메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 32, Issue 4, 2004, Pages 519-546

Pity's pathologies portrayed: Rrousseau and the limits of democratic compassion

Author keywords

Compassion; Democratic theory; Difference; Identity; Jean Jacques Rousseau; Pity

Indexed keywords


EID: 4043051518     PISSN: 00905917     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1177/0090591703258118     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (50)

References (102)
  • 1
    • 0004027519 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • Judith Shklar, Ordinary Vices (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1984).
    • (1984) Ordinary Vices
    • Shklar, J.1
  • 2
    • 4043157806 scopus 로고
    • ed. J. P. Mayer (New York: Harper)
    • Alexis de Tocqueville, Democracy in America, ed. J. P. Mayer (New York: Harper, 1988), vol. 2, pt. 3, 564. This generalized compassion perhaps stems, as Tracy Strong argues, from the kind of equality and transparency that democracies alone permit. Tracy Strong, Jean-Jacques Rousseau and the Politics of the Ordinary (Thousand Osks,CA.: Sage, 1994), 145-46.
    • (1988) Democracy in America , vol.2 , Issue.PART. 3 , pp. 564
    • De Tocqueville, A.1
  • 3
    • 0003760429 scopus 로고
    • Thousand Osks,CA.: Sage
    • Alexis de Tocqueville, Democracy in America, ed. J. P. Mayer (New York: Harper, 1988), vol. 2, pt. 3, 564. This generalized compassion perhaps stems, as Tracy Strong argues, from the kind of equality and transparency that democracies alone permit. Tracy Strong, Jean-Jacques Rousseau and the Politics of the Ordinary (Thousand Osks,CA.: Sage, 1994), 145-46.
    • (1994) Jean-Jacques Rousseau and the Politics of the Ordinary , pp. 145-146
    • Strong, T.1
  • 4
    • 0003174447 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nietzsche's complaints about modern compassion are complex. Most conspicuous is his contempt for pity as a "sickness" or "nausea" endemic to democratic society. Friedrich Nietzsche, Genealogy of Morals, esp. "Preface," 5-6; III, 14. But he also alludes to a kind of noble or aristocratic "mercy," borne of the pathos of distance and the "consciousness of power," as a fitting attitude of the powerful toward the weak or "parasites" beneath them. Nietzsche, Genealogy, II, 10. Cf. Beyond Good and Evil, V, 201-2; VII, 225.
    • Genealogy , vol.2 , pp. 10
    • Nietzsche1
  • 5
    • 4043075672 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nietzsche's complaints about modern compassion are complex. Most conspicuous is his contempt for pity as a "sickness" or "nausea" endemic to democratic society. Friedrich Nietzsche, Genealogy of Morals, esp. "Preface," 5-6; III, 14. But he also alludes to a kind of noble or aristocratic "mercy," borne of the pathos of distance and the "consciousness of power," as a fitting attitude of the powerful toward the weak or "parasites" beneath them. Nietzsche, Genealogy, II, 10. Cf. Beyond Good and Evil, V, 201-2; VII, 225.
    • Beyond Good and Evil , vol.5 , pp. 201-202
  • 6
    • 4043115627 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nietzsche's complaints about modern compassion are complex. Most conspicuous is his contempt for pity as a "sickness" or "nausea" endemic to democratic society. Friedrich Nietzsche, Genealogy of Morals, esp. "Preface," 5-6; III, 14. But he also alludes to a kind of noble or aristocratic "mercy," borne of the pathos of distance and the "consciousness of power," as a fitting attitude of the powerful toward the weak or "parasites" beneath them. Nietzsche, Genealogy, II, 10. Cf. Beyond Good and Evil, V, 201-2; VII, 225.
    • Beyond Good and Evil , vol.7 , pp. 225
  • 7
    • 0003776036 scopus 로고
    • New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press
    • Carl Schmitt, The Concept of the Political (New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press, 1976), esp. pp. 28-29, 35-37, 54, 68.
    • (1976) The Concept of the Political , pp. 28-29
    • Schmitt, C.1
  • 8
    • 4043072831 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On this latter point about how, notwithstanding their veneer of compassion, modern democracies may still vent their cruelty upon those who are outside or alien, see Nietzsche, Genealogy of Morals, I, 11, p. 40: the same men who are held so sternly in check inter pares ... and who on the other hand in their relations with one another show themselves so resourceful in consideration, self-control, delicacy, loyalty, pride, and friendship - once they go outside, where the strange, the stranger is found, they are not much better than uncaged beasts of prey.
    • Genealogy of Morals , vol.1 , Issue.11 , pp. 40
    • Nietzsche1
  • 9
    • 4043082797 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sympathy, empathy and obligation
    • ed. Anne Jaap Jacobson (University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press)
    • Nancy Hirschman, "Sympathy, Empathy and Obligation," in Feminist Interpretations of David Hume, ed. Anne Jaap Jacobson (University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 2000), 174.
    • (2000) Feminist Interpretations of David Hume , pp. 174
    • Hirschman, N.1
  • 10
    • 0013510969 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Citizenship and national identity
    • Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
    • Jürgen Habermas, "Citizenship and National Identity," in Between Facts and Norms (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996); Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement (Cambridge, MA: Belknap, 1996); Benjamin Barber, Strong Democracy: Participatory Politics for a New Age (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984). For a treatment of the more general problem of "affect" in democratic theory, which raises questions about this characterization of Habermas and problematizes the strict antinomy between reason and affect, see Patchen Markell, "Making Affect Safe for Democracy?" Political Theory 28 (2000): 38-63.
    • (1996) Between Facts and Norms
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 11
    • 0004294588 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Belknap
    • Jürgen Habermas, "Citizenship and National Identity," in Between Facts and Norms (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996); Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement (Cambridge, MA: Belknap, 1996); Benjamin Barber, Strong Democracy: Participatory Politics for a New Age (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984). For a treatment of the more general problem of "affect" in democratic theory, which raises questions about this characterization of Habermas and problematizes the strict antinomy between reason and affect, see Patchen Markell, "Making Affect Safe for Democracy?" Political Theory 28 (2000): 38-63.
    • (1996) Democracy and Disagreement
    • Gutmann, A.1    Thompson, D.2
  • 12
    • 84936526619 scopus 로고
    • Berkeley: University of California Press
    • Jürgen Habermas, "Citizenship and National Identity," in Between Facts and Norms (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996); Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement (Cambridge, MA: Belknap, 1996); Benjamin Barber, Strong Democracy: Participatory Politics for a New Age (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984). For a treatment of the more general problem of "affect" in democratic theory, which raises questions about this characterization of Habermas and problematizes the strict antinomy between reason and affect, see Patchen Markell, "Making Affect Safe for Democracy?" Political Theory 28 (2000): 38-63.
    • (1984) Strong Democracy: Participatory Politics for A New Age
    • Barber, B.1
  • 13
    • 0034407486 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Making affect safe for democracy?
    • Jürgen Habermas, "Citizenship and National Identity," in Between Facts and Norms (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996); Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement (Cambridge, MA: Belknap, 1996); Benjamin Barber, Strong Democracy: Participatory Politics for a New Age (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984). For a treatment of the more general problem of "affect" in democratic theory, which raises questions about this characterization of Habermas and problematizes the strict antinomy between reason and affect, see Patchen Markell, "Making Affect Safe for Democracy?" Political Theory 28 (2000): 38-63.
    • (2000) Political Theory , vol.28 , pp. 38-63
    • Markell, P.1
  • 14
    • 0004108379 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • Notably, Carol Gilligan, In a Different Voice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1982); Joan Tronto, Moral Boundaries: A Political Argument for an Ethic of Care (New York: Routledge, 1993). This case has been recently made in similar terms but without reference to Rousseau by Maureen Whitebrook, "Compassion as a Political Virtue," Political Studies 50 (2002): 529-44.
    • (1982) In A Different Voice
    • Gilligan, C.1
  • 15
    • 0003515047 scopus 로고
    • New York: Routledge
    • Notably, Carol Gilligan, In a Different Voice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1982); Joan Tronto, Moral Boundaries: A Political Argument for an Ethic of Care (New York: Routledge, 1993). This case has been recently made in similar terms but without reference to Rousseau by Maureen Whitebrook, "Compassion as a Political Virtue," Political Studies 50 (2002): 529-44.
    • (1993) Moral Boundaries: A Political Argument for An Ethic of Care
    • Tronto, J.1
  • 16
    • 0036702751 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Compassion as a political virtue
    • Notably, Carol Gilligan, In a Different Voice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1982); Joan Tronto, Moral Boundaries: A Political Argument for an Ethic of Care (New York: Routledge, 1993). This case has been recently made in similar terms but without reference to Rousseau by Maureen Whitebrook, "Compassion as a Political Virtue," Political Studies 50 (2002): 529-44.
    • (2002) Political Studies , vol.50 , pp. 529-544
    • Whitebrook, M.1
  • 19
    • 30244466808 scopus 로고
    • Introduction
    • ed. and trans. Allan Bloom (New York: Basic Books)
    • Consider, for example, the widely differing interpretations that make Rousseau into the apostle of compassion: Allan Bloom, "Introduction," in Emile, or On Education, ed. and trans. Allan Bloom (New York: Basic Books, 1979), 17-20. Or, as Leo Strauss puts it, "Compassion is the passion from which all social virtues derive." Natural Right and History (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1953), 270; and those others who read Rousseau as the harbinger of contemporary democratic theory, James Miller, Rousseau: Dreamer of Democracy (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1984).
    • (1979) Emile, or on Education , pp. 17-20
    • Bloom, A.1
  • 20
    • 4043177753 scopus 로고
    • Compassion is the passion from which all social virtues derive
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • Consider, for example, the widely differing interpretations that make Rousseau into the apostle of compassion: Allan Bloom, "Introduction," in Emile, or On Education, ed. and trans. Allan Bloom (New York: Basic Books, 1979), 17-20. Or, as Leo Strauss puts it, "Compassion is the passion from which all social virtues derive." Natural Right and History (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1953), 270; and those others who read Rousseau as the harbinger of contemporary democratic theory, James Miller, Rousseau: Dreamer of Democracy (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1984).
    • (1953) Natural Right and History , pp. 270
    • Strauss, L.1
  • 21
    • 84883910068 scopus 로고
    • New Haven, CT: Yale University Press
    • Consider, for example, the widely differing interpretations that make Rousseau into the apostle of compassion: Allan Bloom, "Introduction," in Emile, or On Education, ed. and trans. Allan Bloom (New York: Basic Books, 1979), 17-20. Or, as Leo Strauss puts it, "Compassion is the passion from which all social virtues derive." Natural Right and History (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1953), 270; and those others who read Rousseau as the harbinger of contemporary democratic theory, James Miller, Rousseau: Dreamer of Democracy (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1984).
    • (1984) Rousseau: Dreamer of Democracy
    • Miller, J.1
  • 22
    • 0003687723 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On natural freedom, wholeness, and goodness as Rousseau's intended goals, see Strauss, Natural Right and History, 277-83. For a contrary view of the naturalness of human dependency, see Joel Schwartz, The Sexual Politics of Jean-Jacques Rousseau (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984).
    • Natural Right and History , pp. 277-283
    • Strauss1
  • 23
    • 0003428311 scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • On natural freedom, wholeness, and goodness as Rousseau's intended goals, see Strauss, Natural Right and History, 277-83. For a contrary view of the naturalness of human dependency, see Joel Schwartz, The Sexual Politics of Jean-Jacques Rousseau (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984).
    • (1984) The Sexual Politics of Jean-Jacques Rousseau
    • Schwartz, J.1
  • 24
    • 0004036086 scopus 로고
    • Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, esp. chaps. 2 and 3
    • On thinking of liberal democracy as distinguished not by any particular set of political institutions but in terms of its commitment to these procedures and the intrinsic value of moral equality, see George Kateb, The Inner Ocean: Individualism and Democratic Culture (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1992), esp. chaps. 2 and 3; on willfulness and individual agency as essential to a liberal democracy, see Richard Flathman, Willful Liberalism: Voluntarism and Individualism in Political Theory and Practice (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1992); as essential for a strong democracy, see Barber, Strong Democracy, chap. 6.
    • (1992) The Inner Ocean: Individualism and Democratic Culture
    • Kateb, G.1
  • 25
    • 0003577995 scopus 로고
    • Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press
    • On thinking of liberal democracy as distinguished not by any particular set of political institutions but in terms of its commitment to these procedures and the intrinsic value of moral equality, see George Kateb, The Inner Ocean: Individualism and Democratic Culture (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1992), esp. chaps. 2 and 3; on willfulness and individual agency as essential to a liberal democracy, see Richard Flathman, Willful Liberalism: Voluntarism and Individualism in Political Theory and Practice (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1992); as essential for a strong democracy, see Barber, Strong Democracy, chap. 6.
    • (1992) Willful Liberalism: Voluntarism and Individualism in Political Theory and Practice
    • Flathman, R.1
  • 26
    • 0004185568 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 6
    • On thinking of liberal democracy as distinguished not by any particular set of political institutions but in terms of its commitment to these procedures and the intrinsic value of moral equality, see George Kateb, The Inner Ocean: Individualism and Democratic Culture (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1992), esp. chaps. 2 and 3; on willfulness and individual agency as essential to a liberal democracy, see Richard Flathman, Willful Liberalism: Voluntarism and Individualism in Political Theory and Practice (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1992); as essential for a strong democracy, see Barber, Strong Democracy, chap. 6.
    • Strong Democracy
    • Barber1
  • 28
    • 0004063810 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press
    • William Connolly, Why I Am Not a Secularist (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1999), 144-45.
    • (1999) Why I Am Not A Secularist , pp. 144-145
    • Connolly, W.1
  • 29
    • 4043133847 scopus 로고
    • ed. Roger Masters (New York: St. Martin's)
    • Unless otherwise noted, citations from Rousseau are to The First and Second Discourses, ed. Roger Masters (New York: St. Martin's, 1964); On the Social Contract, ed. Roger Masters and trans. Judith R. Masters (New York: St. Martin's, 1978); Emile, or On Education, ed. and trans. Allan Bloom (New York: Basic Books, 1979); The Reveries of the Solitary Walker, ed., trans., and with an introduction by Charles Butterworth (New York: New York University Press, 1979); and Politics and the Arts: Letter to M. D'Alembert on the Theatre (Glencoe, IL: Free Press, 1960).
    • (1964) The First and Second Discourses
    • Rousseau1
  • 30
    • 0004292368 scopus 로고
    • trans. Judith R. Masters (New York: St. Martin's)
    • Unless otherwise noted, citations from Rousseau are to The First and Second Discourses, ed. Roger Masters (New York: St. Martin's, 1964); On the Social Contract, ed. Roger Masters and trans. Judith R. Masters (New York: St. Martin's, 1978); Emile, or On Education, ed. and trans. Allan Bloom (New York: Basic Books, 1979); The Reveries of the Solitary Walker, ed., trans., and with an introduction by Charles Butterworth (New York: New York University Press, 1979); and Politics and the Arts: Letter to M. D'Alembert on the Theatre (Glencoe, IL: Free Press, 1960).
    • (1978) On the Social Contract
    • Masters, R.1
  • 31
    • 0004327677 scopus 로고
    • New York: Basic Books
    • Unless otherwise noted, citations from Rousseau are to The First and Second Discourses, ed. Roger Masters (New York: St. Martin's, 1964); On the Social Contract, ed. Roger Masters and trans. Judith R. Masters (New York: St. Martin's, 1978); Emile, or On Education, ed. and trans. Allan Bloom (New York: Basic Books, 1979); The Reveries of the Solitary Walker, ed., trans., and with an introduction by Charles Butterworth (New York: New York University Press, 1979); and Politics and the Arts: Letter to M. D'Alembert on the Theatre (Glencoe, IL: Free Press, 1960).
    • (1979) Emile, or on Education
    • Bloom, A.1
  • 32
    • 0004228584 scopus 로고
    • New York: New York University Press
    • Unless otherwise noted, citations from Rousseau are to The First and Second Discourses, ed. Roger Masters (New York: St. Martin's, 1964); On the Social Contract, ed. Roger Masters and trans. Judith R. Masters (New York: St. Martin's, 1978); Emile, or On Education, ed. and trans. Allan Bloom (New York: Basic Books, 1979); The Reveries of the Solitary Walker, ed., trans., and with an introduction by Charles Butterworth (New York: New York University Press, 1979); and Politics and the Arts: Letter to M. D'Alembert on the Theatre (Glencoe, IL: Free Press, 1960).
    • (1979) The Reveries of the Solitary Walker
    • Butterworth, C.1
  • 33
    • 0041087447 scopus 로고
    • Glencoe, IL: Free Press
    • Unless otherwise noted, citations from Rousseau are to The First and Second Discourses, ed. Roger Masters (New York: St. Martin's, 1964); On the Social Contract, ed. Roger Masters and trans. Judith R. Masters (New York: St. Martin's, 1978); Emile, or On Education, ed. and trans. Allan Bloom (New York: Basic Books, 1979); The Reveries of the Solitary Walker, ed., trans., and with an introduction by Charles Butterworth (New York: New York University Press, 1979); and Politics and the Arts: Letter to M. D'Alembert on the Theatre (Glencoe, IL: Free Press, 1960).
    • (1960) Politics and the Arts: Letter to M. D'Alembert on the Theatre
  • 34
    • 0013484110 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • For an excellent discussion of how natural pity is activated by the imagination and transformed into compassion, see David Marshall, The Surprising Effects of Sympathy: Marivaux, Diderot, Rousseau, and Mary Shelley (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988), 148-52. See also Jacques Derrida, Of Grammatology (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1997), 182-87.
    • (1988) The Surprising Effects of Sympathy: Marivaux, Diderot, Rousseau, and Mary Shelley , pp. 148-152
    • Marshall, D.1
  • 35
    • 0003905795 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press
    • For an excellent discussion of how natural pity is activated by the imagination and transformed into compassion, see David Marshall, The Surprising Effects of Sympathy: Marivaux, Diderot, Rousseau, and Mary Shelley (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988), 148-52. See also Jacques Derrida, Of Grammatology (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1997), 182-87.
    • (1997) Of Grammatology , pp. 182-187
    • Derrida, J.1
  • 37
    • 4043133845 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rousseau and the discovery of political compassion
    • ed. Clifford Orwin and Nathan Tarcov (Chicago: University of Chicago Press)
    • Clifford Orwin, "Rousseau and the Discovery of Political Compassion," in The Legacy of Rousseau, ed. Clifford Orwin and Nathan Tarcov (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1997), 309.
    • (1997) The Legacy of Rousseau , pp. 309
    • Orwin, C.1
  • 38
    • 60950072014 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press
    • Contrast the reading of Mira Morgenstern, for whom the "sweetness" of pity derives at least in part from the discovery of individual empowerment and independence. Rousseau and the Politics of Ambiguity (University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1996), 65, 68-69.
    • (1996) Rousseau and the Politics of Ambiguity , pp. 65
  • 39
    • 4043162108 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Rousseau's choice of the term "commiseration" is noteworthy. Literally, "sharing the misery of another" - this may be the necessary condition for us to think about acting to relieve that misery, but it is, as we will see below, far from a sufficient condition for this kind of willful human agency.
  • 41
    • 4043088523 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Compare Orwin, "Rousseau and the Discovery," 302, 307-8: "Within the context of Emile, the greatest importance of compassion is not to society but to Emile himself." Cf. John Charvet, The Social Problem in the Philosophy of Rousseau (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1974), who assumes that the purpose of pity is to produce good for others and to serve as the foundation of a new social order (see esp. pp. 83-93).
    • Rousseau and the Discovery , pp. 302
    • Orwin1
  • 42
    • 4043068586 scopus 로고
    • Within the context of Emile, the greatest importance of compassion is not to society but to Emile himself
    • Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press
    • Compare Orwin, "Rousseau and the Discovery," 302, 307-8: "Within the context of Emile, the greatest importance of compassion is not to society but to Emile himself." Cf. John Charvet, The Social Problem in the Philosophy of Rousseau (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1974), who assumes that the purpose of pity is to produce good for others and to serve as the foundation of a new social order (see esp. pp. 83-93).
    • (1974) The Social Problem in the Philosophy of Rousseau , pp. 83-93
    • Charvet, J.1
  • 43
    • 61249408477 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Music, politics, theater and representation
    • ed. Patrick Riley (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press)
    • Compare C. N. Dugan and Tracy Strong, "Music, Politics, Theater and Representation," in The Cambridge Companion to Rousseau, ed. Patrick Riley (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2001), esp. 333, 339, 343.
    • (2001) The Cambridge Companion to Rousseau , pp. 333
    • Dugan, C.N.1    Strong, T.2
  • 46
    • 0040753749 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, esp.
    • Cf. Elizabeth Wingrove, who interestingly suggests that the theater represents not just a suspension of will, but a willing complicity in the crimes of others, Rousseau's Republican Romance (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2000), esp. 175-76; for a more extended discussion of the performative aspect of sympathy in the theater, see Marshall, Surprising Effects of Sympathy, esp. 143-48.
    • (2000) Rousseau's Republican Romance , pp. 175-176
  • 47
    • 0013484110 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • esp.
    • Cf. Elizabeth Wingrove, who interestingly suggests that the theater represents not just a suspension of will, but a willing complicity in the crimes of others, Rousseau's Republican Romance (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2000), esp. 175-76; for a more extended discussion of the performative aspect of sympathy in the theater, see Marshall, Surprising Effects of Sympathy, esp. 143-48.
    • Surprising Effects of Sympathy , pp. 143-148
    • Marshall1
  • 48
    • 43249117925 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rousseau and the case against (and for) the arts
    • esp.
    • Christopher Kelly offers a concise account of Rousseau's ambivalence toward the arts. "Rousseau and the Case against (and for) the Arts," in The Legacy of Rousseau, esp. 20-25.
    • The Legacy of Rousseau , pp. 20-25
  • 49
    • 4043131015 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • There are major scholarly debates about the consistency of Rousseau's account of pity as either an immanent or an active virtue (or both), and my analysis addresses these controversies implicitly. But I am mainly concerned here with the related but distinct question of whether commiseration is ultimately experienced as "sweet" or "irksome."
  • 51
    • 4043138043 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Toronto, Canada: University of Toronto Press
    • Contrast the reading of Margaret Ogrodnick, Instinct and Intimacy: Political Philosophy and Autobiography in Rousseau (Toronto, Canada: University of Toronto Press, 1999), 137. If my point here is correct, virtually all of what Jacques Derrida has written about the "maternal metaphor" for compassion in Rousseau is wrong. There is little textual evidence in Rousseau to suggest that children have a natural affection for their parents that is written into their hearts by God. And in the above-cited passages in the Second Discourse, Rousseau makes it clear that maternal or familial affection, like romantic love, arises only by habit or custom. Cf. Derrida, Of Grammatology, 173-75.
    • (1999) Instinct and Intimacy: Political Philosophy and Autobiography in Rousseau , pp. 137
    • Ogrodnick, M.1
  • 52
    • 0003905795 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Contrast the reading of Margaret Ogrodnick, Instinct and Intimacy: Political Philosophy and Autobiography in Rousseau (Toronto, Canada: University of Toronto Press, 1999), 137. If my point here is correct, virtually all of what Jacques Derrida has written about the "maternal metaphor" for compassion in Rousseau is wrong. There is little textual evidence in Rousseau to suggest that children have a natural affection for their parents that is written into their hearts by God. And in the above-cited passages in the Second Discourse, Rousseau makes it clear that maternal or familial affection, like romantic love, arises only by habit or custom. Cf. Derrida, Of Grammatology, 173-75.
    • Of Grammatology , pp. 173-175
    • Derrida1
  • 53
    • 4043084221 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Here the intensity of the spectator's reaction is rooted in its inability to differentiate itself from other beings
    • Although her subsequent discussion leads in a different direction, this point is supported by the following observation of Elizabeth Wingrove: "Here the intensity of the spectator's reaction is rooted in its inability to differentiate itself from other beings." Rousseau's Republican Romance, 32.
    • Rousseau's Republican Romance , pp. 32
    • Wingrove, E.1
  • 54
    • 84974115097 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Consider also Rousseau's example of the pongos, who take pains to cover the bodies of their dead with branches or leaves so that they don't have to be confronted by its presence. Second Discourse, 205n, 208n.
    • Second Discourse
  • 57
    • 4043050203 scopus 로고
    • ed. C. B. Macpherson (New York: Penguin), chap. 13
    • Hobbes, Leviathan, ed. C. B. Macpherson (New York: Penguin, 1968), chap. 13, pp. 184-85.
    • (1968) Leviathan , pp. 184-185
    • Hobbes1
  • 58
    • 0003836151 scopus 로고
    • trans. Peter Gay (Bloomington: Indiana University Press)
    • Compare Ernst Cassirer, The Question of Jean-Jacques Rousseau, trans. Peter Gay (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1967), 101: According to Rousseau, Hobbes had quite rightly recognized that in the pure state of nature there was no bond of sympathy binding the single individuals to each other. . . . According to Rousseau, the only flaw in Hobbes's psychology consisted in putting an active egoism in the place of the purely passive egoism which prevails in the state of nature. See also Jean Starobinski, Jean-Jacques Rousseau: Transparency and Obstruction, trans. Arthur Goldhammer (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988), 298-99.
    • (1967) The Question of Jean-Jacques Rousseau , pp. 101
    • Cassirer, E.1
  • 59
    • 0003428309 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. Arthur Goldhammer (Chicago: University of Chicago Press)
    • Compare Ernst Cassirer, The Question of Jean-Jacques Rousseau, trans. Peter Gay (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1967), 101: According to Rousseau, Hobbes had quite rightly recognized that in the pure state of nature there was no bond of sympathy binding the single individuals to each other. . . . According to Rousseau, the only flaw in Hobbes's psychology consisted in putting an active egoism in the place of the purely passive egoism which prevails in the state of nature. See also Jean Starobinski, Jean-Jacques Rousseau: Transparency and Obstruction, trans. Arthur Goldhammer (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988), 298-99.
    • (1988) Jean-Jacques Rousseau: Transparency and Obstruction , pp. 298-299
    • Starobinski, J.1
  • 60
    • 0003892378 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, esp.
    • Roger Masters seems to go even further than this in claiming that natural pity is not just "obscure," immanent, or aversive in the state of nature, but entirely nonexistent. Roger Masters, The Political Philosophy of Rousseau (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1968), esp. 140-42.
    • (1968) The Political Philosophy of Rousseau , pp. 140-142
    • Masters, R.1
  • 62
    • 0004040659 scopus 로고
    • New York: Viking
    • Hannah Arendt develops this point more fully, especially Eichmann in Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of Evil (New York: Viking, 1968). The response of Martin Buber, who "felt no pity at all" for Eichmann because he could feel pity only "for those whose actions I can understand in my heart," is suggestive (cited in Eichmann in Jerusalem, 251). In this view, compassion for the guilty entails the recognition both of common humanity and of a similar susceptibility to evil in oneself. Absent any sense that one could have committed a similar crime, or indeed of the mental workings of the criminal, it is impossible to feel pity. Notice that in this view, contrary to Rousseau, it is the comprehensibility of deed itself, rather than our overriding compassion for the doer as a fellow, sensible being, that is determinative. Compare Nietzsche, Genealogy of Morals, II, 10, who notes that the cognitive ability to separate the deed from the doer is what allows modern compassion to come into full bloom.
    • (1968) Eichmann in Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of Evil
  • 63
    • 4043136621 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hannah Arendt develops this point more fully, especially Eichmann in Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of Evil (New York: Viking, 1968). The response of Martin Buber, who "felt no pity at all" for Eichmann because he could feel pity only "for those whose actions I can understand in my heart," is suggestive (cited in Eichmann in Jerusalem, 251). In this view, compassion for the guilty entails the recognition both of common humanity and of a similar susceptibility to evil in oneself. Absent any sense that one could have committed a similar crime, or indeed of the mental workings of the criminal, it is impossible to feel pity. Notice that in this view, contrary to Rousseau, it is the comprehensibility of deed itself, rather than our overriding compassion for the doer as a fellow, sensible being, that is determinative. Compare Nietzsche, Genealogy of Morals, II, 10, who notes that the cognitive ability to separate the deed from the doer is what allows modern compassion to come into full bloom.
    • Genealogy of Morals , vol.2 , pp. 10
    • Nietzsche1
  • 64
    • 0002830983 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Compassion: The basic social emotion
    • Martha Nussbaum has posited specific and helpful criteria under which we might wish to exercise compassion in lieu of justice. "Compassion: The Basic Social Emotion," Social Philosophy and Policy 13 (1996): 27-58. Whitebrook has criticized these general criteria as too restrictive. However, her attempt to incorporate a greater degree of discretion, making compassion into a kind of "default position" not just for those who suffer or even those who deserve compassion, but for anyone who is "vulnerable," would seem to render compassion more open to this charge of its indiscriminacy. Cf. "Compassion as a Political Virtue," esp. 537, 540-42.
    • (1996) Social Philosophy and Policy , vol.13 , pp. 27-58
  • 65
    • 0002830983 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • esp.
    • Martha Nussbaum has posited specific and helpful criteria under which we might wish to exercise compassion in lieu of justice. "Compassion: The Basic Social Emotion," Social Philosophy and Policy 13 (1996): 27-58. Whitebrook has criticized these general criteria as too restrictive. However, her attempt to incorporate a greater degree of discretion, making compassion into a kind of "default position" not just for those who suffer or even those who deserve compassion, but for anyone who is "vulnerable," would seem to render compassion more open to this charge of its indiscriminacy. Cf. "Compassion as a Political Virtue," esp. 537, 540-42.
    • Compassion As A Political Virtue , pp. 537
  • 66
    • 78049311860 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Orwin has similarly described the difficulty of generalizing pity into a universal virtue because of its inherent partiality. "Rousseau and the Discovery," 307-8. Compare Emile, IV, p. 227 , where Rousseau himself raises the distinction between justice and compassion. While presumably one cannot be just without having compassion, simply being compassionate may not be enough to make one just. For a similar point, see Philonenko, Jean-Jacques Rousseau, 187, and the discussion of Derrida, Of Grammatology, 191.
    • Rousseau and the Discovery , pp. 307-308
  • 67
    • 4043050202 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Orwin has similarly described the difficulty of generalizing pity into a universal virtue because of its inherent partiality. "Rousseau and the Discovery," 307-8. Compare Emile, IV, p. 227 , where Rousseau himself raises the distinction between justice and compassion. While presumably one cannot be just without having compassion, simply being compassionate may not be enough to make one just. For a similar point, see Philonenko, Jean-Jacques Rousseau, 187, and the discussion of Derrida, Of Grammatology, 191.
    • Emile , vol.4 , pp. 227
  • 68
    • 4043072830 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Orwin has similarly described the difficulty of generalizing pity into a universal virtue because of its inherent partiality. "Rousseau and the Discovery," 307-8. Compare Emile, IV, p. 227 , where Rousseau himself raises the distinction between justice and compassion. While presumably one cannot be just without having compassion, simply being compassionate may not be enough to make one just. For a similar point, see Philonenko, Jean-Jacques Rousseau, 187, and the discussion of Derrida, Of Grammatology, 191.
    • Jean-Jacques Rousseau , pp. 187
    • Philonenko1
  • 69
    • 0003905795 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Orwin has similarly described the difficulty of generalizing pity into a universal virtue because of its inherent partiality. "Rousseau and the Discovery," 307-8. Compare Emile, IV, p. 227 , where Rousseau himself raises the distinction between justice and compassion. While presumably one cannot be just without having compassion, simply being compassionate may not be enough to make one just. For a similar point, see Philonenko, Jean-Jacques Rousseau, 187, and the discussion of Derrida, Of Grammatology, 191.
    • Of Grammatology , pp. 191
    • Derrida1
  • 70
    • 77951027979 scopus 로고
    • New York: Norton
    • Stendahl, Red and Black (New York: Norton, 1969), 384-89.
    • (1969) Red and Black , pp. 384-389
    • Stendahl1
  • 72
    • 4043058691 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jean-Jacques rousseau and equality
    • ed. Stanley Hoffman (Chicago: University of Chicago Press)
    • Judith Shklar notes many of these same limitations of pity as a political virtue. Judith Shklar, "Jean-Jacques Rousseau and Equality," in Political Thought and Political Thinkers, ed. Stanley Hoffman (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1998), esp. 289.
    • (1998) Political Thought and Political Thinkers , pp. 289
    • Shklar, J.1
  • 75
    • 0003101980 scopus 로고
    • The liberalism of fear
    • ed. Nancy Rosenblum (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)
    • Judith Shklar, "The Liberalism of Fear," in Liberalism and the Moral Life, ed. Nancy Rosenblum (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989).
    • (1989) Liberalism and the Moral Life
    • Shklar, J.1
  • 77
    • 84897341799 scopus 로고
    • New York: St. Martin's
    • Rousseau's ultimate position with respect to the divergent pathways of cosmopolitanism and patriotism is beyond the scope of this essay. But in this context, we should not forget his contempt for those "supposed cosmopolites who, justifying their love of the homeland by means of their love of the human race, boast of loving everyone in order to have the right to love no one." "Geneva Manuscript," ed. Roger Masters (New York: St. Martin's, 1978), 161-62.
    • (1978) Geneva Manuscript , pp. 161-162
    • Masters, R.1
  • 78
    • 0003428309 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Compare Starobinski, Jean-Jacques Rousseau, 286: To accept a gift is to admit one's inferiority; it is to incur an obligation to people whose kindness is a way of signaling social distance while insincerely glossing it over. The equality [Rousseau] wants - the reciprocity of free minds - excludes dependence of any kind, and in the first place the dependence created by the kindness of the benevolent.
    • Jean-Jacques Rousseau , pp. 286
    • Starobinski1
  • 80
    • 84862399410 scopus 로고
    • "On Cruelty," whose natural sensitivity extends even to plants! De Michel Montaigne
    • London: Penguin
    • Cf. Montaigne, "On Cruelty," whose natural sensitivity extends even to plants! Michel de Montaigne, The Complete Essays (London: Penguin, 1991), 488.
    • (1991) The Complete Essays , pp. 488
    • Montaigne1
  • 81
    • 4043150766 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Rousseau's revelation of the self as an ungrounded and perfectible tabula rasa invites dilemmas of difference and recognition unknown to earlier thinkers. Once the self has become in Rousseau's hands nothing more than the "perfectible" reflection of conventional differences and cultural influences, true recognition can take place only under two equally unlikely sets of conditions: either between equals in the pure state of nature or within civil society, when two selves have been forged by an identical set of social influences. With the advent of civil society, the first possibility vanishes forever, and with the continuous process of civilization, the likelihood of the latter diminishes by the day.
  • 82
    • 0003801384 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rousseau looks to be guilty of pursuing what Joan Tronto has criticized as a "morality first" strategy by conceiving of pity as ultimately best confined to private relationships between individuals rather than constitutive of the political bonds between citizens. Tronto, Moral Boundaries, 158.
    • Moral Boundaries , pp. 158
    • Tronto1
  • 83
    • 4043102663 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Here, I have in mind certain "communitarian critics" of liberalism such as Robert Bellah, Amitai Etzioni, Michael Sandel, and Alasdair MacIntyre. Even if they do not explicitly or uniformly call for more compassion (or more democracy!) as a remedy for these ailments of liberalism, they have presented a challenging criticism of the excessive thinness, legalism. neutrality, and sentimental inertness of liberal political theory.
  • 84
    • 4043088523 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • esp.
    • Cf. Orwin, "Rousseau and the Discovery," esp. 298-99; Plattner, Rousseau's State of Nature, 128-32.
    • Rousseau and the discovery , pp. 298-299
    • Orwin1
  • 86
    • 4043166314 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • By reading Rousseau here as a "critic of liberalism" and the primacy of private property, self-interest, and individual rights, I do not mean to suggest that his critique was not also applicable to aristocratic or courtly society.
  • 87
    • 4043145064 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Rousseau's stipulation that the sum of our obligations to our fellow citizens consists in refraining from causing them undue suffering is compatible with even the least flattering criticisms of contemporary liberal society by Bellah, MacIntyre, or Sandel. A market society characterized by self-interest, anomie, and atomization may prove the quintessential example of a world where we take no special pains to be cruel to others. Emphasizing both the thin obligations of fellow citizens to one another and the relative unlikelihood of even these minimal duties being recognized makes Rousseau among the most realistic of political theorists.
  • 88
    • 0007342483 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • esp. 170-71n
    • Cf. Melzer, Natural Goodness of Man, who suggests that an immanent human "expansiveness" to identify with others forms the basis of patriotism, political community, and justice for Rousseau, esp. 170-71n. Compare Ogrodnick, Instinct and Intimacy, 135-38. Below, I raise questions not just about this possibility for Rousseau, but also and more importantly whether even this immanent expansiveness can overcome the problem of moral otherness.
    • Natural Goodness of Man
    • Melzer1
  • 89
    • 4043142222 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Melzer, Natural Goodness of Man, who suggests that an immanent human "expansiveness" to identify with others forms the basis of patriotism, political community, and justice for Rousseau, esp. 170-71n. Compare Ogrodnick, Instinct and Intimacy, 135-38. Below, I raise questions not just about this possibility for Rousseau, but also and more importantly whether even this immanent expansiveness can overcome the problem of moral otherness.
    • Instinct and Intimacy , pp. 135-138
    • Ogrodnick1
  • 90
    • 0001897069 scopus 로고
    • Citizenship and national identity
    • ed. Ron Beiner (Albany: State University of New York Press)
    • Cf. Jürgen Habermas, "Citizenship and National Identity," in Theorizing Citizenship, ed. Ron Beiner (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1995). For a characterization of the particularistic and affective dimensions of Rousseau's thoughts on patriotism, see Marc Plattner, "Rousseau and the Origins of Nationalism," in The Legacy of Rousseau, esp. 187-93.
    • (1995) Theorizing Citizenship
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 91
    • 77954046720 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rousseau and the origins of nationalism
    • esp.
    • Cf. Jürgen Habermas, "Citizenship and National Identity," in Theorizing Citizenship, ed. Ron Beiner (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1995). For a characterization of the particularistic and affective dimensions of Rousseau's thoughts on patriotism, see Marc Plattner, "Rousseau and the Origins of Nationalism," in The Legacy of Rousseau, esp. 187-93.
    • The Legacy of Rousseau , pp. 187-193
    • Plattner, M.1
  • 94
    • 4043135249 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. John T. Scott and Robert D. Zaretsky (University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press)
    • Tzvetan Todorov, Frail Happiness: An Essay on Rousseau, trans. John T. Scott and Robert D. Zaretsky (University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 2001), 29.
    • (2001) Frail Happiness: An Essay on Rousseau , pp. 29
    • Todorov, T.1
  • 95
    • 84971792320 scopus 로고
    • The theodicy of the second discourse: The 'Pure state of nature' and Rousseau's political thought
    • John T. Scott, "The Theodicy of the Second Discourse: The 'Pure State of Nature' and Rousseau's Political Thought," American Political Science Review 86 (1992): 708.
    • (1992) American Political Science Review , vol.86 , pp. 708
    • Scott, J.T.1
  • 98
    • 0004273060 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Penguin Books
    • One problem with doing so is compassion's tendency to eclipse civic equality. See especially Hannah Arendt, On Revolution (New York: Penguin Books, 1977), 90: Measured against the immense sufferings of the immense majority of the people, the impartiality of justice and law, the application of the same rules to those who sleep in palaces and those who sleep under the bridges of Paris, was like a mockery.
    • (1977) On Revolution , pp. 90
    • Arendt, H.1
  • 102
    • 0004185568 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • esp. chaps. 6 and 8
    • Habermas, "Citizenship and National Identity," esp. 503-6; Barber, Strong Democracy, esp. chaps. 6 and 8.
    • Strong Democracy
    • Barber1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.