메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 61, Issue 3, 2003, Pages 259-273

Perceptual constraints and perceptual schemata: The possibility of perceptual style

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 45749135669     PISSN: 00218529     EISSN: 15406245     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/1540-6245.00111     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (9)

References (31)
  • 1
    • 61049480222 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Even the examples of analytical cubism by Georges Braque and Picasso, which at first look identical, can, with some familiarity with their work, be told apart on the basis of differences in methods of composition
    • Even the examples of analytical cubism by Georges Braque and Picasso, which at first look identical, can, with some familiarity with their work, be told apart on the basis of differences in methods of composition
  • 2
    • 0003160748 scopus 로고
    • Toward a Theory of Style
    • Berel Lang, University of Pennsylvania Press
    • A parallel treatment of style in music can be found in Leonard B. Meyer, 'Toward a Theory of Style" in Berel Lang, The Concept of Style (University of Pennsylvania Press, 1979)
    • (1979) The Concept of Style
    • Meyer, L.B.1
  • 4
    • 0003674479 scopus 로고
    • Harvard University Press
    • I refer to Arthur Danto's philosophy of art history, according to which art history has ended. See his The Transfiguration of the Commonplace (Harvard University Press, 1981)
    • (1981) The Transfiguration of the Commonplace
  • 5
    • 80054580262 scopus 로고
    • The Styles of Art History: Entities or Processes?
    • Raymond A. Macdonald, "The Styles of Art History: Entities or Processes? The Journal of Speculative Philosophy 7 (1993): 48-63
    • (1993) The Journal of Speculative Philosophy , vol.7 , pp. 48-63
    • MacDonald, R.A.1
  • 6
    • 61049111690 scopus 로고
    • Essence, Expression, and History: Arthur Danto's Philosophy of Art
    • ed. Mark Rollins Oxford: Blackwell
    • Arthur Danto, The Transfiguration of the Commonplace. For a helpful discussion of this aspect of Danto's philosophy of art, see Noël Carroll, "Essence, Expression, and History: Arthur Danto's Philosophy of Art," in Danto and His Critics, ed. Mark Rollins (Oxford: Blackwell, 1993), pp. 79-106
    • (1993) Danto and His Critics , pp. 79-106
    • Carroll, N.1
  • 8
    • 0004076007 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Schema is used, not in the philosophical sense of an established inference, but in the related psychological sense of an internal model or representation of a unit of knowledge that corresponds, roughly, to a domain of interaction with the world. These units might include objects in the usual sense, but also other things "from some attention-riveting detail of an object all the way up to some sophisticated domain of social or linguistic interaction for purposeful beings." Richard L. Gregory, ed., The Oxford Companion to the Mind (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987), p. 696. These units encompass related knowledge to a given context or purpose such that our knowledge storage and retrieval can be as economical as possible, in terms of real time and use of neurons. This means that we store units of related knowledge that when triggered by related items in the environment set off prescriptions for responses. This is what is meant by the claim that expectations and prior learning will influence what you notice and how you respond
    • (1987) The Oxford Companion to the Mind , pp. 696
    • Gregory, R.L.1
  • 9
    • 80054156886 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Every artistic community probably has their equivalent to the young Roar Studio painters of Melbourne from whom a collective roar of color and animation burst forth for a limited time in the early 1980s before they were picked up and tamed by more mainstream art world practices
    • Every artistic community probably has their equivalent to the young Roar Studio painters of Melbourne from whom a collective roar of color and animation burst forth for a limited time in the early 1980s before they were picked up and tamed by more mainstream art world practices
  • 10
    • 54749135824 scopus 로고
    • New York: Macmillan
    • W. K. Wimsatt and M. C. Beardsley wrote a very influential article titled "The Intentional Fallacy," in which they argued that the intention of the artist was irrelevant to an interpretation of an artwork (published in Morris Weitz, ed., Problems in Aesthetics [New York: Macmillan, 1959]). After much published debate, Beardsley conceded that intentions that were explicit and visible in the artwork were relevant to the artwork's interpretation. See Mary Mothersill for a summary of the debate (Beauty Restored [Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984], pp. 14-21). This debate, while timely in the face of formalist theories of art, is superseded in the light of ready-mades like Duchamp's Fountain, which Danto responded to with his theory of indiscernibles wherein the artist's intentions, and the art world's readiness to accept a particular object as an artwork, is what defines an object as an artwork
    • (1959) Problems in Aesthetics
    • Weitz, M.1
  • 11
    • 80054601968 scopus 로고
    • The Artistic Enfranchisement of Real Objects: The Artworld
    • ed. George Dickie and R. J. Sclafani New York: St. Martin's Press
    • See Arthur Danto, "The Artistic Enfranchisement of Real Objects: The Artworld" in Aesthetics: A Critical Anthology, ed. George Dickie and R. J. Sclafani (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1977), pp. 22-35
    • (1977) Aesthetics: A Critical Anthology , pp. 22-35
    • Danto, A.1
  • 12
    • 61049443995 scopus 로고
    • Danto, Style, and Intention
    • For Carroll's argument that Danto is inconsistent in holding that artists' intentions are relevant to interpretation while not to attribution of style, see Noël Carroll, "Danto, Style, and Intention," The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 53 (1995): 251-257
    • (1995) The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , vol.53 , pp. 251-257
    • Carroll, N.1
  • 15
    • 0003834557 scopus 로고
    • New York: W. H. Freeman
    • David Marr, Vision (New York: W. H. Freeman, 1982)
    • (1982) Vision
    • Marr, D.1
  • 17
    • 12444253421 scopus 로고
    • Oxford University Press
    • Marr, Vision. See also the various perceptual strategies explored in The Artful Eye, ed. Richard Gregory, John Harris, Priscilla Heard, and David Rose (Oxford University Press, 1995)
    • (1995) The Artful Eye
    • Gregory, R.1    Harris, J.2    Heard, P.3    Rose, D.4
  • 18
    • 58749097381 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An Explanation for Normal and Anomalous Drawing Ability and Some Implications for Research on Perception and Imagery
    • Another way to make this distinction is between structural (primary) and denotational (secondary) descriptions; only the latter involves semantic content. See J. A. McMahon, "An Explanation for Normal and Anomalous Drawing Ability and Some Implications for Research on Perception and Imagery," Visual Arts Research 28 (2002): 38-52
    • (2002) Visual Arts Research , vol.28 , pp. 38-52
    • McMahon, J.A.1
  • 21
    • 0026524861 scopus 로고
    • Mental Images Can Be Ambiguous: Reconstruais and Reference-Frame Reversals
    • That such a separation of the visual experience from semantic content is possible, see M. A. Peterson, J. F. Kihlstrom, P. Rose, and M. L. Glisky, "Mental Images Can Be Ambiguous: Reconstruais and Reference-Frame Reversals," Memory and Cognition 20 (1993): 102-123
    • (1993) Memory and Cognition , vol.20 , pp. 102-123
    • Peterson, M.A.1    Kihlstrom, J.F.2    Rose, P.3    Glisky, M.L.4
  • 22
    • 45749139891 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Invisible Content of Visual Art
    • esp. p. 25
    • This paper began as a response to Mark Rollins's suggestion that the perception of certain artworks might, in effect, isolate, select, and combine perceptual strategies in various ways. See Mark Rollins, "The Invisible Content of Visual Art," The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 59 (2001): 19-27, esp. p. 25
    • (2001) The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , vol.59 , pp. 19-27
    • Rollins, M.1
  • 23
    • 0034372561 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Using Science to Investigate Jackson Pollock's Drip Paintings
    • Richard P. Taylor, Adam P. Micolich, and David Jonas, "Using Science to Investigate Jackson Pollock's Drip Paintings," Journal of Consciousness Studies 7 (2000): 137-150
    • (2000) Journal of Consciousness Studies , vol.7 , pp. 137-150
    • Taylor, R.P.1    Micolich, A.P.2    Jonas, D.3
  • 24
    • 80054616459 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Viewer-centered means that our focus is centered on just the particular view we have at any one moment. It is like framing the particular view that you have and noticing the relations between objects just as much as the shape of the objects themselves. Object-centered means that you bring to bear all the assumptions you have about the solidity of objects, and the fact that there are relatively few connected surfaces, and you register the shapes you perceive as connected, variously sized volumes, ipso facto objects. Marr, Vision, for a more detailed explanation. Or for a very introductory text, part 2 of Ilona Roth and Vicki Bruce, Perception and Representation (Philadelphia: Open University Press, 1995)
    • Viewer-centered means that our focus is centered on just the particular view we have at any one moment. It is like framing the particular view that you have and noticing the relations between objects just as much as the shape of the objects themselves. Object-centered means that you bring to bear all the assumptions you have about the solidity of objects, and the fact that there are relatively few connected surfaces, and you register the shapes you perceive as connected, variously sized volumes, ipso facto objects. See Marr, Vision, for a more detailed explanation. Or for a very introductory text, see part 2 of Ilona Roth and Vicki Bruce, Perception and Representation (Philadelphia: Open University Press, 1995)
  • 25
    • 0004138656 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Bradford, MIT Press, chaps. 5 and 9
    • Robert L. Solso, Cognition and the Visual Arts (Cambridge, MA: Bradford, MIT Press, 1994), chaps. 5 and 9
    • (1994) Cognition and the Visual Arts
    • Solso, R.L.1
  • 26
    • 84870095771 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Solso writes: "Artists throughout the ages have chosen to emphasize one or another aspect of the rules of visual perception in the way they portray their impression of the world and its people" (p. 230). His examples: Peter Max: illumination, colors, and a hint of visual perspective; Roy Lichtenstein: linear perspective, occluded objects, diminishing size; M. C. Escher: shadows, linear perspective, exploits the saccadic nature of our eye movement during visual perception, and top-down expectations; Picasso: (analytical cubism) exploits linear perspective, shapes from shading, occluding contours, orientational and volumetric primitives; Cezanne: motion parallax; binocular disparity; color as tone; Van Gogh: distorted laws of linear perspective; Monet: atmospheric perspective, color as tone (to show depth), occluded objects, diminishing detail in texture to show depth; diminishing size, elevation, and linear perspective; Leonardo's Last Supper: linear perspective, gestalt
    • Solso writes: "Artists throughout the ages have chosen to emphasize one or another aspect of the rules of visual perception in the way they portray their impression of the world and its people" (p. 230). His examples: Peter Max: illumination, colors, and a hint of visual perspective; Roy Lichtenstein: linear perspective, occluded objects, diminishing size; M. C. Escher: shadows, linear perspective, exploits the saccadic nature of our eye movement during visual perception, and top-down expectations; Picasso: (analytical cubism) exploits linear perspective, shapes from shading, occluding contours, orientational and volumetric primitives; Cezanne: motion parallax; binocular disparity; color as tone; Van Gogh: distorted laws of linear perspective; Monet: atmospheric perspective, color as tone (to show depth), occluded objects, diminishing detail in texture to show depth; diminishing size, elevation, and linear perspective; Leonardo's Last Supper: linear perspective, gestalt groupings (four groups of heads); Massacio's The Holy Trinity in Santa Maria Novella: linear perspective, elevation, occluding figures; Jan van Eyck's The Betrothal of Arnolfini: linear perspective, occluding objects, diminishing size, shape from shading, atmospheric perspective
  • 27
    • 0003827546 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Phaidon Press
    • I use "realistic" as though it is an unproblematic style category. It is not. For an example of the issues involved, see Ernst Gombrich's Art and Illusion (Oxford: Phaidon Press, 1977)
    • (1977) Art and Illusion
    • Gombrich, E.1
  • 28
    • 0004261997 scopus 로고
    • Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill
    • and Nelson Goodman's Languages of Art (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1968)
    • (1968) Languages of Art
    • Goodman, N.1
  • 29
    • 0003075135 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Spatial Representation and Selection in the Brain: Neuropsychological and Computational Constraints
    • 9-47
    • See Glyn Humphreys and Dietmar Heinke, "Spatial Representation and Selection in the Brain: Neuropsychological and Computational Constraints," Visual Cognition 5 (1998): 1-2 and 9-47
    • (1998) Visual Cognition , vol.5 , pp. 1-2
    • Humphreys, G.1    Heinke, D.2
  • 30
    • 80054580145 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This would be an example of ontogenetic, not phylogenetic, evolution
    • This would be an example of ontogenetic, not phylogenetic, evolution
  • 31
    • 80054601831 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I would like to thank Michael Davis (Ph.D. scholar, Australian National University) for his research assistance, which was funded by an Australian Research Council small grant, awarded to me by the University of Canberra, 2001. I would also like to express my gratitude to an anonymous referee for The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism for very helpful suggestions and constructive criticisms, which I have attempted to address. I am especially grateful to Philip Alperson for his support of this paper
    • I would like to thank Michael Davis (Ph.D. scholar, Australian National University) for his research assistance, which was funded by an Australian Research Council small grant, awarded to me by the University of Canberra, 2001. I would also like to express my gratitude to an anonymous referee for The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism for very helpful suggestions and constructive criticisms, which I have attempted to address. I am especially grateful to Philip Alperson for his support of this paper


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.