-
1
-
-
0003624191
-
-
New York: Columbia University Press
-
John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996), p. 64, n. 19.
-
(1996)
Political Liberalism
, Issue.19
, pp. 64
-
-
Rawls, J.1
-
2
-
-
4344632353
-
-
note
-
I should point out a technical distinction here. Citizens who fail in their duty of moral civility in a particular instance (they fail to adhere to the norms of public reason when they ought to) are not necessarily being unreasonable. They may well accept points (1)-(3), but simply have failed to act as those three premises require, or they may mistakenly believe that the duty of moral civility does not apply in their given situation. Being unreasonable entails a definite rejection of one of the three points mentioned.
-
-
-
-
3
-
-
4344700932
-
-
note
-
It is clearly possible for citizens who are generally reasonable to make unreasonable demands, and vice versa. Strictly speaking, therefore, it is not the unreasonable citizen who is ignored by public reason, but rather unreasonable views or claims.
-
-
-
-
4
-
-
80053870593
-
John Rawls and the political coercion of unreasonable people
-
ed. Victoria Davion and Clark Wolf (Oxford: Rowman & Littlefield)
-
Marilyn Friedman, 'John Rawls and the Political Coercion of Unreasonable People," The Idea of a Political Liberalism: Essays on John Rawls, ed. Victoria Davion and Clark Wolf (Oxford: Rowman & Littlefield, 2000), p. 23.
-
(2000)
The Idea of a Political Liberalism: Essays on John Rawls
, pp. 23
-
-
Friedman, M.1
-
5
-
-
0002231837
-
The idea of public reason revisited
-
ed. Samuel Freeman (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press)
-
Rawls, 'The Idea of Public Reason Revisited,' Collected Papers, ed. Samuel Freeman (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1999), p. 614. Also see Rawls, The Law of Peoples (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1999), p. 16, n. 8, where he explicitly rejects the type of argument attributed to him by Friedman.
-
(1999)
Collected Papers
, pp. 614
-
-
Rawls1
-
6
-
-
0003499065
-
-
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
-
Rawls, 'The Idea of Public Reason Revisited,' Collected Papers, ed. Samuel Freeman (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1999), p. 614. Also see Rawls, The Law of Peoples (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1999), p. 16, n. 8, where he explicitly rejects the type of argument attributed to him by Friedman.
-
(1999)
The Law of Peoples
, Issue.8
, pp. 16
-
-
Rawls1
-
7
-
-
0004048289
-
-
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
-
See Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971), p. 218.
-
(1971)
A Theory of Justice
, pp. 218
-
-
Rawls1
-
8
-
-
0003836741
-
-
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
-
Rawls, Justice as Fairness: A Restatement (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2001), p. 81.
-
(2001)
Justice as Fairness: A Restatement
, pp. 81
-
-
Rawls1
-
9
-
-
84930561211
-
Reason and agreement in social contract views
-
For more on the role of the conception of the person in the original position see Samuel Freeman, 'Reason and agreement in social contract views,' Philosophy and Public Affairs, 19 (1990), 122-57.
-
(1990)
Philosophy and Public Affairs
, vol.19
, pp. 122-157
-
-
Freeman, S.1
-
13
-
-
0003624191
-
-
For more on the burdens of judgement, see Rawls, Political Liberalism, pp. 54-8.
-
Political Liberalism
, pp. 54-58
-
-
Rawls1
-
19
-
-
0007310158
-
The idea of public reason revisited
-
Rawls, 'The idea of public reason revisited,' Collected Papers, p. 592.
-
Collected Papers
, pp. 592
-
-
Rawls1
-
26
-
-
0042341237
-
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
This position is also defended by Gerald F. Gaus in Justificatory Liberalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996), pp. 164-5.
-
(1996)
Justificatory Liberalism
, pp. 164-165
-
-
Gaus, G.F.1
-
27
-
-
0004048289
-
-
Again see Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 218. There is also a parallel here with Rawls's theory of international justice, and his argument as to why liberal societies should tolerate nonliberal peoples. Although 'decent societies,' to use Rawls's term, are not initially represented in the second original position used to derive the law of peoples, the principle of international toleration nevertheless applies to them. See Rawls, The Law of Peoples, part II. I should note that I do not agree with much of what Rawls has to say about 'decent societies' in the international system, but this can be set aside for the moment, as it does provide a clear version of the argument I wish to present.
-
A Theory of Justice
, pp. 218
-
-
Rawls1
-
28
-
-
4344642077
-
-
Again see Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 218. There is also a parallel here with Rawls's theory of international justice, and his argument as to why liberal societies should tolerate nonliberal peoples. Although 'decent societies,' to use Rawls's term, are not initially represented in the second original position used to derive the law of peoples, the principle of international toleration nevertheless applies to them. See Rawls, The Law of Peoples, part II. I should note that I do not agree with much of what Rawls has to say about 'decent societies' in the international system, but this can be set aside for the moment, as it does provide a clear version of the argument I wish to present.
-
The Law of Peoples, Part II
-
-
Rawls1
-
29
-
-
4344667590
-
-
note
-
We should note that neither Friedman, nor Kelly and McPherson endorse the substantive conclusions in (2) and (3)-rather they are attempting to criticise (1) by claiming that these unacceptable conclusions follow from it.
-
-
-
-
30
-
-
4344572410
-
-
Rawls, Political Liberalism, p. 64, n. 19. Also see A Theory of Justice, pp. 219-20.
-
Political Liberalism
, Issue.19
, pp. 64
-
-
Rawls1
-
31
-
-
84871647310
-
-
Rawls, Political Liberalism, p. 64, n. 19. Also see A Theory of Justice, pp. 219-20.
-
A Theory of Justice
, pp. 219-220
-
-
-
35
-
-
4344685565
-
-
note
-
The experience of the United States, especially the American South, in the period between the Civil War and the present day is, I think, a compelling example of a generally liberal democratic society which nevertheless allowed unreasonableness (in the form of racism) to spread unchecked from generation to generation, and as a result African-Americans suffered terrible abuses of human rights and dignities.
-
-
-
-
36
-
-
0042341237
-
-
For the difference between undefeated and victorious public reasons see Gaus, Justificatory Liberalism, pp. 144-58.
-
Justificatory Liberalism
, pp. 144-158
-
-
Gaus1
-
37
-
-
4344646067
-
-
note
-
I believe the containment argument may extend to other categories as well, but I focus here on the education case-the aim is just to show that the containment argument can work in at least one instance, not to enumerate all the possible instances where it might work.
-
-
-
-
38
-
-
0004154937
-
-
(Oxford: Oxford University Press), ch. 6
-
For a more extensive discussion of the parental right to educational choice see Eamonn Callan, Creating Citizens (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997), ch. 6.
-
(1997)
Creating Citizens
-
-
Callan, E.1
-
39
-
-
0004266638
-
-
Baltimore, Md.: John Hopkins University Press
-
Although the example I use here is fictional, it mirrors in some ways the real example of Hasidic Jews used by Jeff Spinner in The Boundaries of Citizenship (Baltimore, Md.: John Hopkins University Press, 1994), pp. 108-12.
-
(1994)
The Boundaries of Citizenship
, pp. 108-112
-
-
Spinner, J.1
-
40
-
-
4344599602
-
Creating citizens
-
ch. 6; or Amy Gutmann, (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press)
-
Again, for more on this see Callan, Creating Citizens, ch. 6; or Amy Gutmann, Democratic Education (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1999).
-
(1999)
Democratic Education
-
-
Callan1
-
41
-
-
0004156723
-
-
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
-
The two cases differ, of course. The state is justified in intervening in the education of the unreasonable community and so the parents' rights are merely infringed, whereas the case of the nosy neighbours involves a rights violation because the intervention is unjustified. For the distinction between infringing and violating a right see Judith Jarvis Thompson, Rights, Restitution and Risk (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1986), p. 40.
-
(1986)
Rights, Restitution and Risk
, pp. 40
-
-
Thompson, J.J.1
-
43
-
-
0003440982
-
-
Spinner-Halev, The Boundaries of Citizenship, pp. 95-9. Also his 'Cultural pluralism and partial citizenship," Multicultural Questions, ed. Christian Joppke and Steven Lukes (Oxford; Oxford University Press, 1999), pp. 65-86; and his Surviving Diversity (Baltimore, Md.: John Hopkins University Press, 2000).
-
The Boundaries of Citizenship
, pp. 95-99
-
-
Spinner-Halev1
-
44
-
-
0010849810
-
Cultural pluralism and partial citizenship
-
Oxford; Oxford University Press
-
Spinner-Halev, The Boundaries of Citizenship, pp. 95-9. Also his 'Cultural pluralism and partial citizenship," Multicultural Questions, ed. Christian Joppke and Steven Lukes (Oxford; Oxford University Press, 1999), pp. 65-86; and his Surviving Diversity (Baltimore, Md.: John Hopkins University Press, 2000).
-
(1999)
Multicultural Questions
, pp. 65-86
-
-
Joppke, C.1
Lukes, S.2
-
45
-
-
0040625939
-
-
Baltimore, Md.: John Hopkins University Press
-
Spinner-Halev, The Boundaries of Citizenship, pp. 95-9. Also his 'Cultural pluralism and partial citizenship," Multicultural Questions, ed. Christian Joppke and Steven Lukes (Oxford; Oxford University Press, 1999), pp. 65-86; and his Surviving Diversity (Baltimore, Md.: John Hopkins University Press, 2000).
-
(2000)
Surviving Diversity
-
-
-
46
-
-
0003440982
-
-
See The Boundaries of Citizenship, pp. 95-9. I should point out that the Amish are not necessarily unreasonable citizens. The fact that they reject the modern world does not mean they reject the freedom and equality of persons. I am imagining a group that shares the Amish's desire to be left alone, but is also unreasonable.
-
The Boundaries of Citizenship
, pp. 95-99
-
-
-
47
-
-
0037620531
-
-
Spinner-Halev's most recent book, Surviving Diversity, focuses on the problems posed by this second category of persons for the United States, although the groups he examines are not always unreasonable in the strict sense. He identifies Protestant fundamentalists, Orthodox Catholics, and Orthodox and Hasidic Jews as conservative religious groups whose goals will often conflict with those of liberalism.
-
Surviving Diversity
-
-
Spinner-Halev1
-
49
-
-
4344566494
-
-
note
-
I define hate speech or literature as expression whose primary intention is to deny the freedom and equality of persons.
-
-
-
-
50
-
-
1342298676
-
A right to do wrong
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
Jeremy Waldron, 'A right to do wrong,' Liberal Rights (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), pp. 63-87.
-
(1993)
Liberal Rights
, pp. 63-87
-
-
Waldron, J.1
-
53
-
-
84874000720
-
-
I should point out that, even if he accepted the distinction, Waldron would not draw the line between wrongness and unreasonableness in the same place as I do here. He appears to believe, for example, that we have a right to join a racist political party and endeavour to get it elected, whereas I will deny that we do have this right. See Ibid., p. 63.
-
Liberal Rights
, pp. 63
-
-
-
54
-
-
2942710101
-
Social unity and primary goods
-
Rawls, 'Social unity and primary goods,' Collected Papers, p. 386.
-
Collected Papers
, pp. 386
-
-
Rawls1
-
55
-
-
52549100332
-
Rights in conflict
-
Waldron, 'Rights in conflict,' Liberal Rights, pp. 222-3.
-
Liberal Rights
, pp. 222-223
-
-
Waldron1
-
57
-
-
0004223708
-
-
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press
-
Ronald Dworkin focuses on both of these arguments in his defence of the right to hate speech, but does not address the more fundamental objection pressed here. See Dworkin, Sovereign Virtue (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2000), pp. 365-6.
-
(2000)
Sovereign Virtue
, pp. 365-366
-
-
Dworkin1
-
58
-
-
4344579568
-
-
note
-
If the Nazis were demanding the suppression of the Communists on containment grounds, that is, claiming that the communists were spreading unreasonable doctrines, then the Nazi speech might be defensible as a legitimate use of political speech. This example is, however, implausible, as it relies on the untenable assumption that the Nazis are sincerely attempting to defend the liberal democratic order.
-
-
-
-
59
-
-
4344568796
-
-
note
-
Rights can of course be more or less stringent, depending on the interest they are meant to protect.
-
-
-
-
60
-
-
4344606757
-
-
note
-
There will undoubtedly be hard cases that will be difficult to place easily into one of the three categories, but this fact is not a serious objection to the general typology provided here.
-
-
-
|