-
1
-
-
0004022577
-
-
Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
Multicultural Citizenship (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995), p. vii
-
(1995)
Multicultural Citizenship
-
-
-
2
-
-
79956777395
-
-
New Zealand History Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
This is emphasised in both Article Two, and again in the final clause, of the Treaty of Waitangi; Waitangi: Maori and Pakeha Perspectives of the Treaty of Waitangi, ed. I. H. Kawharu (Auckland: Oxford University Press, 1989), pp. 316-8. The Secretary of State for War and Colonies, Lord Normanby, was insistent on this point in his formal instructions to the British negotiator, Captain Hobson; W. David Mclntyre and W. J. Gardner, eds., Speeches and Documents on New Zealand History (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1971), pp. 10-7 at p. 14
-
(1971)
Speeches and Documents
, pp. 10-17
-
-
David Mclntyre, W.1
Gardner, W.J.2
-
3
-
-
79956777482
-
-
Lord Nottingham, Maynard v. Moseley [1676] 3 Swan. 651, 655, 36 E.R. 1009, 1011. In fact, of course, that is broadly what Courts of Chancery and the law of equity did throughout the ages; P. S. Atiyah, The Rise and Fall of Freedom of Contract (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1979), pp. 148 ff
-
(1676)
Maynard v. Moseley
, vol.3
-
-
Nottingham, L.1
-
4
-
-
0011914618
-
-
Vattel, The Law of Nations, bk. 2, ch. 12. See similarly Wolff, The Law of Nations, sec. 407
-
The Law of Nations
-
-
Vattel1
-
5
-
-
79956765353
-
The Merchant of Venice
-
William Shakespeare, The Merchant of Venice, Act IV, Scene I
-
Act
, vol.4
-
-
Shakespeare, W.1
-
6
-
-
0031475724
-
-
I refer here specifically to the practice of putting day-to-day social relations on a contractual footing ('contractualism', in contemporary jargon). It remains perfectly possible that practices which are not themselves contractual in form might nonetheless have some deeper 'contractarian' foundations. See David Gauthier, 'Political contractarianism', Journal of Political Philosophy, 5 (1997), 132-48
-
(1997)
Political contractarianism, Journal of Political Philosophy
, vol.5
, pp. 132-148
-
-
Gauthier, D.1
-
9
-
-
79956787170
-
-
ed. Kawharu
-
A useful comparative analysis of the two texts by I. H. Kawharu is contained in Waitangi, ed. Kawharu, pp. 316-21. The differences are discussed more fully in Section IV below
-
is contained in Waitangi
, pp. 316-321
-
-
Kawharu, I.H.1
-
10
-
-
78149451994
-
-
Knowing that, they still appeal surprisingly frequently to precisely these treaties, insisting we govern relations in accordance with them. See Russel Barsh and James Youngblood Henderson, The Road: Indian Tribes and Political Liberty (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1980); Prucha, American Indian Treaties, esp. ch. 17; James Tully, Strange Multiplicity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), esp. pp. 116-39; and Robert A. Williams, Jr., 'The algebra of federal Indian law', Wisconsin Law Review, (1986), 219-99; and, on the role of the Treaty of Waitangi in recent Aotearora/New Zealand political debates, Sharp, Justice and the Maori
-
(1980)
The Road: Indian Tribes and Political Liberty
-
-
Barsh, R.1
Youngblood Henderson, J.2
-
11
-
-
0004162813
-
-
Shaw, Title to Territory in Africa, pp. 38-45. Note that the whole of chapter 5 ('On Property') of the Second Treatise of Government is 'organized around a contrast between Europe, where appropriation without consent is not permitted because political societies exist, and America, where appropriation without consent is permitted because it is in a state of nature'; Tully, An Approach to Political Philosophy, p. 145. These arguments were used to the particular disadvantage of Australian Aborigines, as discussed in Section III below
-
Title to Territory in Africa
, pp. 38-45
-
-
Shaw1
-
12
-
-
33744929448
-
Law, sovereignty and history in a divided culture: the case of New Zealand and the Treaty of Waitangi
-
Oct
-
As suggested by Kawharu, Waitangi, p. 319, insistently translating 'kawanatanga' as meaning merely 'government'. See further J. G. A. Pocock, 'Law, sovereignty and history in a divided culture: the case of New Zealand and the Treaty of Waitangi', McGill Law Journal 43 (Oct 1998), 481-506
-
(1998)
McGill Law Journal
, vol.43
, pp. 481-506
-
-
Pocock, J.G.A.1
-
15
-
-
34247943218
-
Liberal society and the Indian question
-
Prucha, American Indian Treaties
-
Michael Paul Rogin, 'Liberal society and the Indian question', Politics & Society 1 (1971), 269-312. Prucha, American Indian Treaties, ch. 7
-
(1971)
Politics & Society
, vol.1
, pp. 269-312
-
-
Rogin, M.P.1
-
16
-
-
79956783785
-
-
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
-
For a fuller specification of exploitable vulnerabilities, see Robert E. Goodin, Protecting the Vulnerable (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1985), ch. 7 and Reasons for Welfare (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1988), ch. 5
-
(1988)
Protecting the Vulnerable (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1985), ch. 7 and Reasons for Welfare
-
-
Goodin, R.E.1
-
17
-
-
0004312118
-
-
17th edn London: John Murray
-
Henry Sumner Maine, Ancient Law, 17th edn (London: John Murray, 1901)
-
(1901)
Ancient Law
-
-
Sumner Maine, H.1
-
18
-
-
0004180920
-
-
trans, and ed. G. D. H. Cole (London: Everyman/Dent)
-
Jean-Jacques Rousseau, A Discourse on the Origins of Inequality, in The Social Contract and Discourses, trans, and ed. G. D. H. Cole (London: Everyman/Dent, 1913), pp. 27-114, the quotation from the opening lines of pt. 2, at p. 76 of this edition
-
(1913)
A Discourse on the Origins of Inequality, in The Social Contract and Discourses
, pp. 27-114
-
-
Rousseau, J.-J.1
-
19
-
-
0003945278
-
-
Oxford: Polity
-
The Sexual Contract (Oxford: Polity, 1988)
-
(1988)
The Sexual Contract
-
-
-
20
-
-
79956783892
-
-
McHugh, 'Constitutional theory and Maori claims' and 'Crown-tribe relations', pp. 205-8. The analogy in view is between 'individuals subjecting themselves completely to other individuals' and 'groups/peoples subjecting themselves completely to other groups/peoples'. Individually of course we are all the time subjecting ourselves to groups, taking 'oaths of allegiance' and such like. Most of us recognise the practical inevitability of living under some government or another. There is however no corresponding inevitability or practical necessity of one group of people being ruled over by some other
-
Constitutional theory and Maori claims' and 'Crown-tribe relations
, pp. 205-208
-
-
McHugh1
-
21
-
-
0004287799
-
-
Hobbes, Leviathan, ch. 20. Locke, Second Treatise, secs. 23-4. Earlier writers such as Aristotle, Politics, trans. and ed. Ernest Barker (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1946), bk. I, ch. 6 foreshadowed this argument, among others; and even Grotius, Law of War and Peace, bk. 2, ch. 5, secs. 27-30 was inclined to treat the just enslavement of captives as just a special case of slaves justly swapping liberty for sustenance, under force of necessity. Cf. Rousseau, Social Contract, bk. 1, ch. 4 and Discourse on Inequality, pt. 2, p. 95
-
Leviathan
-
-
Hobbes1
-
22
-
-
79956787259
-
-
In the words of Vattel, Law of Nations, bk. 2, ch. 12, p. 168. See similarly Wolff, Law of Nations, secs. 399-403
-
Law of Nations, secs
, pp. 399-403
-
-
Wolff, S.1
-
23
-
-
79956787258
-
Duties of nations to themselves
-
'Duties of nations to themselves', discussed below, apart
-
-
-
-
24
-
-
0003310747
-
Self-government revisited
-
ed. David Miller and Larry Siedentop (Oxford: Clarendon Press Allen E. Buchanan, Secession
-
Enshrined, some international lawyers might say, in the Charter of the United Nations, Articles 1(2) and 55. For an international law discussion, see Brownlie, Principles of Public International Law, ch. 24. For some recent philosophical treatments, see: Brian Barry, 'Self-government revisited', The Nature of Political Theory, ed. David Miller and Larry Siedentop (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983), pp. 121-54; Allen E. Buchanan, Secession (Boulder, CO: Westview, 1991);
-
(1983)
The Nature of Political Theory
, pp. 121-154
-
-
Barry, B.1
-
25
-
-
0000182108
-
National self-determination
-
Avishai Margalit and Joseph Raz, 'National self-determination', Journal of Philosophy, 87 (1990), 439-61
-
(1990)
Journal of Philosophy
, vol.87
, pp. 439-461
-
-
Margalit, A.1
Raz, J.2
-
27
-
-
0004204159
-
-
Wolff, Law of Nations, sec. 80. Wolff, of course, insists that this is permissible only if it is 'not strong enough to protect itself against the wrongs done by other nations'
-
Law of Nations
-
-
Wolff1
-
29
-
-
0002251645
-
however, defends the notion of posthumous harm to individuals; 'The rights of animals and unborn generations
-
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press Harm to Others (New York: Oxford University Press
-
Joel Feinberg, however, defends the notion of posthumous harm to individuals; 'The rights of animals and unborn generations', Rights, Justice and the Bounds of Liberty (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1980), pp. 159-84, and Harm to Others (New York: Oxford University Press, 1984), ch. 2. In any case the identity and even existence conditions of a nation are radically distinct from those surrounding individuals; Robert E. Goodin, Political Theory and Public Policy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1982), ch. 11. The upshot is that it is possible for interests to survive the 'extinguishing' of one state and its replacement by a successor state; Brownlie, Principles of Public International Law, ch. 28
-
(1980)
Rights, Justice and the Bounds of Liberty
, pp. 159-184
-
-
J.el Feinberg1
-
31
-
-
0003944881
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
They are surveyed in Robert E. Goodin, Utilitarianism as a Public Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), ch. 9.1 say 'most' in this and the following sentences, because the final argument surveyed there, of course, is precisely the Mill argument introduced and defended below
-
(1995)
Utilitarianism as a Public Philosophy
-
-
Goodin, R.E.1
-
35
-
-
79956796538
-
-
Though in a Separate Opinion in Barcelona Traction (Second Phase), International Court of Justice Reports (1970), 286-333 at 304, Judge Ammoun did allude to principles of self-determination as among those 'peremptory norms of general international law'-although the only authority he quoted in support of that claim consisted merely of a speech by UN Secretary General U Thant
-
(1970)
Though in a Separate Opinion in Barcelona Traction
, pp. 286-333
-
-
-
36
-
-
0004165120
-
-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
Thomas C. Schelling, The Strategy of Conflict (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1960), p. 43.
-
(1960)
The Strategy of Conflict
, pp. 43
-
-
Schelling, T.C.1
-
37
-
-
0039918831
-
Exchange theory on strategic bases
-
Russell Hardin, 'Exchange theory on strategic bases', Social Science Information 21 (1982), 251-72, at pp. 260-2
-
(1982)
Social Science Information
, vol.21
, pp. 251-272
-
-
Hardin, R.1
-
38
-
-
0040950970
-
Legislative intent
-
Gerald C. MacCallum, Jr., 'Legislative intent', Yale Law Journal 75 (1966), 754-87
-
(1966)
Yale Law Journal
, vol.75
, pp. 754-787
-
-
Jr.MacCallum, G.C.1
-
39
-
-
84929068794
-
Can the Treaty of Waitangi provide a constitutional basis for New Zealand's political future?
-
In what follows, I use the English text and the more colloquial version of the two Maori translations found in Kawharu, Waitangi, pp. 316-21. For further discussions, see Richard Mulgan, 'Can the Treaty of Waitangi provide a constitutional basis for New Zealand's political future?' Political Science 41, # 2 (Dec. 1989), 51-68, at pp. 55-6; and Pocock, 'Law, sovereignty and history in a divided culture'
-
(1989)
Political Science
, vol.41
, pp. 51-68
-
-
Mulgan, R.1
-
41
-
-
0000098233
-
Originalism: the lesser evil
-
Antonin Scalia, 'Originalism: the lesser evil', University of Cincinnati Law Review 57 (1989), 849-65 is a conspicuous exception here. More representative are, e.g.: Sunstein, After the Rights Revolution and 'Five theses on originalism', Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy 19, #2 (Winter 1996), 311-6; William N. Eskridge, Jr., 'Public values in statutory interpretation', University of Pennsylvania Law Review 137 (1989), 1007-1104 and Dynamic Statutory Interpretation (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1994); and Ronald M. Dworkin, Freedom's Law: The Moral Reading of the American Constitution (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1996), ch. 5. See, more generally, the 'Symposium: originalism and the Constitution', Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy 19, #2 (Winter 1996), 237-525
-
(1989)
University of Cincinnati Law Review
, vol.57
, pp. 849-865
-
-
Scalia, A.1
-
42
-
-
0003761185
-
-
Canadian Royal Commission on Aboriginal Peoples, People to People, Nation to Nation (Ottawa: Ministry of Supply & Services Canada, 1996), ch. 2
-
(1996)
People to People, Nation to Nation
-
-
-
43
-
-
79956731725
-
-
Holmes, in Missouri v. Holland, 252 US 416, 433 (1920). Quoted in Sunstein, After the Rights Revolution, p. 126
-
(1920)
Missouri v. Holland
, vol.252
-
-
Holmes1
-
44
-
-
84935493449
-
Superseding historic injustice
-
Jeremy Waldron, 'Superseding historic injustice', Ethics 103 (1992), 4-28 at p. 9. See similarly David Lyons, 'The new indian claims and the original rights to land', Social Theory & Practice 4 (1977), 249-72
-
(1992)
Ethics
, vol.103
, pp. 4-28
-
-
Waldron, J.1
-
45
-
-
84925906445
-
The new indian claims and the original rights to land
-
David Lyons, 'The new indian claims and the original rights to land', Social Theory & Practice 4 (1977), 249-72
-
(1977)
Social Theory & Practice
, vol.4
, pp. 249-272
-
-
Lyons, D.1
-
46
-
-
0011586310
-
-
Richard Mulgan, Maori, Pakeha and Democracy (Auckland: Oxford University Press, 1989) and 'Can the Treaty of Waitangi provide a constitutional basis for New Zealand's political future?'
-
(1989)
Maori, Pakeha and Democracy
-
-
Mulgan, R.1
-
50
-
-
0031479753
-
Plessy v. Ferguson in libertarian perspective
-
Mark Tushnet, 'Plessy v. Ferguson in libertarian perspective', Law & Philosophy 16 (1997), 245-58
-
(1997)
Law & Philosophy
, vol.16
, pp. 245-258
-
-
Tushnet, M.1
-
51
-
-
0004292576
-
-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
Goodin, Political Theory and Public Policy, ch. 5. See similarly Avishai Margalit, The Decent Society (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1996)
-
(1996)
The Decent Society
-
-
Margalit, S.A.1
-
52
-
-
0003497974
-
-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
Bruce Ackerman, We, the People (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1991)
-
(1991)
We, the People
-
-
Ackerman, B.1
|