메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 32, Issue 5, 2006, Pages 573-599

The basic norm and democracy in Hans Kelsen's legal and political theory

Author keywords

basic norm; constitutional making; constitu ere; democracy; Hannah Arendt; Hans Kelsen; immanent norm

Indexed keywords


EID: 43249173852     PISSN: 01914537     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1177/0191453706064898     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (28)

References (163)
  • 1
    • 0042081329 scopus 로고
    • Professor Stone and the Pure Theory of Law
    • July
    • Hans Kelsen, ‘Professor Stone and the Pure Theory of Law’, Stanford Law Review 17 (July 1965): 1143.
    • (1965) Stanford Law Review , vol.17 , pp. 1143
    • Kelsen, H.1
  • 2
    • 85017298442 scopus 로고
    • On the Basic Norm
    • Hans Kelsen, ‘On the Basic Norm’, California Law Review 47(1) (1959): 107.
    • (1959) California Law Review , vol.47 , Issue.1 , pp. 107
    • Kelsen, H.1
  • 4
    • 0003516637 scopus 로고
    • trans. A. Wedberg (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 437–8
    • Hans Kelsen, General Theory of Law and State, trans. A. Wedberg (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1945), pp. 405, 437–8.
    • (1945) General Theory of Law and State , pp. 405
    • Kelsen, H.1
  • 5
    • 0004287704 scopus 로고
    • trans. M. Knight (Berkeley: University of California Press, n. 23
    • Hans Kelsen, Pure Theory of Law, trans. M. Knight (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1978), p. 50, n. 23.
    • (1978) Pure Theory of Law , pp. 50
    • Kelsen, H.1
  • 6
    • 84998123173 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Science and Politics
    • Kelsen, ‘Science and Politics’, p. 361.
    • Kelsen1
  • 8
    • 77952809017 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Basic Norm of Society
    • ed. Stanley L. Paulson and Bonnie Litschewski Paulson (Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • Tony Honoré, ‘The Basic Norm of Society’, in Normativity and Norms: Critical Perspectives on Kelsenian Themes, ed. Stanley L. Paulson and Bonnie Litschewski Paulson (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998), p. 90.
    • (1998) Normativity and Norms: Critical Perspectives on Kelsenian Themes , pp. 90
    • Honoré, T.1
  • 10
    • 84997911819 scopus 로고
    • The Pure Theory of Law: Demythologizing Legal Thought
    • See also, ed. The California Law Review (Berkeley: University of California Press
    • See also William Ebenstein, ‘The Pure Theory of Law: Demythologizing Legal Thought’, in Essays in Honor of Hans Kelsen, ed. The California Law Review (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1971), pp. 639–41.
    • (1971) Essays in Honor of Hans Kelsen , pp. 639-641
    • Ebenstein, W.1
  • 14
    • 84998123173 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Science and Politics
    • 355
    • Kelsen, ‘Science and Politics’, pp. 350, 355.
    • Kelsen1
  • 15
    • 0010916706 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. B. L. Paulson and S. L. Paulson (Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • Hans Kelsen, Introduction to the Problems of Legal Theory, trans. B. L. Paulson and S. L. Paulson (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), pp. 56–8;
    • (1992) Introduction to the Problems of Legal Theory , pp. 56-58
    • Kelsen, H.1
  • 19
    • 20844448461 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. O. Beaud and F. Malkani (Paris: PUF
    • Hans Kelsen, Théorie Générale des Normes, trans. O. Beaud and F. Malkani (Paris: PUF, 1996), p. 344.
    • (1996) Théorie Générale des Normes , pp. 344
    • Kelsen, H.1
  • 20
    • 84950138622 scopus 로고
    • Mystery and Mystique in the Basic Norm
    • Julius Stone, ‘Mystery and Mystique in the Basic Norm’, The Modern Law Review 26(1) (1963): 34–59;
    • (1963) The Modern Law Review , vol.26 , Issue.1 , pp. 34-59
    • Stone, J.1
  • 22
    • 84859031314 scopus 로고
    • Kelsen's Theory of the Basic Norm
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • Joseph Raz, ‘Kelsen's Theory of the Basic Norm’, in The Authority of Law: Essays on Law and Morality (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1979), pp. 122–45;
    • (1979) The Authority of Law: Essays on Law and Morality , pp. 122-145
    • Raz, J.1
  • 24
    • 77952809017 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Basic Norm of Society
    • Honoré, ‘The Basic Norm of Society’, pp. 89–112;
    • Honoré1
  • 25
    • 84874254338 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Hypothesis of the Basic Norm: Hans Kelsen and Hermann Cohen
    • Geert Edel, ‘The Hypothesis of the Basic Norm: Hans Kelsen and Hermann Cohen’, in Normativity and Norms, pp. 195–220;
    • Normativity and Norms , pp. 195-220
    • Edel, G.1
  • 26
    • 84874260976 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the Transcendental Import of Kelsen's Basic Norm
    • Gerhard Luf, ‘On the Transcendental Import of Kelsen's Basic Norm’, Normativity and Norms, pp. 221–33.
    • Normativity and Norms , pp. 221-233
    • Luf, G.1
  • 27
    • 84892808054 scopus 로고
    • The Political Element in Legal Theory: a Look at Kelsen's Pure Theory
    • Julius Cohen, ‘The Political Element in Legal Theory: a Look at Kelsen's Pure Theory’, The Yale Law Journal 88(1) (1978): 1–38;
    • (1978) The Yale Law Journal , vol.88 , Issue.1 , pp. 1-38
    • Cohen, J.1
  • 29
    • 84998123173 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Science and Politics
    • Kelsen, ‘Science and Politics’, p. 365.
    • Kelsen1
  • 30
    • 84884083210 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • Frank Michelman, Brennan and Democracy (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1999), p. 48.
    • (1999) Brennan and Democracy , pp. 48
    • Michelman, F.1
  • 34
    • 33645111286 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Foundations of Democracy
    • Hans Kelsen, ‘Foundations of Democracy’, Ethics 66 (1955): 3;
    • (1955) Ethics , vol.66 , pp. 3
    • Kelsen, H.1
  • 35
    • 84998123173 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Science and Politics
    • Kelsen, ‘Science and Politics’, p. 365.
    • Kelsen1
  • 36
    • 84997962464 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Value Judgments in the Science of Law
    • Kelsen, ‘Value Judgments in the Science of Law’, p. 221;
    • Kelsen1
  • 39
    • 0009431341 scopus 로고
    • The Purity of the Pure Theory of Law
    • ed. Richard Tur and William Twining (Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • Joseph Raz, ‘The Purity of the Pure Theory of Law’, in Essays on Kelsen, ed. Richard Tur and William Twining (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), pp. 79–97.
    • (1986) Essays on Kelsen , pp. 79-97
    • Raz, J.1
  • 40
    • 84997916382 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See the renowned chapter, ‘The Law as a Normative Coercive Order; Legal Community and Gang of Robbers’, in, 's
    • See the renowned chapter, ‘The Law as a Normative Coercive Order; Legal Community and Gang of Robbers’, in Kelsen's Pure Theory of Law, pp. 44–50.
    • Pure Theory of Law , pp. 44-50
    • Kelsen1
  • 41
    • 84998123173 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Science and Politics
    • Kelsen, ‘Science and Politics’, p. 364;
    • Kelsen1
  • 43
    • 0042583109 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Vienna: Nachdruck, 104, 338. For an illuminating discussion of the basic norm in Kelsen's early writings, see Paulson's ‘On the Early Development of the Grundnorm’, pp. 217–30
    • Hans Kelsen, Allgemeine Staatslehre (Vienna: Nachdruck, 1993), pp. 99, 104, 338. For an illuminating discussion of the basic norm in Kelsen's early writings, see Paulson's ‘On the Early Development of the Grundnorm’, pp. 217–30.
    • (1993) Allgemeine Staatslehre , pp. 99
    • Kelsen, H.1
  • 44
    • 84997967073 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the Basic Norm
    • Kelsen, ‘On the Basic Norm’, p. 109.
    • Kelsen1
  • 50
    • 0041581028 scopus 로고
    • The Neo-Kantian Dimension of Kelsen's Pure Theory of Law
    • See, Autumn
    • See Stanley L. Paulson, ‘The Neo-Kantian Dimension of Kelsen's Pure Theory of Law’, Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 12(3) (Autumn 1992): 324–8.
    • (1992) Oxford Journal of Legal Studies , vol.12 , Issue.3 , pp. 324-328
    • Paulson, S.L.1
  • 51
    • 84874257842 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Neo-Kantian Theory of Legal Knowledge in Kelsen's Pure Theory of Law?
    • For a different approach, see
    • For a different approach, see Stefan Hammer, ‘A Neo-Kantian Theory of Legal Knowledge in Kelsen's Pure Theory of Law?’, in Normativity and Norms, pp. 177–94.
    • Normativity and Norms , pp. 177-194
    • Hammer, S.1
  • 52
    • 84998123173 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Science and Politics
    • Kelsen, ‘Science and Politics’, p. 364.
    • Kelsen1
  • 53
    • 0004220262 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • H. L. A. Hart, The Concept of Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1961), p. 245.
    • (1961) The Concept of Law , pp. 245
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 55
    • 84998123173 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Science and Politics
    • Kelsen, ‘Science and Politics’, pp. 359–60;
    • Kelsen1
  • 60
    • 84997962464 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Value Judgments in the Science of Law
    • Kelsen, ‘Value Judgments in the Science of Law’, p. 223;
    • Kelsen1
  • 65
    • 84997967073 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the Basic Norm
    • Kelsen, ‘On the Basic Norm’, p. 108.
    • Kelsen1
  • 68
    • 0004273060 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Harmondsworth, Mx and New York: Penguin Books
    • Hannah Arendt, On Revolution (Harmondsworth, Mx and New York: Penguin Books, 1963), pp. 183–4.
    • (1963) On Revolution , pp. 183-184
    • Arendt, H.1
  • 69
    • 84952401799 scopus 로고
    • Declarations of Independence
    • For a similar point, see
    • For a similar point, see Jacques Derrida, ‘Declarations of Independence’, New Political Science 15 (1986): 7–15.
    • (1986) New Political Science , vol.15 , pp. 7-15
    • Derrida, J.1
  • 70
    • 0003983498 scopus 로고
    • For an insightful comparative discussion of Arendt and Derrida related to the perplexities of foundations, see, Ithaca, NY and London: Cornell University Press
    • For an insightful comparative discussion of Arendt and Derrida related to the perplexities of foundations, see Bonnie Honig, Political Theory and the Displacement of Politics (Ithaca, NY and London: Cornell University Press, 1993), pp. 86–109.
    • (1993) Political Theory and the Displacement of Politics , pp. 86-109
    • Honig, B.1
  • 71
    • 0002404574 scopus 로고
    • The Force of Law: The “Mystical Foundations of Authority”
    • ed. Drucilla Cornell, Michel Rosenfeld, and David Gray Carlson (New York and London: Routledge
    • Jacques Derrida, ‘The Force of Law: The “Mystical Foundations of Authority”’, in Deconstruction and the Possibility of Justice, ed. Drucilla Cornell, Michel Rosenfeld, and David Gray Carlson (New York and London: Routledge, 1992), p. 6.
    • (1992) Deconstruction and the Possibility of Justice , pp. 6
    • Derrida, J.1
  • 72
    • 79954241269 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Trial of (Post) Modernity or the Tale of the Two Revolutions
    • As Arendt perceptively put it in her discussion of the French Revolution, the ‘authority … of the new power, the pouvoir constitué … could not be guaranteed by the Constituent Assembly, the pouvoir constituant, because the power of the Assembly itself was not constitutional and could never be constitutional since it was prior to the constitution itself’; Arendt, On Revolution, p. 163. For a detailed discussion of this problem, set against Derrida's and Honig's versions of the perplexities of foundations, see, ed. Larry May and Jerome Kohl (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
    • As Arendt perceptively put it in her discussion of the French Revolution, the ‘authority … of the new power, the pouvoir constitué … could not be guaranteed by the Constituent Assembly, the pouvoir constituant, because the power of the Assembly itself was not constitutional and could never be constitutional since it was prior to the constitution itself’; Arendt, On Revolution, p. 163. For a detailed discussion of this problem, set against Derrida's and Honig's versions of the perplexities of foundations, see David Ingram, ‘Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Trial of (Post) Modernity or the Tale of the Two Revolutions’, in Hannah Arendt: Twenty Years Later, ed. Larry May and Jerome Kohl (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996): 221–50.
    • (1996) Hannah Arendt: Twenty Years Later , pp. 221-250
    • Ingram, D.1
  • 73
    • 84903912284 scopus 로고
    • Collective Identity and Constitutional Power
    • For an exposition of the constituent paradox, see, Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press
    • For an exposition of the constituent paradox, see Sheldon S. Wolin, ‘Collective Identity and Constitutional Power’, in The Presence of the Past (Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1989), pp. 12–13;
    • (1989) The Presence of the Past , pp. 12-13
    • Wolin, S.S.1
  • 74
    • 0007316099 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Constitutional Authorship
    • ed. Larry Alexander (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Frank Michelman, ‘Constitutional Authorship’, in Constitutionalism: Philosophical Foundations, ed. Larry Alexander (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), p. 77.
    • (1998) Constitutionalism: Philosophical Foundations , pp. 77
    • Michelman, F.1
  • 78
    • 84874254338 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Hypothesis of the Basic Norm
    • Edel, ‘The Hypothesis of the Basic Norm’, p. 217.
    • Edel1
  • 79
    • 84972442680 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In a mode, highly reminiscent of a realist approach, Kelsen argued that ‘every legal order which has the degree of effectiveness necessary to make it positive is more or less a compromise between conflicting interest-groups in their struggle for power, in their antagonistic tendencies to determine the content of the social order. This struggle for power invariably presents itself as a struggle for “justice”; all the fighting groups use the ideology of “natural law.” They never represent the interests that they seek to realize as mere group-interests, but as the “true,” the “common,” the “general” interest. The result of this struggle determines the temporary content of the legal order’;, 117
    • In a mode, highly reminiscent of a realist approach, Kelsen argued that ‘every legal order which has the degree of effectiveness necessary to make it positive is more or less a compromise between conflicting interest-groups in their struggle for power, in their antagonistic tendencies to determine the content of the social order. This struggle for power invariably presents itself as a struggle for “justice”; all the fighting groups use the ideology of “natural law.” They never represent the interests that they seek to realize as mere group-interests, but as the “true,” the “common,” the “general” interest. The result of this struggle determines the temporary content of the legal order’; Kelsen, General Theory of Law and State, pp. 438–9, 117.
    • General Theory of Law and State , pp. 438-439
    • Kelsen1
  • 85
    • 84969833143 scopus 로고
    • Die Krise der Staatslehre
    • As early as 1926, Herman Heller had charged Kelsen with reintroducing facticity into legal theory from the back door and within the concept of the basic norm. See, ed. Fritz Borinski, Martin Drath, Gerhart Niemeyer, and Otto Stammer (Tübingen: J. C. B. Mohr, 24. Two years later, Carl Schmitt repeated this criticism, by arguing that Kelsen's supposed derivation of the validity of the legal system from the Grundnorm was a ‘tautology of raw factuality’
    • As early as 1926, Herman Heller had charged Kelsen with reintroducing facticity into legal theory from the back door and within the concept of the basic norm. See Herman Heller, ‘Die Krise der Staatslehre’, in Gesammelte Schrifften, ed. Fritz Borinski, Martin Drath, Gerhart Niemeyer, and Otto Stammer (Tübingen: J. C. B. Mohr, 1992), pp. 23, 24. Two years later, Carl Schmitt repeated this criticism, by arguing that Kelsen's supposed derivation of the validity of the legal system from the Grundnorm was a ‘tautology of raw factuality’;
    • (1992) Gesammelte Schrifften , pp. 23
    • Heller, H.1
  • 86
    • 0004260663 scopus 로고
    • Berlin: Duncker und Humblot
    • C. Schmitt, Verfassungslehre 1928 (Berlin: Duncker und Humblot, 1928), pp. 8–9.
    • (1928) Verfassungslehre 1928 , pp. 8-9
    • Schmitt, C.1
  • 87
    • 84966963965 scopus 로고
    • Franz Neumann, almost two decades later, criticized Kelsen's pure theory of law as nihilistic and decisionistic; see, New York: Harper Torchbooks
    • Franz Neumann, almost two decades later, criticized Kelsen's pure theory of law as nihilistic and decisionistic; see Franz Neumann, Behemoth: The Structure and Practice of National-Socialism: 1933–1944 (New York: Harper Torchbooks, 1944), pp. 46–7.
    • (1944) Behemoth: The Structure and Practice of National-Socialism: 1933–1944 , pp. 46-47
    • Neumann, F.1
  • 88
    • 0004161626 scopus 로고
    • Also see, Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press
    • Also see Friedrich A. Hayek, The Constitution of Liberty (Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press, 1978), p. 238
    • (1978) The Constitution of Liberty , pp. 238
    • Hayek, F.A.1
  • 89
    • 0003701935 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and, London: Routledge, 47, 48–56
    • and Friedrich A. Hayek, Law, Legislation, and Liberty (London: Routledge, 1998), pp. 45, 47, 48–56;
    • (1998) Law, Legislation, and Liberty , pp. 45
    • Hayek, F.A.1
  • 90
    • 0000842517 scopus 로고
    • Positivism and Fidelity to Law — a Reply to Professor Hart
    • Lon L. Fuller, ‘Positivism and Fidelity to Law — a Reply to Professor Hart’, Harvard Law Review 71(4) (1958): 658–61;
    • (1958) Harvard Law Review , vol.71 , Issue.4 , pp. 658-661
    • Fuller, L.L.1
  • 91
    • 0003561004 scopus 로고
    • Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press
    • Norberto Bobbio, Democracy and Dictatorship (Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press, 1989), pp. 86–8
    • (1989) Democracy and Dictatorship , pp. 86-88
    • Bobbio, N.1
  • 92
    • 84925124126 scopus 로고
    • Kelsen et les sources du droit
    • Norberto Bobbio, ‘Kelsen et les sources du droit’, Archives de philosophie du droit 27 (1982): 135–45
    • (1982) Archives de philosophie du droit , vol.27 , pp. 135-145
    • Bobbio, N.1
  • 93
    • 80051684209 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and, Paris: Bruylant LGDJ
    • and Norberto Bobbio, Essais de théorie du droit (Paris: Bruylant LGDJ, 1998), pp. 185–283;
    • (1998) Essais de théorie du droit , pp. 185-283
    • Bobbio, N.1
  • 94
    • 84951307820 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Validity and the Basic Norm
    • Hughes, ‘Validity and the Basic Norm’;
    • Hughes1
  • 96
    • 34249771612 scopus 로고
    • Lon Fuller, Gustav, Radbruch, and the “Positivist Thesis”
    • For an informed presentation of this debate, see
    • For an informed presentation of this debate, see Stanley L. Paulson, ‘Lon Fuller, Gustav, Radbruch, and the “Positivist Thesis”’, Law and Philosophy 13 (1994): 313–59.
    • (1994) Law and Philosophy , vol.13 , pp. 313-359
    • Paulson, S.L.1
  • 97
    • 0003576528 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This criticism of Kelsen's legal positivism has also been more recently reiterated by Habermas in, trans. W. Rehg (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
    • This criticism of Kelsen's legal positivism has also been more recently reiterated by Habermas in Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy, trans. W. Rehg (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996), p. 87.
    • (1996) Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy , pp. 87
  • 98
    • 0009456819 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For this point, see, New York and Oxford: Rowman & Littlefield
    • For this point, see Andrew Arato, Civil Society, Constitution, and Legitimacy (New York and Oxford: Rowman & Littlefield, 2000), pp. 229–30.
    • (2000) Civil Society, Constitution, and Legitimacy , pp. 229-230
    • Arato, A.1
  • 102
    • 0003725960 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This distinction between autonomous and heteronomous lawmaking informs Kelsen's procedural definition of democracy as a method, 2nd edn (Tübingen: J. C. B. Mohr
    • This distinction between autonomous and heteronomous lawmaking informs Kelsen's procedural definition of democracy as a method. Hans Kelsen, Vom Wesen und Wert der Democratie, 2nd edn (Tübingen: J. C. B. Mohr, 1929), pp. 79–81;
    • (1929) Vom Wesen und Wert der Democratie , pp. 79-81
    • Kelsen, H.1
  • 103
    • 33645111286 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Foundations of Democracy
    • Kelsen, ‘Foundations of Democracy’, pp. 3–4.
    • Kelsen1
  • 105
    • 33645111286 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Foundations of Democracy
    • Kelsen, ‘Foundations of Democracy’, pp. 26–33.
    • Kelsen1
  • 108
    • 0040546181 scopus 로고
    • Neo-Federalism?
    • I take the distinction between ‘higher’ and ‘normal’ lawmaking from Bruce Ackerman. See, ed. Jon Elster and Rune Slagstad (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • I take the distinction between ‘higher’ and ‘normal’ lawmaking from Bruce Ackerman. See Bruce Ackerman, ‘Neo-Federalism?’, in Constitutionalism and Democracy, ed. Jon Elster and Rune Slagstad (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988);
    • (1988) Constitutionalism and Democracy
    • Ackerman, B.1
  • 109
    • 70350510907 scopus 로고
    • Constitutional Politics/Constitutional Law
    • Bruce Ackerman, ‘Constitutional Politics/Constitutional Law’, Yale Law Journal 99 (1989): pp. 453–546;
    • (1989) Yale Law Journal , vol.99 , pp. 453-546
    • Ackerman, B.1
  • 115
    • 0042583012 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kelsen's Theory of the Basic Norm
    • Raz, ‘Kelsen's Theory of the Basic Norm’, pp. 125–6.
    • Raz1
  • 119
    • 84997984761 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Law, State, and Justice in the Pure Theory of Law
    • Kelsen denounced the notion of consent based on a founding constituting contract as ‘one of the worst legal fictions invented by Roman jurists’. Instead, he claims that the recognition of the basic norm by objective, impartial, scientific profession of legal scientists is a more promising way to address the validity of constitutional foundations
    • Kelsen denounced the notion of consent based on a founding constituting contract as ‘one of the worst legal fictions invented by Roman jurists’. Instead, he claims that the recognition of the basic norm by objective, impartial, scientific profession of legal scientists is a more promising way to address the validity of constitutional foundations. Kelsen, ‘Law, State, and Justice in the Pure Theory of Law’, p. 291.
    • Kelsen1
  • 121
    • 33645111286 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Foundations of Democracy
    • Kelsen, ‘Foundations of Democracy’, p. 22.
    • Kelsen1
  • 122
    • 84976184916 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Why Should the Law be Obeyed?
    • Kelsen, ‘Why Should the Law be Obeyed?’, p. 262.
    • Kelsen1
  • 123
    • 0042583012 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kelsen's Theory of the Basic Norm
    • Also, see Raz for a penetrating critique of Kelsen's reference to a hypothetical legal person, 144–5
    • Also, see Raz for a penetrating critique of Kelsen's reference to a hypothetical legal person; Raz, ‘Kelsen's Theory of the Basic Norm’, pp. 141, 144–5.
    • Raz1
  • 125
    • 84998187853 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • According to Carlos Miguel Herrera, Kelsen understood sovereignty to be a hypothetical concept too, a theoretical construction, which, like the constituent power, was a necessary logical presupposition for a juridical theory of the state. See his chapter ‘La souveraineté du dogme à l'hypothèse’, Paris: Éditions KIMÉ
    • According to Carlos Miguel Herrera, Kelsen understood sovereignty to be a hypothetical concept too, a theoretical construction, which, like the constituent power, was a necessary logical presupposition for a juridical theory of the state. See his chapter ‘La souveraineté du dogme à l'hypothèse’, in Théorie juridique et politique chez Hans Kelsen (Paris: Éditions KIMÉ, 1997), pp. 115–18.
    • (1997) Théorie juridique et politique chez Hans Kelsen , pp. 115-118
  • 127
    • 0042582986 scopus 로고
    • Reichgesetz und Landesgesetz nach österreichischer Verfassung
    • Hans Kelsen, ‘Reichgesetz und Landesgesetz nach österreichischer Verfassung’, Archiv des öffentlichen Rechts 32 (1914): 217.
    • (1914) Archiv des öffentlichen Rechts , vol.32 , pp. 217
    • Kelsen, H.1
  • 129
    • 84997962464 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Value Judgments in the Science of Law
    • Kelsen, ‘Value Judgments in the Science of Law’, p. 224.
    • Kelsen1
  • 139
    • 16244417372 scopus 로고
    • Willing
    • With this argument, she further developed her more theoretical statement that ‘political power … is always limited power and since power and freedom in the sphere of human plurality are in fact synonyms, this means also that political freedom is always limited freedom’, San Diego and New York: a Harvest Book
    • With this argument, she further developed her more theoretical statement that ‘political power … is always limited power and since power and freedom in the sphere of human plurality are in fact synonyms, this means also that political freedom is always limited freedom’. Hannah Arendt, ‘Willing’, in The Life of the Mind (San Diego and New York: a Harvest Book, 1978), p. 201.
    • (1978) The Life of the Mind , pp. 201
    • Arendt, H.1
  • 142
    • 84998156360 scopus 로고
    • Some Questions in Moral Philosophy
    • For the principle of justice, see
    • For the principle of justice, see Hannah Arendt, ‘Some Questions in Moral Philosophy’, Social Research 51(1–2) (1984): 741.
    • (1984) Social Research , vol.51 , Issue.1-2 , pp. 741
    • Arendt, H.1
  • 147
    • 33749119430 scopus 로고
    • As Olivier Beaud has incisively remarked, ‘It is, therefore, possible to analyze the constituent power from a Kelsian point of view. There is, in his eyes, an initial constituent act, founding of norms that invite us to take it into consideration in legal analysis. The originating constituent power, therefore, is not completely absent from Kelsen's œuvre, even if he rejects it.’, Paris: PUF
    • As Olivier Beaud has incisively remarked, ‘It is, therefore, possible to analyze the constituent power from a Kelsian point of view. There is, in his eyes, an initial constituent act, founding of norms that invite us to take it into consideration in legal analysis. The originating constituent power, therefore, is not completely absent from Kelsen's œuvre, even if he rejects it.’ Olivier Beaud, La puissance de l'état (Paris: PUF, 1994), p. 213.
    • (1994) La puissance de l'état , pp. 213
    • Beaud, O.1
  • 148
    • 80051684209 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For the same reason, Stanley Paulson has described these late writings of Kelsen as belonging to a ‘voluntaristic period’ starting in 1960. ‘This late period,’ Paulson rightly argues, ‘is marked by the complete abandonment of the conceptual neo-Kantian apparatus. From now on, the juridical norm is presented as the meaning of an act of the will … In a word, in this late period, Kelsen joins traditional juridical positivism, in the version offered by the thinkers of the “will,” those same thinkers he had fought against for a long time’. For a similar point, see
    • For the same reason, Stanley Paulson has described these late writings of Kelsen as belonging to a ‘voluntaristic period’ starting in 1960. ‘This late period,’ Paulson rightly argues, ‘is marked by the complete abandonment of the conceptual neo-Kantian apparatus. From now on, the juridical norm is presented as the meaning of an act of the will … In a word, in this late period, Kelsen joins traditional juridical positivism, in the version offered by the thinkers of the “will,” those same thinkers he had fought against for a long time’. For a similar point, see Bobbio, Essais de théorie du droit, p. 236;
    • Essais de théorie du droit , pp. 236
    • Bobbio1
  • 151
    • 85044802986 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Popular Sovereignty, Democracy, and the Constituent Power
    • I discuss the constituent power in more details, June
    • I discuss the constituent power in more details, in ‘Popular Sovereignty, Democracy, and the Constituent Power’, Constellations 12(2) (June 2005): 223–44.
    • (2005) Constellations , vol.12 , Issue.2 , pp. 223-244
  • 152
    • 61449088266 scopus 로고
    • Metaphysical Naturalism, Semantic Normativity, and Meta-Semantic Irrealism
    • For the notion of semantic normativity, see, ed. Enrique Villanueva (Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Publishing)
    • For the notion of semantic normativity, see Terry Horgan and Mark Timmons, ‘Metaphysical Naturalism, Semantic Normativity, and Meta-Semantic Irrealism’, in Naturalism and Normativity, ed. Enrique Villanueva (Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Publishing, 1993), pp. 180–204.
    • (1993) Naturalism and Normativity , pp. 180-204
    • Horgan, T.1    Timmons, M.2
  • 157
    • 84997950250 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Speech in the Federal Convention on Suffrage
    • New York: Library of America
    • James Madison, ‘Speech in the Federal Convention on Suffrage’, in Writings (New York: Library of America, 1999), p. 133.
    • (1999) Writings , pp. 133
    • Madison, J.1
  • 159
    • 84997962464 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Value Judgments in the Science of Law
    • Kelsen, ‘Value Judgments in the Science of Law’, p. 210.
    • Kelsen1
  • 160
    • 0003665678 scopus 로고
    • This argument builds on Saul A. Kripke's reasoning developed in, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • This argument builds on Saul A. Kripke's reasoning developed in Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1982), p. 37.
    • (1982) Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language , pp. 37
  • 161
    • 26444500156 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kripke's Sceptical Paradox: Normativeness and Meaning
    • Also, see
    • Also, see Paul Coates, ‘Kripke's Sceptical Paradox: Normativeness and Meaning’, Mind, new series 95 (1996): 77–80;
    • (1996) Mind, new series , vol.95 , pp. 77-80
    • Coates, P.1
  • 162
    • 60949254152 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kripke's Normativity Argument
    • J. L. Zalabardo, ‘Kripke's Normativity Argument’, Canadian Journal of Philosophy 27(4) (1997): 467–88.
    • (1997) Canadian Journal of Philosophy , vol.27 , Issue.4 , pp. 467-488
    • Zalabardo, J.L.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.