메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 59, Issue 1, 2001, Pages 59-71

Moral prejudice and aesthetic deformity: Rereading Hume's "Of the Standard of Taste"

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 48349137233     PISSN: 00218529     EISSN: 15406245     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/0021-8529.00007     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (15)

References (32)
  • 1
    • 84963088891 scopus 로고
    • Hume's Aesthetics Reassessed
    • See Peter Jones, "Hume's Aesthetics Reassessed," The Philosophical Quarterly 26 (1976): 56.
    • (1976) The Philosophical Quarterly , vol.26 , pp. 56
    • Jones, P.1
  • 2
    • 0003970946 scopus 로고
    • Eugene F. Miller (Indianapolis: Liberty Fund)
    • All references to Hume's essays are to David Hume, Essays Moral, Political, and Literary, ed. Eugene F. Miller (Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 1985).
    • (1985) Essays Moral, Political, and Literary
    • Hume, D.1
  • 3
    • 79953481483 scopus 로고
    • revised by P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press)
    • Hereafter, I give all references to "Of the Standard of Taste" (1757) in the text, in parentheses. Other works by Hume to which I refer are the essay "Of Moral Prejudices" (1742), A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge, revised by P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989),
    • (1989) A Treatise of Human Nature
    • Selby-Bigge, L.A.1
  • 5
    • 34347320999 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Contemporary moralist aestheticians influenced by Hume's essay include: Noël Carroll, Moderate Moralisin
    • Contemporary moralist aestheticians influenced by Hume's essay include: Noël Carroll, "Moderate Moralisin," The British Journal of Aesthetics 36 (1996): 223-238,
    • (1996) The British Journal of Aesthetics , vol.36 , pp. 223-238
  • 6
    • 0038186319 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Ethical Criticism of Art
    • Jerrold Levinson New York: Cambridge University Press
    • and Berys Gaut, "The Ethical Criticism of Art," in Aesthetics and Ethics: Essays at the Intersection, ed. Jerrold Levinson (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998), pp. 182-203. In the works cited, Carroll and Gaut primarily are engaged in defending their own brand of moralist aesthetics.
    • (1998) Aesthetics and Ethics: Essays at the Intersection , pp. 182-203
    • Gaut, B.1
  • 7
    • 0042364677 scopus 로고
    • The Expression of Feeling in Imagination
    • For particularly insightful discussions of Hume's essay in work whose primary concern is not to defend a moralist aesthetics, see Richard Moran, "The Expression of Feeling in Imagination," Philosophical Review 103 (1994): 75-106,
    • (1994) Philosophical Review , vol.103 , pp. 75-106
    • Moran, R.1
  • 8
    • 60949464138 scopus 로고
    • Morals in Fiction and Fictional Morality, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society
    • and Kendall Walton, "Morals in Fiction and Fictional Morality," Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, supplementary volume 68 (1994): 27-50.
    • (1994) Supplementary , vol.68 , pp. 27-50
    • Walton, K.1
  • 9
    • 0040350678 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Finally, Daniel Jacobson's "In Praise of Immoral Art," Philosophical Topics 25 (1997): 155-199, primarily takes issue with contemporary moralist aestheticians. Where Jacobson does attempt to offer a reading of Hume's views, however, he sometimes neglects responses that Hume could make in answer to his criticisms. Such neglect reinforces my view that contemporary aestheticians need to come to terms with Hume before presuming to argue in favor of, or against, a purportedly Humean moralist aesthetics.
    • (1997) Praise of Immoral Art, Philosophical Topics , vol.25 , pp. 155-199
    • Jacobson, D.1
  • 11
    • 84861979919 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course, Hume also recognizes a use of "prejudice" possessing a strictly negative connotation. In the Treatise, for example, Hume refers to prejudice properly so-called. If our experience is not sufficiently broad, or we have mistaken an isolated relation of coincidence (e.g., "This Irishman is witless") for causality ("Irish origin causes witlessness"), our mistaken causal reasoning generates prejudiced beliefs, such as the belief that an Irishman cannot have wit. See A Treatise of Human Nature, p. 146.
    • A Treatise of Human Nature , pp. 146
  • 12
    • 61049538127 scopus 로고
    • Hume's Standard of Taste: Breaking the Circle
    • See, for example, Peter Kivy, "Hume's Standard of Taste: Breaking the Circle," The British Journal of Aesthetics 7 (1967): 62-63,
    • (1967) The British Journal of Aesthetics , vol.7 , pp. 62-63
    • Kivy, P.1
  • 13
    • 80054302071 scopus 로고
    • New York: Burt Franklin & Co
    • and The Seventh Sense (New York: Burt Franklin & Co., 1976), pp. 146-147.
    • (1976) The Seventh Sense , pp. 146-147
  • 14
    • 80054296922 scopus 로고
    • I believe this is a misreading of Hume. Kivy offers a reading more sensitive to the contextualist element in Hume's essay in Hume's Neighbor's Wife: An Essay on the Evolution of Hume's Aesthetics
    • I believe this is a misreading of Hume. Kivy offers a reading more sensitive to the contextualist element in Hume's essay in "Hume's Neighbor's Wife: An Essay on the Evolution of Hume's Aesthetics," The British Journal of Aesthetics 23 (1983): 206-207.
    • (1983) The British Journal of Aesthetics , vol.23 , pp. 206-207
  • 15
    • 84971148032 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The passages in question specify that a critic ought "allow nothing to enter into his consideration, but the very object which is submitted to his examination," and that "when any work is addressed to the public, though I should have a friendship or enmity with the author, I must depart from this situation; and considering myself as a man in general, forget, if possible, my individual being and my peculiar circumstances." See "Of the Standard of Taste," pp. 239-240.
    • Of the Standard of Taste , pp. 239-240
  • 16
    • 61049248270 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • especially the section headed Moral Sensitivity: Delicacy or Prejudice?
    • Daniel Jacobson is one recent critic who appears ready to saddle Hume with some such dilemma. See Jacobson, "In Praise of Immoral Art," especially the section headed "Moral Sensitivity: Delicacy or Prejudice?"
    • In Praise of Immoral Art
    • Jacobson1
  • 17
    • 62249086861 scopus 로고
    • The Pennsylvania State University Press p. 71
    • On a reading offered by Stephen Darwall, for example, Hume's moral judge remains a spectator whose "(pleasurable) approbation is not an intrinsic response to contemplating the [character] trait [being assessed], but a response generated by sympathy with other pleasurable states she or he believes likely to be caused or realized by it" in those who may actually encounter the person with the trait. For Darwall's interpretation of the moral case, see "Hume and the Invention of Utilitarian in Hume and Hume's Connections, ed. M. A. Stewart and John P. Wright (The Pennsylvania State University Press, 1995), pp. 58-82, p. 71. In contrast, I suggest in what follows that Hume's true aesthetic judges imaginatively adopt a point of view that enables them to experience the same type of intrinsic response to a work of art as that which would be experienced by its intended audience.
    • (1995) Hume and the Invention of Utilitarian in Hume and Hume's Connections , pp. 58-82
    • Stewart, M.A.1    Wright, J.P.2
  • 18
    • 84974232187 scopus 로고
    • Hume and the Invention of Utilitarianism," and Geoffrey Sayre-McCord, "On Why Hume's 'General Point of View' Isn't Ideal - And Shouldn't Be
    • See, for example, Darwall, "Hume and the Invention of Utilitarianism," and Geoffrey Sayre-McCord, "On Why Hume's 'General Point of View' Isn't Ideal - And Shouldn't Be," Social Philosophy and Policy 11 (1994): 202-228.
    • (1994) Social Philosophy and Policy , vol.11 , pp. 202-228
    • Darwall1
  • 19
    • 33644674845 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hume on Cultural Conflicts of Value
    • For a discussion of relativism in the context of Hume's ethics, see Kate Abramson, "Hume on Cultural Conflicts of Value," Philosophical Studies 94 (1999): 173-187.
    • (1999) Philosophical Studies , vol.94 , pp. 173-187
    • Abramson, K.1
  • 20
    • 79957173039 scopus 로고
    • "On Why Hume's 'General Point of View' Isn't Ideal - And Shouldn't Be," and Elizabeth Radcliffe, "Hume on Motivating Sentiments, the General Point of View and the Inculcation of Morality"
    • I would want to develop this reading in such a way that it could allow for a gap between occurrent sentiments and judgments in particular cases while maintaining that true judges ideally judge a work beautiful in response to pleasurable feelings elicited in them by the work itself. For discussion of how the gap between occurrent sentiments and judgments is treated in the moral case, see Geoffrey Sayre-McCord, "On Why Hume's 'General Point of View' Isn't Ideal - And Shouldn't Be," and Elizabeth Radcliffe, "Hume on Motivating Sentiments, the General Point of View and the Inculcation of Morality," Hume Studies 20 (1994): 37-58. Note, however, that if my reading of Hume's aesthetic point of view is correct, Sayre-McCord is too quick in claiming, "The general point of view, as it describes a standard of taste in morals, parallels to an extraordinary degree the point of view of a qualified critic" (p. 220). Rather than attempting to assimilate Hume's aesthetic and moral points of view, I believe that we do well to attend to their differences and, most importantly, to subject to greater philosophical scrutiny the very idea of a "point of view."
    • (1994) Hume Studies , vol.20 , pp. 37-58
    • Sayre-McCord, G.1
  • 21
    • 0003523972 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Blackwell Publishers
    • If simulation theories of the mind are correct, however, this imaginative feat is not in fact so difficult; rather, we engage in it all the time. For a discussion of such simulation theories, see Martin Davies and Tony Stone, eds., Mental Simulation: Evaluations and Applications (Cambridge: Blackwell Publishers, 1995).
    • (1995) Mental Simulation: Evaluations and Applications
    • Davies, T.1    Stone, M.2
  • 23
    • 80054291067 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Criticisms such as Carroll's in fact dogged the essay from the start. For example, Peter Kivy reports that shortly after its publication, an anonymous reviewer wrote: "Instead of fixing and ascertaining the standard of taste, as we expected, our author only leaves us in the same uncertainty as he found us: and concludes with the philosophers of old, that all we know is, that we know nothing." See Peter Kivy, The Seventh Sense, p. 149. In response to a version of this paper read at the 1998 annual meeting of the American Society for Aesthetics, Carroll noted that he no longer endorses his earlier reading of Hume. To the best of my knowledge, none of Carroll's later published writings provides an answer to the problem I pursue here.
    • The Seventh Sense , pp. 149
    • Kivy, P.1
  • 24
    • 84857606531 scopus 로고
    • Hume and the Standard of Taste
    • Christopher MacLachlan, "Hume and the Standard of Taste," Hume Studies 12 (1986): 31.
    • (1986) Hume Studies , vol.12 , pp. 31
    • MacLachlan, C.1
  • 25
    • 79954299843 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Temple University Press
    • George Dickie, too, initially is ready to ascribe a form of relativism to Hume. Commenting on the "But notwithstanding ..." passage, he writes: "Through the bulk of his essay Hume combats relativism on the cognitive front, but at the end of the essay, when he turns his attention to affective matters, he quickly gives in to relativism. Why does Hume capitulate and should he?" Dickie, Evaluating Art (Temple University Press, 1988), p. 147.
    • (1988) Evaluating Art , pp. 147
    • Dickie1
  • 26
    • 80054239282 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • Hume's attempt to avoid relativist conclusions in other writings, particularly in A Dialogue and in his correspondence, makes this clear. See, for example, Hume's letter of March 1753 to James Balfour. There, Hume chides Balfour for attributing to him the skeptical views of Palamedes (who argues that moral determinations depend not on human nature but on "fashion, vogue, custom, and law") in A Dialogue: "I must only complain of you a little for ascribing to me the sentiments which I have put into the mouth of the Sceptic in the Dialogue. I have surely endeavored to refute the Sceptic with all the force of which I am master; and my refutation must be allowed sincere, because drawn from the capital principles of my system." The Letters of David Hume, vol. 1, ed. J. Y. T. Greig (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1969), p. 173.
    • (1969) The Letters of David Hume , vol.1 , pp. 173
    • Greig, J.Y.T.1
  • 27
    • 80054239316 scopus 로고
    • Fate Norton (New York: Cambridge University Press)
    • By a categorical judgment I simply mean a judgment that places a work in one of two categories: beautiful/good of its kind or ugly/bad of its kind. Peter Jones likewise interprets the distinctions Hume here mentions as "residual variations within otherwise agreed judgments," and George Dickie similarly regards them as impacting only rankings of the value of different positive aesthetic properties. See Peter Jones, "Hume's Literary and Aesthetic Theory," The Cambridge Companion to Hume, ed. Fate Norton (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1993), p. 273,
    • (1993) Hume's Literary and Aesthetic Theory, The Cambridge Companion to Hume , pp. 273
    • Jones, P.1
  • 29
    • 77951848621 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Consistency in One's Personal Aesthetics
    • Ted Cohen has suggested that analyzing "It's good but I don't like it" is reminiscent of working on Moore's paradox. See Ted Cohen, "On Consistency in One's Personal Aesthetics," in Aesthetics and Ethics: Essays at the Intersection.
    • Aesthetics and Ethics: Essays at the Intersection
    • Cohen, T.1
  • 31
    • 80054239455 scopus 로고
    • University of California Press
    • Leni Riefenstahl's Triumph of the Will is a somewhat hackneyed example of a work whose moral deficiencies constitute aesthetic flaws, according to moralist aestheticians. Here, I offer the example of a work that has for a long time occupied my own thoughts about the relevance of moral considerations to aesthetic assessment. Some people, no doubt, will think I have misread Chaplin. Those who do will find an able ally in Andre Bazin, "The Myth of Monsieur Verdoux," in his What Is Cinema? vol. 2 (University of California Press, 1971),pp. 102-123.
    • (1971) The Myth of Monsieur Verdoux, in his What Is Cinema? , vol.2 , pp. 102-123


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.