메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 101, Issue 3, 2004, Pages 111-139

On the systematicity of language and thought
[No Author Info available]

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 49549096030     PISSN: 0022362X     EISSN: 19398549     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.5840/jphil2004101321     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (71)

References (33)
  • 1
    • 0023968207 scopus 로고
    • Connectionism and Cognitive Architecture: A Critical Analysis
    • For example, Jerry Fodor and Zenon Pylyshyn, "Connectionism and Cognitive Architecture: A Critical Analysis," Cognition, XXVIII (1988): 3-71
    • (1988) Cognition , vol.28 , pp. 3-71
    • Fodor, J.1    Pylyshyn, Z.2
  • 3
    • 84979417874 scopus 로고
    • The Constituent Structure of Mental States: A Reply to Fodor and Pylyshyn
    • Paul Smolensky, "The Constituent Structure of Mental States: A Reply to Fodor and Pylyshyn," Southern Journal of Philosophy, XXVI (1987): 137-60
    • (1987) Southern Journal of Philosophy , vol.26 , pp. 137-160
    • Smolensky, P.1
  • 4
    • 84971179405 scopus 로고
    • On the Proper Treatment of Connectionism
    • Smolensky
    • Smolensky, "On the Proper Treatment of Connectionism," Behavioral and Brain Sciences, XI (1988): 1-23
    • (1988) Behavioral and Brain Sciences, XI , pp. 1-23
  • 5
    • 84986860288 scopus 로고
    • Systematicity in Connectionist Language Learning
    • Robert Hadley, "Systematicity in Connectionist Language Learning," Mind and Language, IX (1994): 247-72
    • (1994) Mind and Language , vol.9 , pp. 247-272
    • Hadley, R.1
  • 6
    • 0012572304 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cognition, Systematicity, and Nomic Necessity
    • Hadley
    • Hadley, "Cognition, Systematicity, and Nomic Necessity," Mind and Language, XII (1997): 137-53
    • (1997) Mind and Language , vol.12 , pp. 137-153
  • 7
    • 84986837759 scopus 로고
    • On Being Systematically Connectionist
    • Lars Niklasson and Tim van Gelder, "On Being Systematically Connectionist," Mind and Language, IX (1994): 288-302
    • (1994) Mind and Language , vol.9 , pp. 288-302
    • Niklasson, L.1    Van Gelder, T.2
  • 8
    • 0010881690 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Systematicity
    • 12 December
    • Robert Cummins, "Systematicity," this JOURNAL, XCIII, 12 (December 1996): 591-614. The bibliographies of these papers contain many more citations
    • (1996) This JOURNAL , vol.93 , pp. 591-614
    • Cummins, R.1
  • 12
    • 0009150124 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Can Connectionists Explain Systematicity?
    • here p. 175.
    • "Can Connectionists Explain Systematicity?" Mind and Language, XII, 2 (1997): 154-77, here p. 175
    • (1997) Mid and Language , vol.12 , Issue.2 , pp. 154-177
  • 13
    • 61249509235 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Niklasson and van Gelder; Cummins; and Hadley for similar comments to this effect
    • Cf. Niklasson and van Gelder; Cummins; and Hadley for similar comments to this effect
  • 14
  • 16
    • 0026110506 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jess Gropen, Pinker, Michelle Hollander, and Richard Goldberg, Syntax and Semantics in the Acquisition of Locative Verbs, Journal of Child Language, XVIII (1991): 115-51.
    • Jess Gropen, Pinker, Michelle Hollander, and Richard Goldberg, "Syntax and Semantics in the Acquisition of Locative Verbs," Journal of Child Language, XVIII (1991): 115-51
  • 17
    • 79954375766 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf., for example, Pinker, pp. 45-47 for more discussion.
    • Cf., for example, Pinker, pp. 45-47 for more discussion
  • 18
    • 0038405691 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Distributivity and Negation: The Syntax of Each and Every
    • Anna Szabolcsi, ed, Boston: Kluwer
    • For example, Filippo Beghelli and Tim Stowell, "Distributivity and Negation: The Syntax of Each and Every," in Anna Szabolcsi, ed., Ways of Scope Taking (Boston: Kluwer, 1997), pp. 71-107
    • (1997) Ways of Scope Taking , pp. 71-107
    • Beghelli, F.1    Stowell, T.2
  • 21
    • 34248732979 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Does Syntax Reveal Semantics? A Case Study of Complex Demonstratives
    • in James E. Tomberlin, ed
    • Kent Johnson and Ernie Lepore, "Does Syntax Reveal Semantics? A Case Study of Complex Demonstratives," in James E. Tomberlin, ed., Philosophical Perspectives: Language and Mind, XVI (2002): 17-41
    • (2002) Philosophical Perspectives: Language and Mind , vol.16 , pp. 17-41
    • Johnson, K.1    Lepore, E.2
  • 22
    • 60949187421 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Meanings
    • eds, NewYork: Seven Bridges
    • Stephen Schiffer, "Meanings," in Joseph Keim Campbell, Michael O'Rourke and David Shier, eds., Meaning and Truth (NewYork: Seven Bridges, 2002), pp. 79-102
    • (2002) Meaning and Truth , pp. 79-102
    • Schiffer, S.1
  • 23
    • 0003564330 scopus 로고
    • Westport, CT: Praeger, ch. 3
    • For more discussion, cf. Noam Chomsky, Knowledge of Language (Westport, CT: Praeger, 1986), ch. 3
    • (1986) Knowledge of Language
    • Chomsky, N.1
  • 26
    • 0004242804 scopus 로고
    • Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall
    • Such a position appears to have been adopted by W.V. Quine, Philosophy of Logic (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1970), p. 18
    • (1970) Philosophy of Logic , pp. 18
    • Quine, W.V.1
  • 28
    • 0008668735 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Event Structure in Syntax
    • Carol Tenny and James Pustejovsky, eds, Stanford: CSLI
    • Lisa Travis, "Event Structure in Syntax," in Carol Tenny and James Pustejovsky, eds., Events as Grammatical Objects (Stanford: CSLI, 2000), pp. 145-85
    • (2000) Events As Grammatical Objects , pp. 145-185
    • Travis, L.1
  • 29
    • 0003105069 scopus 로고
    • On Argument Structure and the Lexical Expression of Syntactic Relations
    • in Hale and Keyser, eds, Cambridge: MIT, especially p. 102
    • This bit of structure is overtly realized as a morpheme in hundreds of languages; cf. Kenneth Hale and Samuel Jay Keyser, "On Argument Structure and the Lexical Expression of Syntactic Relations," in Hale and Keyser, eds., The View from Building 20 (Cambridge: MIT, 1993), pp. 53-109, see especially p. 102
    • (1993) The View from Building , vol.20 , pp. 53-109
    • Hale, K.1    Keyser, S.J.2
  • 30
    • 79954185198 scopus 로고
    • That [i]nsofar as there are 'theory neutral' data to constrain our speculations about language, systematicity] surely ought to count as one of them
    • Cambridge: MIT
    • It is worth noting that determining the correct linguistic categories is an ongoing project in contemporary linguistics. Thus, it is simply false to say, as Fodor does, that "[i]nsofar as there are 'theory neutral' data to constrain our speculations about language, [systematicity] surely ought to count as one of them" - Psychosemantics (Cambridge: MIT, 1987), p. 150. Even saying what systematicity is, much less whether language has systematicity or not, rests on the highly theoretical notion of a taxonomy of linguistic kinds over which systematicity is defined
    • (1987) Psychosemantics , pp. 150
  • 31
    • 79954322299 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fodor, p. 153;
    • For example, Fodor, p. 153
  • 32
    • 0041136021 scopus 로고
    • Constituent Structure and Explanation in an Integrated Connectionist/Symbolic Cognitive Architecture
    • Fodor and Pylyshyn; Fodor and McLaughlin; Niklasson and van Gelder; Smolensky (Cambridge: Blackwell
    • Fodor and Pylyshyn; Fodor and McLaughlin; Niklasson and van Gelder; Smolensky, "Constituent Structure and Explanation in an Integrated Connectionist/Symbolic Cognitive Architecture," in Cynthia Macdonald and Graham Macdonald, eds., Connectionism: Debates on Psychological Explanation (Cambridge: Blackwell, 1995), pp. 223-90
    • (1995) Connectionism: Debates on Psychological Explanation , pp. 223-290
    • MacDonald, C.1    MacDonald, G.2
  • 33
    • 0003906715 scopus 로고
    • Fodor, Cambridge: Harvard
    • Fodor, The Language of Thought (Cambridge: Harvard, 1975)
    • (1975) The Language of Thought


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.