메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 96, Issue 5, 2008, Pages 1775-1806

How self-restriction laws can influence societal norms and address problems of bounded rationality

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 47849130512     PISSN: 00168092     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (3)

References (172)
  • 1
    • 6944253570 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See John A. Robertson, Paying the Alligator: Precommitment in Law, Bioethics, and Constitutions, 81 TEX. L. REV. 1729, 1730 (2003) (citing Jon Elster's definition of precommitments as strategies that people use 'to protect themselves against passion, preference change, and ... time inconsistency. They do so by removing certain options from the feasible set, by making them more costly or available only with a delay, and by insulating themselves from knowledge about their existence.').
    • See John A. Robertson, "Paying the Alligator": Precommitment in Law, Bioethics, and Constitutions, 81 TEX. L. REV. 1729, 1730 (2003) (citing Jon Elster's definition of precommitments as "strategies that people use 'to protect themselves against passion, preference change, and ... time inconsistency. They do so by removing certain options from the feasible set, by making them more costly or available only with a delay, and by insulating themselves from knowledge about their existence.'").
  • 2
    • 47849129910 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See SENECA, On Anger, in MORAL AND POLITICAL ESSAYS 17, 62 (John M. Cooper & XF. Procopé eds. & trans., Cambridge Univ. Press 1995) (noting that Julius Caesar would burn sympathetic letters written to his vanquished foe, rather than read them and become angry at the letter-writers: Although his anger was normally moderate, he preferred to avoid the very possibility of it, believing ignorance of a person's misdeeds to be the most gracious form of pardon.);
    • See SENECA, On Anger, in MORAL AND POLITICAL ESSAYS 17, 62 (John M. Cooper & XF. Procopé eds. & trans., Cambridge Univ. Press 1995) (noting that Julius Caesar would burn sympathetic letters written to his vanquished foe, rather than read them and become angry at the letter-writers: "Although his anger was normally moderate, he preferred to avoid the very possibility of it, believing ignorance of a person's misdeeds to be the most gracious form of pardon.");
  • 3
    • 0042244188 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Don't Burn Your Bridge Before You Come to It: Some Ambiguities and Complexities of Precommitment, 81
    • citing same
    • Jon Elster, Don't Burn Your Bridge Before You Come to It: Some Ambiguities and Complexities of Precommitment, 81 TEX. L. REV. 1751, 1752 (2003) (citing same).
    • (2003) TEX. L. REV , vol.1751 , pp. 1752
    • Elster, J.1
  • 4
    • 47849110740 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See HOMER, THE ODYSSEY 276 (Robert Fagles trans., Penguin Books 1996) (I told my shipmates, ... 'I alone was to hear [the Sirens'] voices,... / but you must bind me with tight chafing ropes / so I cannot move a muscle, bound to the spot, / erect at the mast-block, lashed by ropes to the mast. / And if I plead commanding you to set me free, / then lash me faster, rope on pressing rope.').
    • See HOMER, THE ODYSSEY 276 (Robert Fagles trans., Penguin Books 1996) ("I told my shipmates, ... 'I alone was to hear [the Sirens'] voices,... / but you must bind me with tight chafing ropes / so I cannot move a muscle, bound to the spot, / erect at the mast-block, lashed by ropes to the mast. / And if I plead commanding you to set me free, / then lash me faster, rope on pressing rope.'").
  • 5
    • 47849119915 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Because of the fame of this classic example, self-restriction laws are sometimes referred to as Ulysses laws. See, e.g., JON ELSTER, ULYSSES AND THE SIRENS: STUDIES IN RATIONALITY AND IRRATIONALITY (rev. ed. 1984).
    • Because of the fame of this classic example, self-restriction laws are sometimes referred to as Ulysses laws. See, e.g., JON ELSTER, ULYSSES AND THE SIRENS: STUDIES IN RATIONALITY AND IRRATIONALITY (rev. ed. 1984).
  • 6
    • 47849097869 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I use public law here to include family law and tax law-in short, anything that was promulgated by the legislature and is of general applicability
    • I use public law here to include family law and tax law-in short, anything that was promulgated by the legislature and is of general applicability.
  • 7
    • 47849087039 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003) (striking down Texas anti-sodomy statute as unconstitutional).
    • See Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003) (striking down Texas anti-sodomy statute as unconstitutional).
  • 8
    • 47849112232 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 599 (Scalia, J., dissenting) (This [decision] effectively decrees the end of all morals legislation.).
    • See id. at 599 (Scalia, J., dissenting) ("This [decision] effectively decrees the end of all morals legislation.").
  • 9
    • 0742306363 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Libertarian Paternalism Is Not an Oxymoron, 70
    • See
    • See Cass R. Sunstein & Richard H. Thaler, Libertarian Paternalism Is Not an Oxymoron, 70 U. CHI. L. REV. 1159 (2003);
    • (2003) U. CHI. L. REV , vol.1159
    • Sunstein, C.R.1    Thaler, R.H.2
  • 10
    • 23844457021 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Libertarian Paternalism Is an Oxymoron, 99
    • see also
    • see also Gregory Mitchell, Libertarian Paternalism Is an Oxymoron, 99 NW. U. L. REV. 1245 (2005).
    • (2005) NW. U. L. REV , vol.1245
    • Mitchell, G.1
  • 11
    • 0038548458 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Regulation for Conservatives: Behavioral Economics and the Case for "Asymmetric Paternalism," 151
    • See
    • See Colin Camerer et al., Regulation for Conservatives: Behavioral Economics and the Case for "Asymmetric Paternalism," 151 U. PA. L. REV. 1211 (2003).
    • (2003) U. PA. L. REV , vol.1211
    • Camerer, C.1
  • 12
  • 13
    • 0345984164 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Inverted Hierarchy of Contract Interpretation and Supplementation,97
    • Eyal Zamir, The Inverted Hierarchy of Contract Interpretation and Supplementation,97 COLUM. L. REV. 1710, 1785-86 (1997).
    • (1997) COLUM. L. REV , vol.1710 , pp. 1785-1786
    • Zamir, E.1
  • 14
    • 47849109948 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It admittedly seems paradoxical to say that behavior could be self-regarding and costly to society. Here, I am thinking of activities like drinking, drug use, or gambling. They are self-regarding in the sense that the activities themselves do not have any direct effect on another person. But they are also potentially costly to society because the activities, if done compulsively, can directly precipitate other, non-self-regarding behavior, like theft, violent crime, and an increased rate of hospitalization.
    • It admittedly seems paradoxical to say that behavior could be self-regarding and costly to society. Here, I am thinking of activities like drinking, drug use, or gambling. They are self-regarding in the sense that the activities themselves do not have any direct effect on another person. But they are also potentially costly to society because the activities, if done compulsively, can directly precipitate other, non-self-regarding behavior, like theft, violent crime, and an increased rate of hospitalization.
  • 15
    • 47849115501 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bounded rationality, a term from behavioral economics, refers to limitations on knowledge and self-control that cause an otherwise rational person to behave contrary to his own self-interests. See generally HERBERT A. SIMON, MODELS OF BOUNDED RATIONALITY (1982). In the context of compulsive behavior, for example, a boundedly rational person might generally act in accordance with predictive models of rational self-interest but behave irrationally where his compulsions are implicated.
    • Bounded rationality, a term from behavioral economics, refers to limitations on knowledge and self-control that cause an otherwise rational person to behave contrary to his own self-interests. See generally HERBERT A. SIMON, MODELS OF BOUNDED RATIONALITY (1982). In the context of compulsive behavior, for example, a boundedly rational person might generally act in accordance with predictive models of rational self-interest but behave irrationally where his compulsions are implicated.
  • 16
    • 47849090345 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Problem and Pathological Gambling, ch
    • available at
    • See Problem and Pathological Gambling, ch. 4 of NAT'L GAMBLING IMPACT STUDY COMM'N REPORT (1999), available at http://govinfo.library.unt.edu/ ngisc/reports/fullrpt.html
    • (1999) 4 of NAT'L GAMBLING IMPACT STUDY COMM'N REPORT
  • 17
    • 47849127006 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (citing a 1997 Harvard Medical School study estimating 15.4 million problem or pathological gamblers in the U.S).
    • (citing a 1997 Harvard Medical School study estimating 15.4 million problem or pathological gamblers in the U.S).
  • 18
    • 47849100286 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Bradley S. Fiorito, Comment, Calling a Lemon a Lemon: Regulating Electronic Gambling Machines to Contain Pathological Gambling, 100 NW. U. L. REV. 1325, 1337-38 & n.92 (2006)
    • See Bradley S. Fiorito, Comment, Calling a Lemon a Lemon: Regulating Electronic Gambling Machines to Contain Pathological Gambling, 100 NW. U. L. REV. 1325, 1337-38 & n.92 (2006)
  • 19
    • 47849090606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (citing AM. PSYCHIATRIC ASS'N, DIAGNOSTIC AND STATISTICAL MANUAL OF MENTAL DISORDERS 674 (4th ed., text rev. 2000)).
    • (citing AM. PSYCHIATRIC ASS'N, DIAGNOSTIC AND STATISTICAL MANUAL OF MENTAL DISORDERS 674 (4th ed., text rev. 2000)).
  • 20
    • 47849115248 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 1328-29.
    • See id. at 1328-29.
  • 21
    • 47849110737 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MO. CODE REGS. ANN. tit. 11, § 45-17.010 (2001).
    • MO. CODE REGS. ANN. tit. 11, § 45-17.010 (2001).
  • 22
    • 47849127789 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Carol O'Hare, Self-Exclusion-Concept vs. Reality, 8 GAMING L. REV. 189, 189 (2004) (quoting Kevin Mullally, executive director of the Missouri Gaming Commission).
    • See Carol O'Hare, Self-Exclusion-Concept vs. Reality, 8 GAMING L. REV. 189, 189 (2004) (quoting Kevin Mullally, executive director of the Missouri Gaming Commission).
  • 23
    • 47849107711 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The acclaim has not been universal, though. See, e.g., id. (criticizing casino self-exclusion laws for being an ineffective way to combat compulsive gambling and for potentially exposing casinos to liability arising from failure to keep out all self-excluders).
    • The acclaim has not been universal, though. See, e.g., id. (criticizing casino self-exclusion laws for being an ineffective way to combat compulsive gambling and for potentially exposing casinos to liability arising from failure to keep out all self-excluders).
  • 24
    • 47849114457 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See CAL. CODE REGS. tit. 4, § 12464 (2007);
    • See CAL. CODE REGS. tit. 4, § 12464 (2007);
  • 25
    • 47849085478 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • § 3000.745
    • ILL. ADMIN. CODE tit. 86, § 3000.745 (2007);
    • (2007) CODE tit , vol.86
    • ADMIN, I.1
  • 26
    • 47849094484 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • IND. ADMIN. CODE 6-3-1 (2004);
    • IND. ADMIN. CODE 6-3-1 (2004);
  • 27
    • 47849098638 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • § 304
    • LA. ADMIN. CODE tit. 42, § 304 (2007);
    • (2007) CODE tit , vol.42
    • ADMIN, L.1
  • 28
    • 47849116277 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MICH. COMP. LAWS ANN. § 432.225 (West 2001);
    • MICH. COMP. LAWS ANN. § 432.225 (West 2001);
  • 29
    • 47849090346 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MISS. GAMING COMM'N REGS., § III(J) (2007);
    • MISS. GAMING COMM'N REGS., § III(J) (2007);
  • 30
    • 47849106935 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NJ. ADMIN. CODE § 19:48-2.1 to -2.5 (2000 & Supp. 2004);
    • NJ. ADMIN. CODE § 19:48-2.1 to -2.5 (2000 & Supp. 2004);
  • 31
    • 47849123607 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • N.Y COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 21, § 2836-19.6(e) (2007);
    • N.Y COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 21, § 2836-19.6(e) (2007);
  • 32
    • 47849102852 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • PA. CODE § 503.3 (2007);
    • PA. CODE § 503.3 (2007);
  • 33
    • 47849123361 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • R.I. GEN. LAWS § 41-9.1-25(c) (2006).
    • R.I. GEN. LAWS § 41-9.1-25(c) (2006).
  • 34
    • 47849126516 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Andy Rhea, Voluntary Self-Exclusion Lists: How They Work and Potential Problems, 9 GAMING L. REV. 462,463-67 (2005).
    • See Andy Rhea, Voluntary Self-Exclusion Lists: How They Work and Potential Problems, 9 GAMING L. REV. 462,463-67 (2005).
  • 35
    • 47849099975 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See CAL. CODE REGS. tit. 4, § 12464 (2007);
    • See CAL. CODE REGS. tit. 4, § 12464 (2007);
  • 36
    • 47849100568 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • III. ADMIN. CODE tit. 86, § 3000.755 (2007);
    • III. ADMIN. CODE tit. 86, § 3000.755 (2007);
  • 37
    • 47849132601 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • IND. ADMIN. CODE 6-3-2 (2004);
    • IND. ADMIN. CODE 6-3-2 (2004);
  • 38
    • 47849124981 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • CODE tit
    • LA. ADMIN. CODE tit. 42, § 304(C) (2007);
    • (2007) § 304(C) , vol.42
    • ADMIN, L.1
  • 39
    • 47849127790 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MICH. COMP. LAWS ANN. § 432.225(4) (West 2007);
    • MICH. COMP. LAWS ANN. § 432.225(4) (West 2007);
  • 40
    • 47849107447 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MISS. GAMING COMM'N REGS., § III(J) (2007);
    • MISS. GAMING COMM'N REGS., § III(J) (2007);
  • 41
    • 47849099976 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NJ. ADMIN. CODE § 19:48-2.2 (2000 & Supp. 2004);
    • NJ. ADMIN. CODE § 19:48-2.2 (2000 & Supp. 2004);
  • 42
    • 47849133353 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • N. Y. COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 21, § 2836-19.6(e) (2007);
    • N. Y. COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 21, § 2836-19.6(e) (2007);
  • 43
    • 47849094209 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • PA. CODE § 503.3 (2007);
    • PA. CODE § 503.3 (2007);
  • 44
    • 47849111409 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • R.I. GEN. LAWS § 41-9.1-25(c) (2006).
    • R.I. GEN. LAWS § 41-9.1-25(c) (2006).
  • 45
    • 47849118332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See MO. CODE REGS. ANN. tit. 11, § 45-17.020(1)(A) (2001) (The applicant agrees that placement on the list is for life and the commission is not authorized to remove a person from the list).
    • See MO. CODE REGS. ANN. tit. 11, § 45-17.020(1)(A) (2001) ("The applicant agrees that placement on the list is for life and the commission is not authorized to remove a person from the list").
  • 46
    • 47849102856 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., III. ADMIN. CODE tit. 86, § 3000.780(a) (2007) (Upon the expiration of 5 years from the date of placement on the Self-Exclusion List, any person who has been placed on the Self-Exclusion List may request the Administrator to remove his or her name from the Self-Exclusion List).
    • See, e.g., III. ADMIN. CODE tit. 86, § 3000.780(a) (2007) ("Upon the expiration of 5 years from the date of placement on the Self-Exclusion List, any person who has been placed on the Self-Exclusion List may request the Administrator to remove his or her name from the Self-Exclusion List").
  • 47
    • 47849112997 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See MISS. GAMING COMM'N REGS., § DI(J)(5)(a) (2007). In Mississippi, though, the minimum term a self-excluder can specify is five years.
    • See MISS. GAMING COMM'N REGS., § DI(J)(5)(a) (2007). In Mississippi, though, the minimum term a self-excluder can specify is five years.
  • 49
    • 47849130987 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Rhea, supra note 19, at 462-63 (mentioning cases that have come to divergent conclusions on the issue).
    • See, e.g., Rhea, supra note 19, at 462-63 (mentioning cases that have come to divergent conclusions on the issue).
  • 50
    • 47849089345 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., MO. CODE REGS. ANN. tit. 11, § 45-17.020(1)(A) (2001) ([T]he person understands ... that s/he may be arrested for trespassing if discovered on an excursion gambting boat... [and that] all chips, tokens and electronic credits in his/her possession at the time of the discovery will be forfeited.).
    • See, e.g., MO. CODE REGS. ANN. tit. 11, § 45-17.020(1)(A) (2001) ("[T]he person understands ... that s/he may be arrested for trespassing if discovered on an excursion gambting boat... [and that] all chips, tokens and electronic credits in his/her possession at the time of the discovery will be forfeited.").
  • 51
    • 47849111988 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For more on this subject, see Rhea, supra note 19
    • For more on this subject, see Rhea, supra note 19.
  • 52
    • 47849104839 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sunstein & Thaler, supra note 7, at 1201
    • Sunstein & Thaler, supra note 7, at 1201.
  • 53
    • 47849099444 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 1172-73.
    • See id. at 1172-73.
  • 54
    • 47849124161 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id
    • See id.
  • 55
    • 47849090348 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Fiorito, supra note 13, at 1356 (Sunstein and Thaler do not discuss gambling in their article, but their theory is directly applicable to the gambling milieu.);
    • See Fiorito, supra note 13, at 1356 ("Sunstein and Thaler do not discuss gambling in their article, but their theory is directly applicable to the gambling milieu.");
  • 56
    • 47849089841 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Avuncular State-The New Paternalism, ECONOMIST, Apr. 6, 2006 (discussing casino self-exclusion laws in the context of libertarian paternalism).
    • The Avuncular State-The New Paternalism, ECONOMIST, Apr. 6, 2006 (discussing casino self-exclusion laws in the context of libertarian paternalism).
  • 57
    • 47849128297 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Another way to approach this question would be to ask if the laws are sufficiently libertarian. Only a few states with casino self-exclusion laws permit the individual to remove himself from the list once he is on it, and those that do might make removal virtually impossible by, for example, imposing waiting periods of multiple years. But [t]he libertarian paternatist insists on preserving choice. Sunstein & Thaler, supra note 7, at 1185. Therefore, even those states that create some mechanism for getting off the lists might be insufficiently libertarian: on the continuum between freedom of choice and coercion, a law that imposes very high costs on removing oneself from the list might preserve freedom of choice in a technical sense, even as it drastically inhibits the choices that are practically available to a person
    • Another way to approach this question would be to ask if the laws are sufficiently libertarian. Only a few states with casino self-exclusion laws permit the individual to remove himself from the list once he is on it, and those that do might make removal virtually impossible by, for example, imposing waiting periods of multiple years. But "[t]he libertarian paternatist insists on preserving choice." Sunstein & Thaler, supra note 7, at 1185. Therefore, even those states that create some mechanism for getting off the lists might be insufficiently libertarian: on the continuum between freedom of choice and coercion, a law that imposes very high costs on removing oneself from the list might preserve freedom of choice in a technical sense, even as it drastically inhibits the choices that are practically available to a person.
  • 58
    • 47849091349 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Gerald Dworkin, Paternalism, in MILL'S ON LIBERTT. CRITICAL ESSAYS 61, 62 (Gerald Dworkin ed., 1997) (By paternalism I shall understand roughly the interference with a person's liberty of action justified by reasons referring exclusively to the welfare, good, happiness, needs, interests or values of the person being coerced.).
    • See Gerald Dworkin, Paternalism, in MILL'S ON LIBERTT. CRITICAL ESSAYS 61, 62 (Gerald Dworkin ed., 1997) ("By paternalism I shall understand roughly the interference with a person's liberty of action justified by reasons referring exclusively to the welfare, good, happiness, needs, interests or values of the person being coerced.").
  • 59
    • 0345910646 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Bernard E. Harcourt, The Collapse of the Harm Principle, 90 J. CRIM. L. & CRIMINOLOGY 109, 113 (1999) (The harm principle is effectively collapsing under the weight of its own success. Claims of harm have become so pervasive that the harm principle has become meaningless: the harm principle no longer serves the function of a critical principle because non-trivial harm arguments permeate the debate.).
    • See Bernard E. Harcourt, The Collapse of the Harm Principle, 90 J. CRIM. L. & CRIMINOLOGY 109, 113 (1999) ("The harm principle is effectively collapsing under the weight of its own success. Claims of harm have become so pervasive that the harm principle has become meaningless: the harm principle no longer serves the function of a critical principle because non-trivial harm arguments permeate the debate.").
  • 60
    • 47849096292 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See 3 JOEL FEINBERG, THE MORAL LIMITS OF THE CRIMINAL LAW: HARM TO SELF 84 (1986) ([W]hen an earlier self voluntarily agrees or resolves that his later self do something and that the agreement be irrevocable, and his later self, equally voluntarily, wishes to revoke the earlier agreement, the case is not always to be treated as one sovereign person 'changing his mind' later, but at least sometimes as a close conflict between two equally sovereign persons.).
    • See 3 JOEL FEINBERG, THE MORAL LIMITS OF THE CRIMINAL LAW: HARM TO SELF 84 (1986) ("[W]hen an earlier self voluntarily agrees or resolves that his later self do something and that the agreement be irrevocable, and his later self, equally voluntarily, wishes to revoke the earlier agreement, the case is not always to be treated as one sovereign person 'changing his mind' later, but at least sometimes as a close conflict between two equally sovereign persons.").
  • 61
    • 47849120580 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some people might argue that this complexity demonstrates that the state should not be in the business of evaluating which of two conflicting statements of personal preferences is the true one. But, as discussed infra, the state can make such decisions in a nonpaternalistic way by following either or both of two established methodologies for distinguishing between two conflicting statements of preference
    • Some people might argue that this complexity demonstrates that the state should not be in the business of evaluating which of two conflicting statements of personal preferences is the true one. But, as discussed infra, the state can make such decisions in a nonpaternalistic way by following either or both of two established methodologies for distinguishing between two conflicting statements of preference.
  • 62
    • 44949090968 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See note 34, at, positing a similar hypothetical situation, For another similar example
    • See FETNBERG, supra note 34, at 82 (positing a similar hypothetical situation). For another similar example,
    • supra , pp. 82
    • FETNBERG1
  • 63
    • 47849122885 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see id. (Suppose, for example, that I ask a friend to wake me at five in the morning and urge him to pay no heed to my future self's protests at that hour. When five o'clock comes along, and wakened from a sound sleep I announce a change of mind, the friend is entitled to give greater weight to the clearheaded, deliberate resolution of the earlier self, than to the incoherent, sleepy mumblings of the later one.).
    • see id. ("Suppose, for example, that I ask a friend to wake me at five in the morning and urge him to pay no heed to my future self's protests at that hour. When five o'clock comes along, and wakened from a sound sleep I announce a change of mind, the friend is entitled to give greater weight to the clearheaded, deliberate resolution of the earlier self, than to the incoherent, sleepy mumblings of the later one.").
  • 64
    • 47849118874 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra section I.C.1.a.
    • See infra section I.C.1.a.
  • 65
    • 47849099707 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra section I.C.1.b.
    • See infra section I.C.1.b.
  • 66
    • 47849116279 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • JOHN STUART MILL, ON LIBERTY 101 (Elizabeth Rapaport ed., Hackett Pub. Co., Inc. 1978) (1859).
    • JOHN STUART MILL, ON LIBERTY 101 (Elizabeth Rapaport ed., Hackett Pub. Co., Inc. 1978) (1859).
  • 67
    • 47849118329 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See FEINBERG, supra note 34, at 57 (A majority view, associated with the writings of Plato, Aristotle, Rousseau, Hegel, and Mill, among others, identifies a person's good ultimately with his self-fulfillment- a notion that is certainly not identical with that of autonomy or the right of self-determination.).
    • See FEINBERG, supra note 34, at 57 ("A majority view, associated with the writings of Plato, Aristotle, Rousseau, Hegel, and Mill, among others, identifies a person's good ultimately with his self-fulfillment- a notion that is certainly not identical with that of autonomy or the right of self-determination.").
  • 68
    • 47849131542 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 65
    • Id. at 65.
  • 69
    • 47849108372 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kurt Eggert, Lashed to the Mast and Crying for Help: How Self-Limitation of Autonomy Can Protect Elders from Predatory Lending, 36 LOY. L.A. L. REV. 693, 727 (2003).
    • Kurt Eggert, Lashed to the Mast and Crying for Help: How Self-Limitation of Autonomy Can Protect Elders from Predatory Lending, 36 LOY. L.A. L. REV. 693, 727 (2003).
  • 70
    • 47849090605 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 71
    • 47849126299 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 728 (citing Harry G. Frankfurt, Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person, 68 J. PHIL. 5, 11 (1971)).
    • Id. at 728 (citing Harry G. Frankfurt, Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person, 68 J. PHIL. 5, 11 (1971)).
  • 72
    • 47849123151 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 73
    • 47849129641 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • GERALD DWORKIN, THE THEORY AND PRACTICE OF AUTONOMY 20 (Sydney Shoemaker et al. eds., 1988);
    • GERALD DWORKIN, THE THEORY AND PRACTICE OF AUTONOMY 20 (Sydney Shoemaker et al. eds., 1988);
  • 74
    • 47849123882 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Eggert, supra note 42, at 729 n.155 (quoting same).
    • Eggert, supra note 42, at 729 n.155 (quoting same).
  • 75
    • 47849111698 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Eggert, supra note 42, at 726 n. 145.
    • Eggert, supra note 42, at 726 n. 145.
  • 76
    • 47849093969 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 738 (citations and quotations omitted).
    • Id. at 738 (citations and quotations omitted).
  • 77
    • 47849105875 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 741
    • Id. at 741.
  • 78
    • 47849122890 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 79
    • 47849119638 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 742
    • Id. at 742.
  • 80
    • 47849083663 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 739
    • Id. at 739.
  • 81
    • 33645786491 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wanting, Liking, and Learning: Neuroscience and Paternalism, 73
    • Colin F. Camerer, Wanting, Liking, and Learning: Neuroscience and Paternalism, 73 U. CHI. L. REV. 87, 87 (2006).
    • (2006) U. CHI. L. REV , vol.87 , pp. 87
    • Camerer, C.F.1
  • 82
    • 84888467546 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • notes 92-99 and accompanying text
    • See infra notes 92-99 and accompanying text.
    • See infra
  • 83
    • 47849101080 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Camerer et al, supra note 8, at 1219
    • Camerer et al., supra note 8, at 1219.
  • 84
    • 47849096805 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This suggestion need not conflict with the earlier one that self-restriction laws not be paternalistic. Although the state should not try to determine what is in an individual's best interests, it should consider how self-restriction laws will affect society in general
    • This suggestion need not conflict with the earlier one that self-restriction laws not be paternalistic. Although the state should not try to determine what is in an individual's best interests, it should consider how self-restriction laws will affect society in general.
  • 85
    • 47849108891 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mitchell, supra note 7, at 1275
    • Mitchell, supra note 7, at 1275.
  • 86
    • 47849112998 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Katherine Shaw Späht, Louisiana's Covenant Marriage: Social Analysis and Legal Implications, 59 LA. L. REV. 63, 74 (1998) (emphasis added).
    • Katherine Shaw Späht, Louisiana's Covenant Marriage: Social Analysis and Legal Implications, 59 LA. L. REV. 63, 74 (1998) (emphasis added).
  • 87
    • 0348199090 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the Expressive Function of Law, 144
    • See
    • See Cass R. Sunstein, On the Expressive Function of Law, 144 U. PA. L. REV. 2021, 2025 (1996).
    • (1996) U. PA. L. REV. 2021 , pp. 2025
    • Sunstein, C.R.1
  • 88
    • 47849105602 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id
    • See id.
  • 89
    • 47849102327 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 2026
    • Id. at 2026.
  • 90
    • 47849126765 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 91
    • 47849092978 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 2027.
    • See id. at 2027.
  • 92
    • 47849131543 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 2049.
    • See id. at 2049.
  • 93
    • 47849089098 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 2032.
    • See id. at 2032.
  • 94
    • 47849088319 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 2031
    • Id. at 2031.
  • 95
    • 47849089577 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 2032
    • Id. at 2032.
  • 96
    • 47849099708 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at
    • Id. at 2050-51.
  • 97
    • 47849107196 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 2033
    • Id. at 2033.
  • 98
    • 47849102598 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id at 2045-46
    • Id at 2045-46.
  • 99
    • 47849130192 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See LA. REV. STAT. ANN. § 9:272 (2000 & Supp. 2007).
    • See LA. REV. STAT. ANN. § 9:272 (2000 & Supp. 2007).
  • 100
    • 32944468858 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Katherine Shaw Spaht, Covenant Marriage Seven Years Later: Its As Yet Unfulfilled Promise, 65 LA. L. REV. 605, 605 (2005).
    • Katherine Shaw Spaht, Covenant Marriage Seven Years Later: Its As Yet Unfulfilled Promise, 65 LA. L. REV. 605, 605 (2005).
  • 101
    • 47849107712 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See ARIZ. REV. STAT. ANN. §§ 25-901 to -906 (2007);
    • See ARIZ. REV. STAT. ANN. §§ 25-901 to -906 (2007);
  • 102
    • 47849113290 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ARK. CODE ANN. §§ 9-11-802 to -811 (2002 & Supp. 2007);
    • ARK. CODE ANN. §§ 9-11-802 to -811 (2002 & Supp. 2007);
  • 103
    • 47849085213 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also note 72, at, noting the adoption of the Arizona and Arkansas laws
    • see also Spaht, supra note 72, at 605 (noting the adoption of the Arizona and Arkansas laws).
    • supra , pp. 605
    • Spaht1
  • 104
    • 47849111129 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Katherine Shaw Spaht, Covenant Marriage: An Achievable Legal Response to the Inherent Nature of Marriage and Its Various Goods, 4 AVE MAMA L. REV. 467, 482, 485 (2006).
    • Katherine Shaw Spaht, Covenant Marriage: An Achievable Legal Response to the Inherent Nature of Marriage and Its Various Goods, 4 AVE MAMA L. REV. 467, 482, 485 (2006).
  • 105
    • 47849114689 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 469
    • Id. at 469.
  • 106
    • 47849112477 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 482
    • Id. at 482.
  • 107
    • 47849102855 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 484.
    • See id. at 484.
  • 108
    • 47849096042 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See David Crary, Bible Belt Is Also Divorce Belt, CHI. TRIB., NOV. 12, 1999, at 8.
    • See David Crary, Bible Belt Is Also Divorce Belt, CHI. TRIB., NOV. 12, 1999, at 8.
  • 109
    • 47849095271 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Spaht, supra note 74, at 473 citation and internal quotation marks omitted
    • Spaht, supra note 74, at 473 (citation and internal quotation marks omitted).
  • 110
    • 47849100572 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 474
    • Id. at 474.
  • 111
    • 47849119387 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Tony Perkins, Covenant Marriage: A Legislator's Perspective, 12 REGENT U. L. REV. 27, 28 (1999).
    • Tony Perkins, Covenant Marriage: A Legislator's Perspective, 12 REGENT U. L. REV. 27, 28 (1999).
  • 112
    • 47849121875 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Spaht, supra note 58, at 72
    • Spaht, supra note 58, at 72.
  • 113
    • 47849112999 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Spaht, supra note 74, at 495 (quoting John Witte, Jr. & Joel A. Nichols, Introduction to COVENANT MARRIAGE IN COMPARATIVE PERSPECTIVE 1, 24 (John Witte, Jr. & Eliza Ellison eds., 2005)).
    • Spaht, supra note 74, at 495 (quoting John Witte, Jr. & Joel A. Nichols, Introduction to COVENANT MARRIAGE IN COMPARATIVE PERSPECTIVE 1, 24 (John Witte, Jr. & Eliza Ellison eds., 2005)).
  • 114
    • 47849104840 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Perkins, supra note 81, at 29
    • Perkins, supra note 81, at 29.
  • 115
    • 47849126517 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 116
    • 47849113788 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Spaht, supra note 58, at 130
    • Spaht, supra note 58, at 130
  • 117
    • 0032700161 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Marriage and Trust: Some Lessons from Economics, 23
    • quoting
    • (quoting Robert Rowthorn, Marriage and Trust: Some Lessons from Economics, 23 CAMBRIDGE J. ECON. 661, 688 (1999)).
    • (1999) CAMBRIDGE J. ECON , vol.661 , pp. 688
    • Rowthorn, R.1
  • 118
    • 47849097585 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Spaht, supra note 74, at 489
    • See Spaht, supra note 74, at 489.
  • 119
    • 47849098901 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 489-91.
    • See id. at 489-91.
  • 121
    • 47849114194 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Spaht, supra note 72, at 628
    • Spaht, supra note 72, at 628.
  • 122
    • 47849126300 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Perkins, supra note 81, at 29
    • Perkins, supra note 81, at 29.
  • 123
    • 47849088071 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See U.S. DEP'T OF HEALTH & HUMAN SERVS., BINGE EATING DISORDER 1, 3 (2004), available at http://win.niddk.nih.gov/publications/PDFs/bingedis10.04.pdf (calling binge eating the most common eating disorder and listing type 2 diabetes, heart disease, cancer, and depression among associated complications);
    • See U.S. DEP'T OF HEALTH & HUMAN SERVS., BINGE EATING DISORDER 1, 3 (2004), available at http://win.niddk.nih.gov/publications/PDFs/bingedis10.04.pdf (calling binge eating "the most common eating disorder" and listing type 2 diabetes, heart disease, cancer, and depression among associated complications);
  • 124
    • 47849085967 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • U.S. DEP'T OF HEALTH & HUMAN SERVS., STATISTICS RELATED TO OVERWEIGHT AND OBESITY (2007), available at http://win.niddk.nih.gov/ publications/PDFs/stat904z.pdf (estimating the total direct and indirect costs of overweight and obesity in the United States at $177 billion).
    • U.S. DEP'T OF HEALTH & HUMAN SERVS., STATISTICS RELATED TO OVERWEIGHT AND OBESITY (2007), available at http://win.niddk.nih.gov/ publications/PDFs/stat904z.pdf (estimating the total direct and indirect costs of overweight and obesity in the United States at $177 billion).
  • 126
    • 47849087825 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See stickK FAQs, supra note 93
    • See stickK FAQs, supra note 93.
  • 127
    • 47849111991 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id
    • See id.
  • 128
    • 47849115251 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See sources cited supra note 93
    • See sources cited supra note 93.
  • 129
    • 47849090086 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See stickK FAQs, supra note 93
    • See stickK FAQs, supra note 93.
  • 130
    • 47849099446 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id
    • See id.
  • 131
    • 47849109418 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Tennessee recently became the first state to require identification checks of anyone buying alcohol, regardless of how obviously over twenty-one the purchaser appears. See Lucas L. Johnson II, Tennessee Requires Stores To Check ID Card of Anyone Buying Beer, WASH. POST, July 1, 2007, at A7. In such states, it would impose little or no marginal costs on society to check the identification for a mark that indicates a self-restriction on alcohol consumption
    • Tennessee recently became the first state to require identification checks of anyone buying alcohol, regardless of how obviously over twenty-one the purchaser appears. See Lucas L. Johnson II, Tennessee Requires Stores To Check ID Card of Anyone Buying Beer, WASH. POST, July 1, 2007, at A7. In such states, it would impose little or no marginal costs on society to check the identification for a mark that indicates a self-restriction on alcohol consumption.
  • 133
    • 84963425965 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 42, at, citing same
    • Eggert, supra note 42, at 753 (citing same).
    • supra , pp. 753
    • Eggert1
  • 134
    • 47849105335 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Convicted pedophiles have even requested a far more permanent form of self-restriction, castration. See After Castration, California Sex Offender Seeks Freedom, N. Y TIMES, July 4, 2006, at A12;
    • Convicted pedophiles have even requested a far more permanent form of self-restriction, castration. See After Castration, California Sex Offender Seeks Freedom, N. Y TIMES, July 4, 2006, at A12;
  • 135
    • 47849105873 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Texas Frees Child Molester Who Warns of New Crimes
    • Apr. 9, at
    • Sam Howe Verhovek, Texas Frees Child Molester Who Warns of New Crimes, N. Y. TIMES, Apr. 9, 1996, at B7.
    • (1996) N. Y. TIMES
    • Howe Verhovek, S.1
  • 136
    • 47849125245 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But see Pedophile Who Sought Castration Is Released, ABC NEWS, May 4, 2005, http://abcnews.go.com/GMA/LegalCenter/story?id:= 726907 (suggesting that ankle bracelets, which convicted pedophiles in Texas are forced to wear-and therefore are not examples of self-restriction laws because they do not involve voluntary restriction-are ineffective in preventing recidivism).
    • But see Pedophile Who Sought Castration Is Released, ABC NEWS, May 4, 2005, http://abcnews.go.com/GMA/LegalCenter/story?id:= 726907 (suggesting that ankle bracelets, which convicted pedophiles in Texas are forced to wear-and therefore are not examples of self-restriction laws because they do not involve voluntary restriction-are ineffective in preventing recidivism).
  • 137
    • 47849095541 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It might be worth noting that some of the potential self-restriction laws discussed below express their messages through the criminal law, specifically, by giving people the option to criminalize otherwise legal behavior, thereby conveying a message of the self-restricter's (and in many cases, the state's) disapproval of the behavior. Casino self-exclusion laws already operate through the criminal law. But there are not any extant examples of primarily expressive self-restriction laws that operate through the criminal law, and one possible objection to the proposals that follow is that the criminal law carries too much condemnatory force and potential for stigmatization for it to be properly used as a mechanism for expressing disapproval. Two responses come to mind. First, part of this concern can be mitigated through the choice of punishment for violating the self-restriction law. For example, if violating a self-restriction law results in a nominal fine, then it seems overly formali
    • It might be worth noting that some of the potential self-restriction laws discussed below express their messages through the criminal law - specifically, by giving people the option to criminalize otherwise legal behavior, thereby conveying a message of the self-restricter's (and in many cases, the state's) disapproval of the behavior. Casino self-exclusion laws already operate through the criminal law. But there are not any extant examples of primarily expressive self-restriction laws that operate through the criminal law, and one possible objection to the proposals that follow is that the criminal law carries too much condemnatory force and potential for stigmatization for it to be properly used as a mechanism for expressing disapproval. Two responses come to mind. First, part of this concern can be mitigated through the choice of punishment for violating the self-restriction law. For example, if violating a self-restriction law results in a nominal fine, then it seems overly formalistic to say that the involvement of the criminal law automatically makes it an inappropriately powerful tool for attempting to shape societal norms. Misdemeanors are crimes, too, but we do not normally think that misdemeanors strongly or oppressively inculcate values. Second, "[t]he criminal law has traditionally been seen as performing a moral educative function." See Dan M. Kahan, The Anatomy of Disgust in Criminal Law, 96 MICH. L. REV. 1621, 1653 (1998)
  • 138
    • 47849109685 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (reviewing WILLIAM IAN MILLER, THE ANATOMY OF DISGUST (1997)).
    • (reviewing WILLIAM IAN MILLER, THE ANATOMY OF DISGUST (1997)).
  • 139
    • 34047166967 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Under this view, it is normal and appropriate to use the criminal law to shape societal norms. But see Adil Ahmad Haque, Lawrence v. Texas and the Limits of the Criminal Law, 42 HARV. C.R.-C.L. L. REV. 1, 33-34 (2007) (arguing that Kahan's belief that the expression of social condemnation may be sufficient to justify punishment of individuals who display defective moral values ... is a minority view even among expressive theorists of the criminal law).
    • Under this view, it is normal and appropriate to use the criminal law to shape societal norms. But see Adil Ahmad Haque, Lawrence v. Texas and the Limits of the Criminal Law, 42 HARV. C.R.-C.L. L. REV. 1, 33-34 (2007) (arguing that Kahan's belief "that the expression of social condemnation may be sufficient to justify punishment of individuals who display defective moral values ... is a minority view even among expressive theorists of the criminal law").
  • 140
    • 47849099175 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kahan, supra note 103, at 1655
    • Kahan, supra note 103, at 1655.
  • 141
    • 84963456897 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • notes 62-63,90 and accompanying text
    • See supra notes 62-63,90 and accompanying text.
    • See supra
  • 142
    • 47849086740 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113, 164 (1973) (recognizing a woman's right to choose to obtain an abortion prior to fetal viability);
    • See Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113, 164 (1973) (recognizing a woman's right to choose to obtain an abortion prior to fetal viability);
  • 143
    • 47849083398 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Planned Parenthood of Se. Pa. v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 845-46 (1992) (reaffirming Roe v. Wade on stare decisis grounds).
    • see also Planned Parenthood of Se. Pa. v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 845-46 (1992) (reaffirming Roe v. Wade on stare decisis grounds).
  • 144
    • 37149042803 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Jessica Powley Hayden, Note, The Ties That Bind: The Constitution, Structural Restraints, and Government Actions Overseas, 96 GEO. L.J. 237, 243 & n.35 (2007) (noting that individual rights can be waived, but structural rights cannot).
    • See Jessica Powley Hayden, Note, The Ties That Bind: The Constitution, Structural Restraints, and Government Actions Overseas, 96 GEO. L.J. 237, 243 & n.35 (2007) (noting that individual rights can be waived, but structural rights cannot).
  • 145
    • 47849106420 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Perkins, supra note 81, at 28-29
    • Perkins, supra note 81, at 28-29.
  • 146
    • 47849128562 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kahan, supra note 103, at 1655
    • See Kahan, supra note 103, at 1655.
  • 147
    • 47849133046 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It might also make sense to create certain exceptions-such as in cases of rape-as the default rules and let people opt-out of those exceptions only if they manifest a considered preference to do so
    • It might also make sense to create certain exceptions-such as in cases of rape-as the default rules and let people opt-out of those exceptions only if they manifest a considered preference to do so.
  • 148
    • 47849124441 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003) (invalidating Texas statute criminalizing homosexual sodomy).
    • See Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003) (invalidating Texas statute criminalizing homosexual sodomy).
  • 149
    • 47849109419 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 577-78.
    • See id. at 577-78.
  • 150
    • 47849096043 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Mark Strasser, Monogamy, Licentiousness, Desuetude and Mere Tolerance: The Multiple Misinterpretations of Lawrence v. Texas, 15 S. CAL. REV. L. & WOMEN'S STUD. 95, 95 (2005) (describing various conflicting readings of Lawrence).
    • See, e.g., Mark Strasser, Monogamy, Licentiousness, Desuetude and Mere Tolerance: The Multiple Misinterpretations of Lawrence v. Texas, 15 S. CAL. REV. L. & WOMEN'S STUD. 95, 95 (2005) (describing various conflicting readings of Lawrence).
  • 151
    • 47849116833 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lawrence, 539 U.S. at 578 (emphasis added).
    • Lawrence, 539 U.S. at 578 (emphasis added).
  • 152
    • 47849084415 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 153
    • 47849089581 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 580 (O'Connor, J., concurring) (quoting Dep't of Agrie, v. Moreno, 413 U.S. 528, 534 (1973)) (alteration in original).
    • Id. at 580 (O'Connor, J., concurring) (quoting Dep't of Agrie, v. Moreno, 413 U.S. 528, 534 (1973)) (alteration in original).
  • 154
    • 47849122385 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 583 (citations and quotations omitted).
    • Id. at 583 (citations and quotations omitted).
  • 155
    • 2942605817 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jurisprudence of Tolerance: Judicial Review To Lower the Stakes of Identity Politics, 88
    • Perhaps signal[ing] the majority's preference for heterosexuality is subtly but crucially different from signaling the majority's disapproval of homosexuality, with the former constitutionally legitimate and the latter illegitimate. But that distinction seems more semantic than substantive. See
    • See William N. Eskridge, Jr., Lawrence's Jurisprudence of Tolerance: Judicial Review To Lower the Stakes of Identity Politics, 88 MINN. L. REV. 1021, 1025 (2004). Perhaps "signal[ing] the majority's preference for heterosexuality" is subtly but crucially different from signaling the majority's disapproval of homosexuality, with the former constitutionally legitimate and the latter illegitimate. But that distinction seems more semantic than substantive.
    • (2004) MINN. L. REV , vol.1021 , pp. 1025
    • William, N.1    Eskridge Jr., L.2
  • 156
    • 47849117796 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also WILLIAM N. ESKRIDGE, JR., DISHONORABLE PASSIONS: SODOMY LAWS IN AMERICA 1861-2003, 36 (Justice Scalia was wrong to conclude that ... Lawrence constitutionalized the 'homosexual agenda' and, further, precluded the states from adopting regulations reflecting and trying to influence public morality. In the short term, the Constitution may tolerate some regulations whose justification is, essentially, no promo homo.).
    • See also WILLIAM N. ESKRIDGE, JR., DISHONORABLE PASSIONS: SODOMY LAWS IN AMERICA 1861-2003, 36 ("Justice Scalia was wrong to conclude that ... Lawrence constitutionalized the 'homosexual agenda' and, further, precluded the states from adopting regulations reflecting and trying to influence public morality. In the short term, the Constitution may tolerate some regulations whose justification is, essentially, no promo homo.").
  • 157
    • 47849084413 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I use liberty here in the legal sense of imposing legal obstacles to or consequences for undertaking an action. Any expression of societal disapproval might, of course, make people feel less free to undertake the action but, in the absence of legal obstacles or consequences, I do not think the effect on a person's perceived freedom to act without social repercussions amounts to restriction of liberty.
    • I use "liberty" here in the legal sense of imposing legal obstacles to or consequences for undertaking an action. Any expression of societal disapproval might, of course, make people feel less free to undertake the action but, in the absence of legal obstacles or consequences, I do not think the effect on a person's perceived freedom to act without social repercussions amounts to restriction of liberty.
  • 158
    • 47849089350 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Eskridge, supra note 118, at 1085 (The state can have morals legislation, but it cannot condemn or criminalize conduct that is deeply moral to many productive Americans.).
    • See Eskridge, supra note 118, at 1085 ("The state can have morals legislation, but it cannot condemn or criminalize conduct that is deeply moral to many productive Americans.").
  • 159
    • 1842783709 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Proper Scope of the Police Power, 79
    • See generally
    • See generally Randy E. Barnett, The Proper Scope of the Police Power, 79 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 429 (2004).
    • (2004) NOTRE DAME L. REV , vol.429
    • Barnett, R.E.1
  • 160
    • 84963456897 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 70 and accompanying text
    • See supra note 70 and accompanying text.
    • See supra
  • 161
    • 47849127793 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Barnett, supra note 121, at 429 (quoting a nineteenth-century definition of the police power as the imposition by the government of such a restraint as will prevent the infliction of injury upon others in the enjoyment of [their private rights]).
    • See Barnett, supra note 121, at 429 (quoting a nineteenth-century definition of the police power as the imposition by the government of "such a restraint as will prevent the infliction of injury upon others in the enjoyment of [their private rights]").
  • 162
    • 47849097065 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See R.A.V. v. City of St. Paul, Minn., 505 U.S. 377, 429 (1992) (Stevens, J., concurring) (noting, in the context of government regulation of private speech, that the scope of protection provided expressive activity depends in part upon its content and character);
    • See R.A.V. v. City of St. Paul, Minn., 505 U.S. 377, 429 (1992) (Stevens, J., concurring) (noting, in the context of government regulation of private speech, that "the scope of protection provided expressive activity depends in part upon its content and character");
  • 163
    • 37149020344 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • School Naming Rights and the First Amendment's Perfect Storm, 96
    • describing the complicated family tree of government speech cases, see also
    • see also Joseph Blocher, School Naming Rights and the First Amendment's Perfect Storm, 96 GEO. L.J. 1, 21-25 (2007) (describing the "complicated family tree" of government speech cases).
    • (2007) GEO. L.J , vol.1 , pp. 21-25
    • Blocher, J.1
  • 164
    • 47849108373 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See U.S. CONST. amend. I.
    • See U.S. CONST. amend. I.
  • 165
    • 47849115504 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kahan, supra note 103, at 1652-53 (It's true that liberal regimes renounce (at least in theory) rankings of a particular sort-such as those based on race, gender, and class-but they haven't renounced all perceptions of high and low, noble and base, worthy and unworthy. Even egalitarians hold pedophiles and sadists in low esteem, for example, not just because such persons threaten physical harm, but because their values reveal them to be despicable. Indeed as Miller points out, those who seek to raise the states of historically subordinated groups seek to reshape our emotional economy so that we'll come to see racists, sexists, and homophobes, among others, as debased in exactly the same way. On this account, the proper course for liberalism is not to obliterate disgust, but to reform its objects so that we come to value what is genuinely high, to despise what is genuinely low
    • See Kahan, supra note 103, at 1652-53 ("It's true that liberal regimes renounce (at least in theory) rankings of a particular sort-such as those based on race, gender, and class-but they haven't renounced all perceptions of high and low, noble and base, worthy and unworthy. Even egalitarians hold pedophiles and sadists in low esteem, for example, not just because such persons threaten physical harm, but because their values reveal them to be despicable. Indeed as Miller points out, those who seek to raise the states of historically subordinated groups seek to reshape our emotional economy so that we'll come to see racists, sexists, and homophobes, among others, as debased in exactly the same way. On this account, the proper course for liberalism is not to obliterate disgust, but to reform its objects so that we come to value what is genuinely high, to despise what is genuinely low.").
  • 167
    • 47849097066 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some supporters of anti-sodomy laws might try to distinguish these laws by arguing that sodomy is merely a practice, while race and sex are intrinsic properties. But when, as here, the practice is so closely tied to identity, this distinction seems to carry little force
    • Some supporters of anti-sodomy laws might try to distinguish these laws by arguing that sodomy is merely a practice, while race and sex are intrinsic properties. But when, as here, the practice is so closely tied to identity, this distinction seems to carry little force.
  • 168
    • 47849089349 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • If they were promulgated, however, perhaps it could be done in conjunction with a self-restriction law in which a person could make it a crime to engage in anti-gay hate speech or otherwise discriminate against homosexuals, thus setting up a clear opposition of competing societal norms. See Eskridge, supra note 118, at 1025 (The LGBT social movement wants to persuade America that gay is good, while the traditional family values (TFV) countermovement wants to persuade America that many gay rights would undermine the family, marriage, and other cherished institutions. This is a fine debate for America to have. The Court is simply insisting that the players not hit below the belt and turn a fair fight into a brawl.).
    • If they were promulgated, however, perhaps it could be done in conjunction with a self-restriction law in which a person could make it a crime to engage in anti-gay hate speech or otherwise discriminate against homosexuals, thus setting up a clear opposition of competing societal norms. See Eskridge, supra note 118, at 1025 ("The LGBT social movement wants to persuade America that gay is good, while the traditional family values (TFV) countermovement wants to persuade America that many gay rights would undermine the family, marriage, and other cherished institutions. This is a fine debate for America to have. The Court is simply insisting that the players not hit below the belt and turn a fair fight into a brawl.").
  • 169
    • 47849117797 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See
    • § 8k, 2000, The flag, when it is in such a condition that it is no longer a fitting emblem for display, should be destroyed in a dignified way, preferably by burning
    • See 4 U.S.C. § 8(k) (2000) ("The flag, when it is in such a condition that it is no longer a fitting emblem for display, should be destroyed in a dignified way, preferably by burning.").
    • 4 U.S.C
  • 170
    • 47849111412 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • If the Supreme Court determines that the Second Amendment renders most gun-control bans unconstitutional, see District of Columbia v. Heller, 128 S. Ct. 645 2007, granting certiorari to determine the constitutionality of a District of Columbia handgun ban, a self-restriction law permitting people to make it illegal for them to purchase or own firearms could also shape societal norms and allow people opposed to gun ownership to take advantage of the intrinsic good of living in a world in which gun possession is illegal, at least for them
    • If the Supreme Court determines that the Second Amendment renders most gun-control bans unconstitutional, see District of Columbia v. Heller, 128 S. Ct. 645 (2007) (granting certiorari to determine the constitutionality of a District of Columbia handgun ban), a self-restriction law permitting people to make it illegal for them to purchase or own firearms could also shape societal norms and allow people opposed to gun ownership to take advantage of the intrinsic good of living in a world in which gun possession is illegal, at least for them.
  • 171
    • 15044358175 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • After the Promise: The STD Consequences of Adolescent Virginity Pledges, 36
    • finding that fifty percent of respondents who had consistently taken abstinence pledges had engaged in vaginal intercourse by age nineteen, See
    • See Hannah Brückner & Peter Bearman, After the Promise: The STD Consequences of Adolescent Virginity Pledges, 36 J. ADOLESCENT HEALTH 271, 275 (2005) (finding that fifty percent of respondents who had consistently taken abstinence pledges had engaged in vaginal intercourse by age nineteen).
    • (2005) J. ADOLESCENT HEALTH , vol.271 , pp. 275
    • Brückner, H.1    Bearman, P.2
  • 172
    • 47849119388 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ECONOMIST, May 31, noting that less than one percent of passengers have taken up British Airways' offer to offset carbon emissions
    • But see The Final Cut, ECONOMIST, May 31, 2007 (noting that less than one percent of passengers have taken up British Airways' offer to offset carbon emissions).
    • (2007) But see The Final Cut


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.