 scopus 로고
    • The Public and Its Problems
    • ed. Jo Ann Boydston Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press
    • John Dewey, The Public and Its Problems, in Later Works, 1925-1953, vol. 2, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1988 [1927])
    • (1927) Later Works, 1925-1953 , vol.2
    • Dewey, J.1
  • 109
    • 49749095920 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and 'Democracy and Educational Administration', in Later Works, 1925-1953, 11, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1991[1937]), p. 220;
    • and 'Democracy and Educational Administration', in Later Works, 1925-1953, vol. 11, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1991[1937]), p. 220;
  • 112
  • 114
    • 33745658702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Moral Basis of Political Liberalism
    • 611
    • Charles Larmore, 'The Moral Basis of Political Liberalism', The Journal of Philosophy 96 (1999): 599-625 (611).
    • (1999) The Journal of Philosophy , vol.96 , pp. 599-625
    • Larmore, C.1
  • 115
    • 0036281102 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is precisely why, pace Raymond Geuss, the idealization is relevant; it implies that there is no permanent closure on institutional arrangements, laws and policies that govern us. At the existential level, this orients citizens to their political world in a way that differs from those living under authoritarian regimes; cf. Raymond Geuss, Liberalism and Its Discontents, Political Theory 30 (2002, 320-38 329
    • This is precisely why, pace Raymond Geuss, the idealization is relevant; it implies that there is no permanent closure on institutional arrangements, laws and policies that govern us. At the existential level, this orients citizens to their political world in a way that differs from those living under authoritarian regimes; cf. Raymond Geuss, 'Liberalism and Its Discontents', Political Theory 30 (2002): 320-38 (329).
  • 117
    • 0004223708 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Obviously, Dewey parts company with Dworkin's conflict-aversion thesis, a claim that does not take seriously the ways in which freedom and equality may conflict. See, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, ch. 3
    • Obviously, Dewey parts company with Dworkin's conflict-aversion thesis - a claim that does not take seriously the ways in which freedom and equality may conflict. See Ronald Dworkin, Sovereign Virtue (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000), ch. 3.
    • (2000) Sovereign Virtue
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 119
    • 49749083897 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ibid., pp. 55-66 (emphasis added); cf. 580-1.
    • ibid., pp. 55-66 (emphasis added); cf. 580-1.
  • 121
    • 49749091066 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Immanuel Kant, 'An Answer to the Question: What Is Enlightenment?', in Political Writings, ed. Hans Reiss, trans. N. B. Nisbet (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1970[1784]), pp. 55-6;
    • Immanuel Kant, 'An Answer to the Question: "What Is Enlightenment?"', in Political Writings, ed. Hans Reiss, trans. N. B. Nisbet (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1970[1784]), pp. 55-6;
  • 123
    • 0003457994 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Indeed, Larmore provides further clarification in that a commitment to transparency generates two additional constitutive principles, namely, the value of dialogue and equal respect; see
    • Indeed, Larmore provides further clarification in that a commitment to transparency generates two additional constitutive principles - namely, the value of dialogue and equal respect; see Larmore, Morals of Modernity, pp. 134-44,
    • Morals of Modernity , pp. 134-144
    • Larmore1
  • 124
    • 49749119414 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and 'Political Liberalism', pp. 599-625.
    • and 'Political Liberalism', pp. 599-625.
  • 126
    • 49749153051 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ibid., pp. 177-83.
    • Rawls1
  • 129
    • 49749109789 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • p. 246 emphasis added
    • ibid., p. 246 (emphasis added).
    • Rawls1
  • 130
    • 49749112782 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Ronald Dworkin, 'Liberalism', in Public and Private Morality, ed. Stuart Hampshire (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1978), pp. 113-43 especially p. 116, n. 1.
    • Cf. Ronald Dworkin, 'Liberalism', in Public and Private Morality, ed. Stuart Hampshire (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1978), pp. 113-43 especially p. 116, n. 1.
  • 131
    • 49749144023 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thus Rawls writes: '[W]hen the basic structure of society is publicly known to satisfy its principles for an extended period of time, those subject to these arrangements tend to develop a desire to act in accordance with these principles and to do their part in institutions which exemplify them'; Rawls, Theory of Justice, p. 177.
    • Thus Rawls writes: '[W]hen the basic structure of society is publicly known to satisfy its principles for an extended period of time, those subject to these arrangements tend to develop a desire to act in accordance with these principles and to do their part in institutions which exemplify them'; Rawls, Theory of Justice, p. 177.
  • 133
    • 49749114746 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ibid., p. 205, cf. n. 37.
    • ibid., p. 205, cf. n. 37.
  • 135
    • 49749144814 scopus 로고
    • ed. Stefan Collini New York: Cambridge University Press
    • John Stuart Mill, On Liberty, ed. Stefan Collini (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1989[1859]), p. 103.
    • (1859) On Liberty , pp. 103
    • Stuart Mill, J.1
  • 137
    • 0004001507 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • emphasis added
    • Mill, On Liberty, p. 105 (emphasis added).
    • On Liberty , pp. 105
    • Mill1
  • 138
    • 49749138419 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Berlin was thus inaccurate when he said that for Mill, 'The despot who leaves his subjects a wide area of liberty may be unjust, or encourage the wildest inequalities, care little for order, or virtue, or knowledge; but provided he does not curb their liberty, or at least curbs it less than many other regimes, he meets with Mill's specification' (Berlin, 'Two Concepts', p. 129). Of course, I do not mean to suggest that the subordination of women was not historically defended under the banner of liberal principles. Indeed, republican principles share a similar history. But the point is whether or not liberalism has, as part of its commitment to freedom as non-interference, the ability to address the battered-wife example proffered by republicans.
    • Berlin was thus inaccurate when he said that for Mill, 'The despot who leaves his subjects a wide area of liberty may be unjust, or encourage the wildest inequalities, care little for order, or virtue, or knowledge; but provided he does not curb their liberty, or at least curbs it less than many other regimes, he meets with Mill's specification' (Berlin, 'Two Concepts', p. 129). Of course, I do not mean to suggest that the subordination of women was not historically defended under the banner of liberal principles. Indeed, republican principles share a similar history. But the point is whether or not liberalism has, as part of its commitment to freedom as non-interference, the ability to address the battered-wife example proffered by republicans.
  • 139
    • 49749112276 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Larmore says that Mill does not fit into this category and that he expresses a view of freedom that 'goes back through Bentham to Hobbes, Larmore, Morals of Modernity, p. 124, n. 2
    • Larmore says that Mill does not fit into this category and that he expresses a view of freedom that 'goes back through Bentham to Hobbes' (Larmore, Morals of Modernity, p. 124, n. 2).
  • 140
    • 49749153049 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This view misunderstands Mill's principle of liberty. As Mill writes in Utilitarianism: 'The interest involved is that of security, to every one's feelings the most vital of all interests. Nearly all other earthly benefits are needed by one person, not needed by another; and many of them can, if necessary, be cheerfully foregone, or replaced by something else; but security no human being can possibly do without; on it we depend for all our immunity from evil, and for the whole value of all and every good, beyond the passing moment; since nothing but the gratification of the instance could be of any worth to us, if we could be deprived of anything the next instant by whoever was momentarily stronger than ourselves, John Stuart Mill, Utilitarianism, ed. H. B. Acton New York: Dent, 1972[1863, p. 56
    • This view misunderstands Mill's principle of liberty. As Mill writes in Utilitarianism: 'The interest involved is that of security, to every one's feelings the most vital of all interests. Nearly all other earthly benefits are needed by one person, not needed by another; and many of them can, if necessary, be cheerfully foregone, or replaced by something else; but security no human being can possibly do without; on it we depend for all our immunity from evil, and for the whole value of all and every good, beyond the passing moment; since nothing but the gratification of the instance could be of any worth to us, if we could be deprived of anything the next instant by whoever was momentarily stronger than ourselves'; John Stuart Mill, Utilitarianism, ed. H. B. Acton (New York: Dent, 1972[1863]), p. 56.
  • 141
    • 49749135419 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • John Gray rightly notes of this passage that, 'Mill conceives of security primarily in terms of reliability of established expectations. Violation of one's legal rights . . . the kind of uncertainty which accompanies both arbitrary despotism and weak government - all these are circumstances in which expectations are subject to unpredictable disappointments which in Mill's view amount to an insecurity of freedom';
    • John Gray rightly notes of this passage that, 'Mill conceives of security primarily in terms of reliability of established expectations. Violation of one's legal rights . . . the kind of uncertainty which accompanies both arbitrary despotism and weak government - all these are circumstances in which expectations are subject to unpredictable disappointments which in Mill's view amount to an insecurity of freedom';
  • 142
    • 49749089996 scopus 로고
    • New York: Routledge, ch. 3, pp
    • John Gray, Mill On Liberty: A Defense (New York: Routledge, 1983), ch. 3, pp. 53-4.
    • (1983) Mill On Liberty: A Defense , pp. 53-54
    • Gray, J.1
  • 144
    • 49749134992 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thus William Connolly observes that 'the notion of a constraint, then, involves the idea of a normal range of conduct people can be expected to undertake or forgo when doing so restricts the options of others' (Connolly, Terms, p. 165).
    • Thus William Connolly observes that 'the notion of a constraint, then, involves the idea of a normal range of conduct people can be expected to undertake or forgo when doing so restricts the options of others' (Connolly, Terms, p. 165).
  • 146
    • 49749119914 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As Locke writes on just this point:, F]or law, in its true notion, is not so much the limitation, as the direction of a free and intelligent agent to his proper interest, and prescribes no farther than is for the general good of those under that law: could they be happier without it, the law, as an useless thing, would of itself vanish, So that, however it may be mistaken, the end of law is not to abolish or restrain, but to preserve and enlarge freedom: for in all the states of created beings capable of laws, where there is no law, there is no freedom; for liberty is to be free from restraint and violence from others: which cannot be where there is not law: but freedom is not, as we are told, a liberty for every man to do what he lists for who could be free, when every other man's humour might domineer over him, but a liberty to dispose and order as he lists his person, actions, possessions, and his whole property, within the allowance of those
    • As Locke writes on just this point: '[F]or law, in its true notion, is not so much the limitation, as the direction of a free and intelligent agent to his proper interest, and prescribes no farther than is for the general good of those under that law: could they be happier without it, the law, as an useless thing, would of itself vanish. . . . So that, however it may be mistaken, the end of law is not to abolish or restrain, but to preserve and enlarge freedom: for in all the states of created beings capable of laws, "where there is no law, there is no freedom"; for liberty is to be free from restraint and violence from others: which cannot be where there is not law: but freedom is not, as we are told, "a liberty for every man to do what he lists" (for who could be free, when every other man's humour might domineer over him?) but a liberty to dispose and order as he lists his person, actions, possessions, and his whole property, within the allowance of those laws under which he is, and therein not to be subject to the arbitrary will of another, but freely follow his own'; Locke, Two Treatises, pp. 123-4 (emphasis added).
  • 148
    • 49749103516 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ibid., p. 241.
    • Rawls1
  • 149
    • 49749147062 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To be sure, Rawls does refer to 'Hobbes' thesis' in the section where he takes up the relationship between rule of law and liberty. However, on closer inspection, Rawls' reference is to Hobbes' insight concerning the tendency of agents to lack confidence in each other regarding compliance to the laws, and not to Hobbes' conception of freedom as Skinner believes. Thus, Rawls writes, the suspicion that others are not honoring their duties and obligation is increased by the fact that, in the absence of the authoritative interpretation and enforcement of the rules, it is particularly easy to find excuses for breaking them, This proposition we may think of as Hobbes' thesis, Rawls, Theory of Justice, p. 240
    • To be sure, Rawls does refer to 'Hobbes' thesis' in the section where he takes up the relationship between rule of law and liberty. However, on closer inspection, Rawls' reference is to Hobbes' insight concerning the tendency of agents to lack confidence in each other regarding compliance to the laws, and not to Hobbes' conception of freedom as Skinner believes. Thus, Rawls writes, 'the suspicion that others are not honoring their duties and obligation is increased by the fact that, in the absence of the authoritative interpretation and enforcement of the rules, it is particularly easy to find excuses for breaking them. . . . This proposition we may think of as Hobbes' thesis'; Rawls, Theory of Justice, p. 240.
  • 155
    • 49749091957 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Two Concepts
    • Berlin, 'Two Concepts', pp. 147-78, 152-3.
    • Berlin1
  • 157
    • 0003750156 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Cambridge University Press
    • William Galston, Liberal Purposes (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1992);
    • (1992) Liberal Purposes
    • Galston, W.1
  • 159
    • 49749099170 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • All three thinkers are clear that liberalism has its own distinct virtues, but for them, especially Macedo and Galston, it will often be the case that we must appeal to extra-liberal institutions or a pre-liberal ethos to ensure that those virtues are consistently generated Macedo, Liberal Virtues, p. 285;
    • All three thinkers are clear that liberalism has its own distinct virtues, but for them, especially Macedo and Galston, it will often be the case that we must appeal to extra-liberal institutions or a pre-liberal ethos to ensure that those virtues are consistently generated (Macedo, Liberal Virtues, p. 285;
  • 161
    • 49749097454 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course the immediate question to ask, which I hope this article anticipates, is the following: who are these supposed liberals that Skinner and Pettit want to criticize? Perhaps, as Colin Bird suggested to me, they have the doctrine of economic liberalism in mind that is regularly employed in public discourse and the conventional ideology of corporate capitalism. The basic claim here is that freedom means leaving people to their own devices and limiting the right of the state to intrude in the private transactions of 'consenting adults, The worry over discretionary power usually has as its target not the liberal state as such, but rather the corporations whose dominating practices might receive excessive protection under a regime that affirms a vision of negative liberty. I am inclined to say that none of the thinkers with whom I am concerned, especially Rawls, is a friend of this position. Indeed, we lump them in this category at the risk of simply getting them wrong
    • Of course the immediate question to ask, which I hope this article anticipates, is the following: who are these supposed liberals that Skinner and Pettit want to criticize? Perhaps, as Colin Bird suggested to me, they have the doctrine of economic liberalism in mind that is regularly employed in public discourse and the conventional ideology of corporate capitalism. The basic claim here is that freedom means leaving people to their own devices and limiting the right of the state to intrude in the private transactions of 'consenting adults'. The worry over discretionary power usually has as its target not the liberal state as such, but rather the corporations whose dominating practices might receive excessive protection under a regime that affirms a vision of negative liberty. I am inclined to say that none of the thinkers with whom I am concerned, especially Rawls, is a friend of this position. Indeed, we lump them in this category at the risk of simply getting them wrong.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.