메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 37, Issue 3, 2006, Pages 464-482

Environmental degradation, reparations, and the moral significance of history

(1)  Caney, Simon a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 49549093528     PISSN: 00472786     EISSN: 14679833     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/j.1467-9833.2006.00348.x     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (108)

References (34)
  • 1
    • 0003742376 scopus 로고
    • London: Penguin
    • James Joyce, Ulysses (London: Penguin, 1992 [1922]), p. 42.
    • (1922) Ulysses , pp. 42
    • Joyce, J.1
  • 3
    • 84888625423 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The law of peoples
    • Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press
    • See Rawls's highly pertinent discussion of what he terms "problems of extension" in "The Law of Peoples," in Collected Papers, ed. Samuel Freeman (Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), 531.
    • (1999) Collected Papers , pp. 531
    • Freeman, S.1
  • 4
    • 36448973630 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Climate change and water resources: A global perspective
    • ed. Hans Joachim Schellnhuber et al. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Nigel W. Arnell, "Climate Change and Water Resources: A Global Perspective," in Avoiding Dangerous Climate Change, ed. Hans Joachim Schellnhuber et al. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), 167.
    • (2006) Avoiding Dangerous Climate Change , pp. 167
    • Arnell, N.W.1
  • 5
    • 33746202559 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Impacts of climate change in the tropics: The African experience
    • ed. Hans Joachim Schellnhuber et al. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Anthony Nyong and Isabelle Niang-Diop, "Impacts of Climate Change in the Tropics: The African Experience," in Avoiding Dangerous Climate Change, ed. Hans Joachim Schellnhuber et al. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), 237.
    • (2006) Avoiding Dangerous Climate Change , pp. 237
    • Nyong, A.1    Niang-Diop, I.2
  • 6
    • 49549090790 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Relationship between increases in global mean temperature and impacts on ecosystems, food production, water and socio-economic systems
    • ed. Hans Joachim Schellnhuber et al. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Bill Hare, "Relationship between Increases in Global Mean Temperature and Impacts on Ecosystems, Food Production, Water and Socio-economic Systems," in Avoiding Dangerous Climate Change, ed. Hans Joachim Schellnhuber et al. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), 179.
    • (2006) Avoiding Dangerous Climate Change , pp. 179
    • Hare, B.1
  • 8
    • 27844519343 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Global pattern of trends in streamflow and water availability in a changing climate
    • P. C. D. Milly, K. A. Dunne, and A. V. Vecchia, "Global Pattern of Trends in Streamflow and Water Availability in a Changing Climate," Nature 438, no. 7066 (2005): 347.
    • (2005) Nature , vol.438 , Issue.7066 , pp. 347
    • Milly, P.C.D.1    Dunne, K.A.2    Vecchia, A.V.3
  • 9
    • 84888635636 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Global responsibilities: Ethics, public health, and global environmental change
    • The Causal Account is similar to, but importantly different from, what Dale Jamieson calls "the causal paradigm" in his "Global Responsibilities: Ethics, Public Health, and Global Environmental Change," Indiana Journal of Global Legal Studies 5 (1998): 116-17.
    • (1998) Indiana Journal of Global Legal Studies , vol.5 , pp. 116-117
  • 12
    • 0040962815 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Global environment and international inequality
    • Henry Shue, "Global Environment and International Inequality," International Affairs 75, no. 3 (1999): 533-37.
    • (1999) International Affairs , vol.75 , Issue.3 , pp. 533-537
    • Shue, H.1
  • 13
    • 0034017359 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In defence of historical accountability for greenhouse gas emissions
    • See, for example, Eric Neumayer, "In Defence of Historical Accountability for Greenhouse Gas Emissions," Ecological Economics 33 (2000): 186.
    • (2000) Ecological Economics , vol.33 , pp. 186
    • Neumayer, E.1
  • 14
    • 84888630108 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • That in Brazil the exemption from taxation of virtually all agricultural income, allied to the fact that logging is regarded as proof of land occupancy, has provided incentives to the rich to acquire forests and then to deforest the land
    • Dasgupta writes Oxford: Oxford University Press (footnote 25 omitted)
    • A nice example is given by Partha Dasgupta. Dasgupta writes "that in Brazil the exemption from taxation of virtually all agricultural income, allied to the fact that logging is regarded as proof of land occupancy, has provided incentives to the rich to acquire forests and then to deforest the land," Human Well-Being and the Natural Environment (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001), 114 (footnote 25 omitted).
    • (2001) Human Well-Being and the Natural Environment , pp. 114
    • Dasgupta, P.1
  • 15
    • 84888594276 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Neumayer writes: "where boundary changes have occurred, as in the case of the former Soviet Union, there is no reason why a new nation-state should not be held accountable for emissions that were undertaken on the territory within its current boundaries," in his "In Defence of Historical Accountability," 189.
    • Defence of Historical Accountability , pp. 189
  • 16
    • 66349111754 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Historical emissions and free-riding
    • especially pp. 42-46 and also pp. 46-53
    • Axel Gosseries, "Historical Emissions and Free-Riding," Ethical Perspectives 11, no.1 (2004): 36-60, especially pp. 42-46 and also pp. 46-53.
    • (2004) Ethical Perspectives , vol.11 , Issue.1 , pp. 36-60
    • Gosseries, A.1
  • 19
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • rev. ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • See, more generally, the canonical treatment of "the principle of fairness" by Rawls in A Theory of Justice, rev. ed. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), 96-98.
    • (1999) A Theory of Justice , pp. 96-98
    • Rawls1
  • 20
    • 0003740191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press cf. further pp. 487-88
    • This conception of what it means to benefit someone is equivalent to what Derek Parfit terms "[t]he Two-State Requirement" where this states that "[w]e benefit someone only if we cause him to be better off than he would otherwise at that time have been," Derek Parfit, Reasons and Persons (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986), 487: cf. further pp. 487-88.
    • (1986) Reasons and Persons , pp. 487
    • Parfit, D.1
  • 22
    • 0003333322 scopus 로고
    • Obligations to posterity
    • eds. R. I. Sikora and Brian Barry Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press
    • and Thomas Schwartz "Obligations to Posterity," in Obligations to Future Generations, eds. R. I. Sikora and Brian Barry (Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press, 1978), 3-13.
    • (1978) Obligations to Future Generations , pp. 3-13
    • Schwartz, T.1
  • 23
    • 27844510370 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Who can be wronged?
    • 31
    • For an interesting non-consequentialist response to Parfit, which draws on Scanlon's contractualism, see Rahul Kumar, "Who Can Be Wronged?" Philosophy and Public Affairs, 31, no. 2 (2003): 98-118.
    • (2003) Philosophy and Public Affairs , Issue.2 , pp. 98-118
    • Kumar, R.1
  • 24
    • 0003983843 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • This argument is made by John Broome, Ethics out of Economics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), 168,
    • (1999) Ethics Out of Economics , pp. 168
    • Broome, J.1
  • 25
    • 0003683199 scopus 로고
    • Berkeley: University of California Press 122-24
    • and similar thoughts are expressed by David Heyd, Genethics: Moral Issues in the Creation of People (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1992), 30-31 and 122-24.
    • (1992) Genethics: Moral issues in the Creation of People , pp. 30-31
    • Heyd, D.1
  • 26
    • 84880401083 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Parfit also anticipates this argument (but does not commit himself to it): cf. Reasons and Persons, 358 and, more generally, 487-90.
    • Reasons and Persons , pp. 358
  • 27
    • 34548542622 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the value of coming into existence
    • interesting especially p. 370ff
    • For a clear statement of the argument in the text and a challenge to it, see Nils Holtug's interesting "On the Value of Coming into Existence," Journal of Ethics 5, no. 4 (2001), especially p. 370ff and his formulation of premises (1)-(3) on pp. 371-72.
    • (2001) Journal of Ethics , vol.5 , Issue.4
    • Holtug's, N.1
  • 28
    • 0035200468 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Can we harm future people?
    • footnote 18
    • The argument in the text is also denied by Alan Carter, "Can We Harm Future People?" Environmental Values 10 (2001): 451, footnote 18.
    • (2001) Environmental Values , vol.10 , pp. 451
    • Carter, A.1
  • 29
    • 84888616010 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 49-52
    • Gosseries, note, maintains that benefiting from industrialization only generates duties of reparation if performing the cost of doing so does not exceed the benefit one has gained, "Historical Emissions and Free-Riding," 47 and 49-52. See also his discussion of what should happen if the costs exceed the benefits (pp. 49-52).
    • Historical Emissions and Free-Riding , pp. 47
  • 30
    • 0004273805 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Basil Blackwell 230-31
    • Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State and Utopia (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1974), 152-53 and 230-31.
    • (1974) Anarchy, State and Utopia , pp. 152-153
    • Nozick, R.1
  • 31
    • 84888593903 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A global resources dividend
    • Lanham, MD: Rowman and Little-field
    • Although he does not make this distinction, I believe that one of Thomas Pogge's arguments can be classified as a Negative argument in the sense that I am using it. See Pogge's discussion of historic wrongs in "A Global Resources Dividend," in Ethics of Consumption: The Good Life, Justice, and Global Stewardship, ed. David A. Crocker and Toby Linden (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Little-field, 1998), 509
    • (1998) Ethics of Consumption: The Good Life, Justice, and Global Stewardship , pp. 509
    • Crocker, D.A.1    Linden, T.2
  • 32
    • 33644931649 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Real world justice
    • 41
    • and "Real World Justice," Journal of Ethics 9 (2005): 38-39 and 41.
    • (2005) Journal of Ethics , vol.9 , pp. 38-39
  • 33
    • 85016069698 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cosmopolitan justice, responsibility and global climate change
    • See Simon Caney, "Cosmopolitan Justice, Responsibility and Global Climate Change," Leiden Journal of International Law 18, no. 4 (2005): 747-75.
    • (2005) Leiden Journal of International Law , vol.18 , Issue.4 , pp. 747-775
    • Caney, S.1
  • 34
    • 54749119636 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cosmopolitan justice, rights and global climate change
    • Indeed I have argued elsewhere that there is a human right not to suffer from the ill-effects of global climate change. See "Cosmopolitan Justice, Rights and Global Climate Change," Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 9, no. 2 (2006): 255-78.
    • (2006) Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence , vol.9 , Issue.2 , pp. 255-278


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.