메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 79, Issue 2-3, 2002, Pages 163-196

Combinatorial predication and the ontology of unit attributes

(1)  Mertz, D W a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 38549174426     PISSN: 00268402     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.5840/schoolman2002792/310     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (9)

References (89)
  • 1
    • 79954849901 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Three is a prime number
    • Moderale Realism and its Logic New Haven: Yale University Press pp. 259ff
    • j, 3,., and is referred to in substantival number sentences such as 'Three is a prime number.'The advantages of this view are given in Mertz, Moderale Realism and its Logic (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1996), pp. 259ff.
    • (1996) The advantages of this view are given in Mertz
  • 2
  • 3
    • 38549123701 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Theories of individuation: A Reconsideration of Bare Particulars
    • James P. Moreland, 'Theories of individuation: A Reconsideration of Bare Particulars,' Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 79 (1998), pp. 251-63,
    • (1998) Pacific Philosophical Quarterly , vol.79 , pp. 251-263
    • Moreland, J.P.1
  • 5
    • 0008706392 scopus 로고
    • Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 277
    • Gustav Bergmann, Logic and Reality (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1964), pp. 133-34, 277.
    • (1964) Logic and Reality , pp. 133-134
    • Bergmann, G.1
  • 6
    • 0742334569 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 113ff
    • In regard to Armstrong, he refers to bare particulars as 'thin particulars.' By this designation he seeks to emphasize his thesis that in extra-conceptual reality there are no particulars without some property attached as an ontic predicate, i.e., there are only states-of-affairs or facts. A thin (bare) particular is a conceptual abstraction from a state-of-affairs, as is the property or relation universal, the only other constituent of a state-of-affairs. Also see Armstrong's Nominalism & Realism: Universals & Scientific Realism, Vol. I (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1978), pp. 113ff.
    • (1978) Nominalism & Realism: Universals & Scientific Realism , vol.1
    • Armstrong1
  • 11
    • 0007042374 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Basil Blackwell
    • Keith Campbell takes this line in Abstract Particulars (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1990), p. 69.
    • (1990) Abstract Particulars , pp. 69
    • Campbell, K.1
  • 12
    • 79954967012 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Adopted here is the relationist over the substantivist view of space. For a justification of this view see Moderate Realism, pp. 39-42. There it is argued that the substantivist view that space(-time) is composed of points(-instances) fails because the latter reduce upon analysis to what would be bare particulars reserved as relata for spatial(-temporal) relations. Apparently these bare point-instances would be the same discrete space-time minima essential to the geometrodynamics conception of real space-time Campbell has advocated, e.g., in 'Unit Properties, Relations, and Spatio-Temporal Naturalism,' this issue. Further, it is instructive to note that Campbell holds space to be real as demonstrated by its property of right-& left-handedness (enantiomorphism) and hence concludes that a Leibnizian relationist conception of space is false, since the latter includes a characteristic foundationism (a view advocated by Campbell himself) claiming the eliminative reduction of relations to properties of their relata. The point I would make is that relationism need not be Leibnizian. The counter-theses advocated here are that foundationism is false, that relations and their instances are fully real and unreducible, and that space(-time) is constituted by instances of space(-time) relations.
    • Moderate Realism , pp. 39-42
  • 14
    • 79954784037 scopus 로고
    • Abstract Particulars
    • D. C. Williams 171-92
    • Campbell, Abstract Particulars, D. C. Williams, Review of Metaphysics 7 (1953), pp. 3-18, 171-92;
    • (1953) Review of Metaphysics , vol.7 , pp. 3-18
    • Campbell1
  • 16
    • 9444247866 scopus 로고
    • Particulars in Particular Clothing: Three Trope Theories of Substance
    • Peter Simons, 'Particulars in Particular Clothing: Three Trope Theories of Substance,' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54 (1994), pp. 553-74,
    • (1994) Philosophy and Phenomenological Research , vol.54 , pp. 553-574
    • Simons, P.1
  • 17
    • 33746116712 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Farewell to Substance: A Differentiated Leave-Taking
    • and 'Farewell to Substance: A Differentiated Leave-Taking,' Ratio 11 (1998), pp. 235-52.
    • (1998) Ratio , vol.11 , pp. 235-252
  • 19
    • 0004066802 scopus 로고
    • New York: Simon and Schuster
    • and Human Knowledge, its Scope and Limits (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1948), pp. 292-308.
    • (1948) Human Knowledge, its Scope and Limits , pp. 292-308
  • 20
    • 38749099361 scopus 로고
    • The Identity of Indiscernibles
    • Michael Loux, 2d. ed, Notre Dame, IN: Notre Dame University Press
    • A. J. Ayer, 'The Identity of Indiscernibles' (1954), in Michael Loux, Universals & Particulars, 2d. ed. (Notre Dame, IN: Notre Dame University Press, 1976), pp. 263-70.
    • (1954) Universals & Particulars , pp. 263-270
    • Ayer, A.J.1
  • 21
    • 15944422098 scopus 로고
    • LaSalle, IL: Open Court
    • Brand Blanshard, Reason and Analysis (LaSalle, IL: Open Court, 1962), pp. 399-401.
    • (1962) Reason and Analysis , pp. 399-401
    • Blanshard, B.1
  • 22
    • 0007042374 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The problem for bundles-of-universals theories is simple: a bundle of universals is itself repeat-able, i.e., universal, and so a bundle theory that admits only universals and bundles thereof cannot account for individuation. Cf. Campbell, Abstract Particulars, p. 19.
    • Abstract Particulars , pp. 19
    • Campbell1
  • 24
    • 84949116004 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Individuation and Instance Ontology
    • Mertz, 'Individuation and Instance Ontology,' Australasian Journal of Philosophy 79 (2001), pp. 45-61.
    • (2001) Australasian Journal of Philosophy , vol.79 , pp. 45-61
    • Mertz1
  • 25
    • 61149563208 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Loux on Particulars: Bare and Concrete
    • These theories do not give an account of individuation, they simply posit a category of entities, substance universals, and assign to them the duty of individuation without explanation how this is possible. How is it that a property numerically identical across a plurality of individuals can, contrary to its repeatable nature, render these instantiating entities unrepeatable? See Alica Rothstein and Nathan Oaklander, 'Loux on Particulars: Bare and Concrete,' The Modern Schoolman, 78 (2000), pp. 97-102.
    • (2000) The Modern Schoolman , vol.78 , pp. 97-102
    • Rothstein, A.1    Oaklander, N.2
  • 26
    • 0003948679 scopus 로고
    • London: Routledge & Kegan Paul
    • Peter Simons, 'Particulars in Particular Clothing' and 'Farewell to Substance.' See Edmund Husserl, Logical Investigations (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1970), p. 478.
    • (1970) Logical Investigations , pp. 478
    • Husserl, E.1
  • 30
    • 0004236558 scopus 로고
    • 13, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, Prop. 1.1; p, Prop. 2.05
    • Ludwig Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1961), p. 7, Prop. 1.1; p. 13, Prop. 2.05.
    • (1961) Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus , pp. 7
    • Wittgenstein, L.1
  • 31
    • 84875299351 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Props. 2.061, 2.062;
    • Wittgenstein, Tractatus, p. 13, Props. 2.061, 2.062;
    • Tractatus , pp. 13
    • Wittgenstein1
  • 33
    • 79954789878 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a critique of Armstrong's independence thesis see my review of his States of Affairs in The Modern Schoolman 75 (1998), pp. 227-31.
    • (1998) The Modern Schoolman , vol.75 , pp. 227-231
  • 34
    • 0040125046 scopus 로고
    • New York: The Free Press also see pp. 27, 73
    • Alfred North Whitehead, Process and Reality (New York: The Free Press, 1978), p. 20, also see pp. 27, 73.
    • (1978) Alfred North Whitehead, Process and Reality , pp. 20
  • 35
    • 0347325954 scopus 로고
    • Stanford, CA: Center for the Study of Language and Information
    • Kenneth Olson, An Essay on Facts (Stanford, CA: Center for the Study of Language and Information, 1987), pp. 60-1.
    • (1987) An Essay on Facts , pp. 60-61
    • Olson, K.1
  • 36
    • 42249095876 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Three Conceptions of States of Affairs
    • WilIiam Vallicella, 'Three Conceptions of States of Affairs,' Nous 34 (2000), pp. 237-259.
    • (2000) Nous , vol.34 , pp. 237-259
    • Vallicella, W.1
  • 38
    • 33748271158 scopus 로고
    • In Defense of Structural Universals
    • Armstrong, 'In Defense of Structural Universals,' Australasian Journal of Philosophy 64 (1986), pp. 85-91;
    • (1986) Australasian Journal of Philosophy , vol.64 , pp. 85-91
    • Armstrong1
  • 41
    • 60949144168 scopus 로고
    • Comments on Armstrong and Forrest
    • David Lewis, 'Comments on Armstrong and Forrest,' Australasian Journal of Philosophy 64 (1986), pp. 92-93.
    • (1986) Australasian Journal of Philosophy , vol.64 , pp. 92-93
    • Lewis, D.1
  • 42
    • 0013013343 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Blackwell
    • Also see his Parts of Classes (Oxford: Blackwell, 1991), pp. 56-57.
    • (1991) Parts of Classes , pp. 56-57
  • 43
    • 79954982040 scopus 로고
    • Nominalism and Realism, and Reinhardt Grossmann
    • Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press
    • E.g., as found in Armstrong, Nominalism and Realism, and Reinhardt Grossmann, The Categorical Structure of the World (Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 1983).
    • (1983) The Categorical Structure of the World
    • Armstrong1
  • 45
    • 79954676843 scopus 로고
    • On the Foundations of Geometry
    • ed. E. Klemke Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • Also see Frege, 'On the Foundations of Geometry' in Essays on Frege, ed. E. Klemke (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1968), pp. 569-71.
    • (1968) Essays on Frege , pp. 569-571
    • Frege1
  • 47
    • 42349097245 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Issues and Options in Exemplification
    • Also see his 'Issues and Options in Exemplification, American Philosophical Quarterly 33 (1996), pp. 133-47.
    • (1996) American Philosophical Quarterly , vol.33 , pp. 133-147
  • 48
    • 0010386761 scopus 로고
    • Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 42ff
    • Gustav Bergmann, Realism (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1967), pp. 9, 42ff.
    • (1967) Realism , pp. 9
    • Bergmann, G.1
  • 49
    • 60950197624 scopus 로고
    • A Refutation of Moderate Nominalism
    • Herbert Hochberg, 'A Refutation of Moderate Nominalism,' Australasian Journal of Philosophy 66 (1988), 188-207.
    • (1988) Australasian Journal of Philosophy , vol.66 , pp. 188-207
    • Hochberg, H.1
  • 50
  • 51
    • 0346647855 scopus 로고
    • 19ff, Princeton: Princeton University Press
    • See Mary Gill, Aristotle on Substance (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1989), pp. 19ff.
    • (1989) Aristotle on Substance
    • Gill, M.1
  • 54
    • 60949803725 scopus 로고
    • A Reconsideration of the Identity and Inherence Theories of the Copula
    • See John Malcolm, 'A Reconsideration of the Identity and Inherence Theories of the Copula,' Journal of the History' of Philosophy 17 (1979), pp. 383-400.
    • (1979) Journal of the History' of Philosophy , vol.17 , pp. 383-400
    • Malcolm, J.1
  • 55
    • 79954857358 scopus 로고
    • Predication and Participation
    • For a particular example of the inherence theory in Aquinas see Keith Buersmeyer, 'Predication and Participation,' The New Scholasticism 55 (1981), pp. 35-51.
    • (1981) The New Scholasticism , vol.55 , pp. 35-51
    • Buersmeyer, K.1
  • 56
    • 0004138736 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2d. ed, ed, Dordrecht: Reidel, 334, 337
    • Gottfried W. Leibniz, Philosophical Papers and Letters, 2d. ed., ed. Leroy Loemker (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1969), pp. 264, 334, 337.
    • (1969) Philosophical Papers and Letters , pp. 264
    • Leibniz, G.W.1
  • 57
    • 0010099845 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 147-149, 2d ed, Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • F. H Bradley, Appearance and Reality, 2d ed. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1897; reprt. ed. 1966), pp. 144-45, 147-49.
    • (1897) Appearance and Reality , pp. 144-145
    • Bradley, F.H.1
  • 60
    • 79954665183 scopus 로고
    • Relations
    • Westport, CT: Greenwood Press
    • F. H. Bradley, 'Relations,' in Collected Essays, Vol. 2 (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1970), p. 638.
    • (1970) Collected Essays , vol.2 , pp. 638
    • Bradley, F.H.1
  • 63
    • 79954898925 scopus 로고
    • ii. 4; ed. T. H. Green and T. H. Grose rpt. ed., Germany: Scientia Verlag Aalen 559
    • David Hume, A Treatise on Human Nature, I. ii. 4; ed. T. H. Green and T. H. Grose (1886; rpt. ed., Germany: Scientia Verlag Aalen, 1964), pp. 352, 559.
    • (1886) A Treatise on Human Nature , vol.1 , pp. 352
    • Hume, D.1
  • 64
    • 0004313844 scopus 로고
    • New York: Columbia University Press
    • There were explicit attempts in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries to demonstrate that proofs in Euclid's Elements are reducible to syllogistic form. See Neal Gilbert, Renaissance Concepts of Method (New York: Columbia University Press, 1960), pp. 89-90.
    • (1960) Renaissance Concepts of Method , pp. 89-90
    • Gilbert, N.1
  • 65
    • 0002808750 scopus 로고
    • Greek Mathematics and Greek Logic
    • ed. John Corcoran Dordrecht: Reidel
    • Ian Mueller has shown that not even the first proposition of the Elements is reducible to syllogistic form. Ian Mueller, 'Greek Mathematics and Greek Logic,' in Ancient Logic and Its Modern Interpretation, ed. John Corcoran (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1974), pp. 35-70.
    • (1974) Ancient Logic and Its Modern Interpretation , pp. 35-70
    • Mueller, I.1
  • 66
    • 0003513971 scopus 로고
    • 221ff, 2d ed, reprt. ed, New York: Norton
    • Bertrand Russell, The Principles of Mathematics, 2d ed. (1903: reprt. ed., New York: Norton, 1938), pp. 221ff.
    • (1903) The Principles of Mathematics
    • Russell, B.1
  • 67
    • 84925971683 scopus 로고
    • The Wiener-Kuratowski Procedure and the Analysis of Order
    • Herbert Hochberg, 'The Wiener-Kuratowski Procedure and the Analysis of Order,' Analysis 41 (1981), pp. 161-3.
    • (1981) Analysis , vol.41 , pp. 161-163
    • Hochberg, H.1
  • 71
    • 0040040377 scopus 로고
    • London: Methuen 54-55
    • Also globally, the non-eliminability of relations provides the ontic underpinning for the analytic methodology that holds that to discover the relations an entity a has with other interrelated entities, i.e., to find a's 'position' in the context of a complex, is to have an explanation of a. As a slogan, 'To explicate is to interrelate.' This contrasts with the once common methodology that 'To explicate is to eliminate.' See Peter Strawson, Subject and Predicate in Logic and Grammar (London: Methuen, 1974), p. 37, 54-55.
    • (1974) Subject and Predicate in Logic and Grammar , pp. 37
    • Strawson, P.1
  • 72
    • 84931330908 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA, MIT Press
    • Also see Jerrold Katz, The Metaphysics of Meaning (Cambridge, MA.; MIT Press, 1990), p. 186.
    • (1990) The Metaphysics of Meaning , pp. 186
    • Katz, J.1
  • 76
    • 84863978543 scopus 로고
    • Buridan's Ontology
    • ed., J. Bogen and J. McGuire (Dordrecht: Reidel)
    • Portions translated by Calvin Normore, 'Buridan's Ontology,' in How Things Are, ed., J. Bogen and J. McGuire (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1985), p. 198.
    • (1985) How Things Are , pp. 198
    • Normore, C.1
  • 78
    • 79954947107 scopus 로고
    • Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press
    • William of Ockham, Ockham's Theory of Terms, trans. Michael Loux (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1974), p. 170.
    • (1974) Theory of Terms , pp. 170
    • Ockham1    Loux, M.2
  • 79
    • 38549153194 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Truthmakers for Negative Truths
    • It is worth noting here that reinforcing this insight into the linking nature of relations is its power in providing a viable 'absence theory' for solving the difficult problem of true negative propositions. The intractability of this problem under standard ontology is highlighted by George Molnar, 'Truthmakers for Negative Truths,' Australasian Journal of Philosophy 78 (2000), pp. 72-86.
    • (2000) Australasian Journal of Philosophy , vol.78 , pp. 72-86
    • Molnar, G.1
  • 80
    • 60950635216 scopus 로고
    • Facts and Classes as Complexes and as Truth Makers
    • Atomic affirmative propositions, e.g., P(a), are held to be true because they correspond to a 'truth-maker' - fact :P(a). Some have held that, by simple analogy, there must be for true negative propositions, e.g., ∼P(a), corresponding 'negative facts.' But this tack, in addition to positing dubious entities, does not account for the fundamental syntactical fact that subjects cannot be negated, but only linguistic predicates, e.g.; whereas one can say 'The ball is not red,' it is nonsensical to say 'The not ball is red.' On the theory of predication defended herein for a negative proposition what is asserted is the absence among the referent(s) of the grammatical subject term(s) (e.g., the ball) of a combi-natorial/predicable state controlled by the intension (e.g., Red) of the referent of the grammatical predicate. Here a predicable nexus is absent, i.e., non-existent, whereas the controlling intension is 'not absent' in the sense that it exists as an abstraction or construction independent of any possible instantiation within a predicable instance. The fact that it is ontic predicates that have this linking aspect explains why only the corresponding linguistic predicates can be negated. Recently Hochberg has attempted to eliminate the need to posit negative facts by proposing that the truth-maker for a negative proposition ∼P(a) is the set of all atomic facts corresponding to the true propositions of the form 'P(a)'. In addition to other problems, this construction commits an epis-temic fallacy of presumed omniscience, a flaw that often infects the substitution of formal models for ontic entities. The set of atomic positive facts is to be the ground for the truth of the negative proposition ∼P(a). Hence, to know that the negative proposition is true we would have to survey the entire infinite set of facts in order to determine that the would-be fact :P(a) is hot in it. Since this is an impossible task for finite minds, we would never be able to determine the truth of negative propositions. See Herbert Hochberg, 'Facts and Classes as Complexes and as Truth Makers,' The Monist 77 (1994), pp. 170-91.
    • (1994) The Monist , vol.77 , pp. 170-191
    • Hochberg, H.1
  • 83
    • 60949310925 scopus 로고
    • Keith Campbell and the Trope View of Predication
    • Also his 'Keith Campbell and the Trope View of Predication,' Australasian Journal of Philosphy 67 (1989), pp. 386-7;
    • (1989) Australasian Journal of Philosphy , vol.67 , pp. 386-387
  • 84
    • 0002596199 scopus 로고
    • Ontology II: Formal Ontology
    • eds. H. Burkhardt & B. Smith Munich: Philosophia Verlag
    • The problem solving power of this analysis of individuated predicates with universal intensions is further magnified when the logic inherent in it is formalized. The result is a 'formal ontology' in the sense of Nino Cocchiarella, 'Ontology II: Formal Ontology' in Handbook of Metaphysics and Ontology, eds. H. Burkhardt & B. Smith (Munich: Philosophia Verlag, 1991), pp. 640-47.
    • (1991) Handbook of Metaphysics and Ontology , pp. 640-647
    • Cocchiarella, N.1
  • 85
    • 53149087493 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Logic of Instance Ontology
    • The logic inherent in realist instance ontology, what I have called 'PPL,' has a number of powerful results, e.g., distinguishing legitimate from illegitimate self-referential predication, distinguishing identity from indiscernibility, and providing an ontology for arithmetic. PPL is developed in Moderate Realism, with an improved version in 'The Logic of Instance Ontology,' Journal of Philosophical Logic 28 (1999), pp. 81-111.
    • (1999) Journal of Philosophical Logic , vol.28 , pp. 81-111
  • 87
    • 0001602526 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Search for Ontological Emergence
    • On the need for emergent properties in science see Michael Silberstein and John McGeever, 'The Search for Ontological Emergence,' Philosophical Quarterly 49 (1999), pp. 182-200.
    • (1999) Philosophical Quarterly , vol.49 , pp. 182-200
    • Silberstein, M.1    McGeever, J.2
  • 89
    • 0004292454 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 324ff
    • David Lewis has in his Parts of Classes advocated the view that mereology provides a general theory of composition. Against this view Simons has pointed out the limitations of mereology in explicating integrated wholes. See Simons' Parts: A Study in Ontology, pp. 324ff.
    • Parts: A Study in Ontology
    • Simons1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.