메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 13, Issue 4, 2007, Pages 441-458

The normative core of paternalism

Author keywords

Action reasons; Actions; Anti paternalism; Harm to others; Interference; Paternalism; Reasons

Indexed keywords


EID: 36648998969     PISSN: 13564765     EISSN: 15728692     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1007/s11158-007-9036-9     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (41)

References (46)
  • 1
    • 36649010846 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Or the invocation of the good of a group of people for interference with them. I will for the most part talk of single persons, though the analysis fits equally well for groups
    • Or the invocation of the good of a group of people for interference with them. I will for the most part talk of single persons, though the analysis fits equally well for groups.
  • 2
    • 36649017247 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A prominent example is Gerald Dworkin, 'Paternalism', in Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2002 Edition), http:// plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2002/entries/paternalism/. Accessed 16 Aug 2006.
    • A prominent example is Gerald Dworkin, 'Paternalism', in Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2002 Edition), http:// plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2002/entries/paternalism/. Accessed 16 Aug 2006.
  • 3
    • 36649035957 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The third condition in Dworkin's analysis of 'X acts paternalistically towards Y by doing (omitting) Z' is: 'X does so just because Z will improve the welfare of Y' (emphasis added).
    • The third condition in Dworkin's analysis of 'X acts paternalistically towards Y by doing (omitting) Z' is: 'X does so just because Z will improve the welfare of Y' (emphasis added).
  • 4
    • 36649017471 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • John Gray claims that paternalism can only be the 'genuine moral dilemma as to whether it is proper to coerce an individual solely in his own interest' - Gray, Mill On Liberty: A Defence (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1983), p. 90, emphasis added.
    • John Gray claims that paternalism can only be the 'genuine moral dilemma as to whether it is proper to coerce an individual solely in his own interest' - Gray, Mill On Liberty: A Defence (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1983), p. 90, emphasis added.
  • 5
    • 36649025701 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Actions may be quite complex, including such state 'actions' as the formulation, adaptation and implementation of policies; policies that can involve legislation, law enforcement, taxes, information, direct aid and infrastructural adjustments
    • Actions may be quite complex, including such state 'actions' as the formulation, adaptation and implementation of policies; policies that can involve legislation, law enforcement, taxes, information, direct aid and infrastructural adjustments.
  • 6
    • 36649007251 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • J.S. Mill's liberty principle states 'that the sole end for which mankind are warranted, individually or collectively, in interfering with the liberty of action of any of their number, is self-protection. That the only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilized community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others. His own good, either physical of moral, is not a sufficient warrant' - see Mill, 'On Liberty', in On Liberty and Other Essays (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991), p. 14.
    • J.S. Mill's liberty principle states 'that the sole end for which mankind are warranted, individually or collectively, in interfering with the liberty of action of any of their number, is self-protection. That the only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilized community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others. His own good, either physical of moral, is not a sufficient warrant' - see Mill, 'On Liberty', in On Liberty and Other Essays (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991), p. 14.
  • 7
    • 36649018110 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Part of the thesis of the present article is that, interpreted generously, Mill claims not only that the good of a person is not a sufficient warrant, but more generally that it is not an acceptable reason, whether or not it is sufficient. C.L. Ten has interpreted Mill along these lines: 'There are certain reasons for intervention in the conduct of individuals which must always be ruled out as irrelevant' - see his Mill on Liberty, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980), p. 40.
    • Part of the thesis of the present article is that, interpreted generously, Mill claims not only that the good of a person is not a sufficient warrant, but more generally that it is not an acceptable reason, whether or not it is sufficient. C.L. Ten has interpreted Mill along these lines: 'There are certain reasons for intervention in the conduct of individuals which must always be ruled out as irrelevant' - see his Mill on Liberty, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980), p. 40.
  • 8
    • 36649030394 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Meanwhile Joel Feinberg's professed methodology in The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law I Harm to others is to investigate 'what kinds of reason can have weight when balanced against the presumptive case for liberty' - see his Harm to others (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984), p. 9.
    • Meanwhile Joel Feinberg's professed methodology in The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law Vol. I Harm to others is to investigate 'what kinds of reason can have weight when balanced against the presumptive case for liberty' - see his Harm to others (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984), p. 9.
  • 9
    • 84938561067 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Joel Feinberg and the Justification of Hard Paternalism
    • On Richard Arneson's interpretation of Feinberg's anti-paternalism, Antipaternalism says that harm or risk of harm to a person who voluntarily consents to absorb the harm or stand the risks is never a good reason for criminal prohibition, see, 259-84, p
    • On Richard Arneson's interpretation of Feinberg's anti-paternalism, 'Antipaternalism says that harm or risk of harm to a person who voluntarily consents to absorb the harm or stand the risks is never a good reason for criminal prohibition' - see Arneson, 'Joel Feinberg and the Justification of Hard Paternalism', Legal Theory 11 (2005) 259-84, p. 263.
    • (2005) Legal Theory , vol.11 , pp. 263
    • Arneson1
  • 10
    • 0004001507 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As soon as any part of a person's conduct affects prejudicially the interests of others, society has jurisdiction over it
    • Cf. Mill, On Liberty p. 83: 'As soon as any part of a person's conduct affects prejudicially the interests of others, society has jurisdiction over it'.
    • On Liberty , pp. 83
    • Mill, C.1
  • 11
    • 36649019573 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Ibid., p. 84: 'Human beings owe to each other help to distinguish the better from the worse, and encouragement to choose the former and avoid the latter.'
    • Cf. Ibid., p. 84: 'Human beings owe to each other help to distinguish the better from the worse, and encouragement to choose the former and avoid the latter.'
  • 12
    • 36649034274 scopus 로고
    • These include Gerald Dworkin, 'Paternalism
    • These include Gerald Dworkin, 'Paternalism', Stanford Encyclopedia; The Monist 56 (1972) 64-84;
    • (1972) Stanford Encyclopedia; The Monist , vol.56 , pp. 64-84
  • 14
    • 0347290192 scopus 로고
    • Manchester: Manchester University Press
    • John Kleinig, Paternalism (Manchester: Manchester University Press 1983);
    • (1983) Paternalism
    • Kleinig, J.1
  • 16
    • 33645250238 scopus 로고
    • Paternalism Defined
    • David Archard, 'Paternalism Defined', Analysis 50/1 (1990) 36-42;
    • (1990) Analysis , vol.50 , Issue.1 , pp. 36-42
    • Archard, D.1
  • 20
    • 36649037383 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On some action-focused accounts of paternalism, lack of consent is listed as an independent condition on paternalistic actions. However, we may incorporate consent into the action component by assuming that whether and what kind of consent is given affects what counts as interference. This approach has the advantage of allowing for different versions of paternalism to attribute to consent as central or as marginal a role as its proponents would like in specifying interference.
    • On some action-focused accounts of paternalism, lack of consent is listed as an independent condition on paternalistic actions. However, we may incorporate consent into the action component by assuming that whether and what kind of consent is given affects what counts as interference. This approach has the advantage of allowing for different versions of paternalism to attribute to consent as central or as marginal a role as its proponents would like in specifying interference.
  • 21
    • 36649036784 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The action component of paternalism traditionally goes by such names as 'interference with choice' (Van de Veer, p. 19),
    • The action component of paternalism traditionally goes by such names as 'interference with choice' (Van de Veer, p. 19),
  • 22
    • 36649036361 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'imposition' (Kleinig, p. 7), 'violation of autonomy' (Gerald Dworkin, 'Some Second Thoughts', in Rolf Sartorius (ed.), Paternalism (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press 1983) 105-11, p. 107),
    • 'imposition' (Kleinig, p. 7), 'violation of autonomy' (Gerald Dworkin, 'Some Second Thoughts', in Rolf Sartorius (ed.), Paternalism (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press 1983) 105-11, p. 107),
  • 23
    • 36649010423 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'limiting liberty' (Joel Feinberg, The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law 2 Harm to Self (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1986), p. ix),
    • 'limiting liberty' (Joel Feinberg, The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law Vol. 2 Harm to Self (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1986), p. ix),
  • 24
    • 36649001386 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • or 'interference with the liberty of action' (Mill, On Liberty p. 14).
    • or 'interference with the liberty of action' (Mill, On Liberty p. 14).
  • 25
    • 36649003696 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is proposed for example by Archard, Paternalism Defined, pp. 38-9
    • This is proposed for example by Archard, 'Paternalism Defined', pp. 38-9.
  • 26
    • 36649007678 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Clarke explicitly renounces the 'solely' and 'mainly' conditions, with the argument that also 'minor' reasons can make an action paternalistic - 'A Definition of Paternalism', p. 2, esp. n.1.
    • Clarke explicitly renounces the 'solely' and 'mainly' conditions, with the argument that also 'minor' reasons can make an action paternalistic - 'A Definition of Paternalism', p. 2, esp. n.1.
  • 27
    • 36649020466 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kleinig, op. cit., p.12 (emphasis in original). The more formally stated definition of paternalism on p. 13 suggest a strict either or-account of the rationale for an action. The surrounding discussion, however, makes it clear that the quoted passage is more in line with Kleinig's intentions.
    • Kleinig, op. cit., p.12 (emphasis in original). The more formally stated definition of paternalism on p. 13 suggest a strict either or-account of the rationale for an action. The surrounding discussion, however, makes it clear that the quoted passage is more in line with Kleinig's intentions.
  • 28
    • 0004260399 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • E.g, That there are such cases is often acknowledged, but the problems they raise for the analysis of paternalism are not
    • E.g. Feinberg, Harm to Self p. 8. That there are such cases is often acknowledged, but the problems they raise for the analysis of paternalism are not.
    • Harm to Self , pp. 8
    • Feinberg1
  • 29
    • 36649029748 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • de Marneffe, op. cit., p. 72.
    • de Marneffe, op. cit., p. 72.
  • 31
    • 36649023941 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., pp. 84-5, 92.
    • Ibid., pp. 84-5, 92.
  • 32
    • 36649005783 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It may be that the reasons there are for an action determine what kind of action it is. This does not pose a problem for the action-reason account. Once an action is distinguished, whether by its actual effects or by some standard based on intentionality, it may be paired with different reasons, that are reasons for that action, to form action-reasons. The framework of action-reasons is independent of how exactly actions and reasons are individuated, though theories about individuation may perhaps be informed by this framework
    • It may be that the reasons there are for an action determine what kind of action it is. This does not pose a problem for the action-reason account. Once an action is distinguished, whether by its actual effects or by some standard based on intentionality, it may be paired with different reasons, that are reasons for that action, to form action-reasons. The framework of action-reasons is independent of how exactly actions and reasons are individuated, though theories about individuation may perhaps be informed by this framework.
  • 33
    • 36649011188 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This account of paternalism makes no direct reference to the attitude of the paternalist. To some extent, being motivated by or accepting as valid, paternalistic reasons for interference may be taken to constitute a paternalistic attitude. However, there is no reference to specific attitudes such as that of superiority or condescension, or the proper attitude of a parent towards her child. This is arguably an advantage of the account, since it is unclear whether paternalism, necessarily involves any such attitudes
    • This account of paternalism makes no direct reference to the attitude of the paternalist. To some extent, being motivated by or accepting as valid, paternalistic reasons for interference may be taken to constitute a paternalistic attitude. However, there is no reference to specific attitudes such as that of superiority or condescension, or the proper attitude of a parent towards her child. This is arguably an advantage of the account, since it is unclear whether paternalism, necessarily involves any such attitudes.
  • 34
    • 36649006026 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We may distinguish between on the one hand the relevance of a reason, determined by whether or not the value that the reason refers to is affected by the choice or action under consideration, and on the other hand the validity of a reason, determined by whether or not the reason should have any weight according to (the correct) normative principles. In order to be a reason for an action, it is enough that the reason is relevant. In order to actually give normative support to the action, the reason must also be valid
    • We may distinguish between on the one hand the relevance of a reason, determined by whether or not the value that the reason refers to is affected by the choice or action under consideration, and on the other hand the validity of a reason, determined by whether or not the reason should have any weight according to (the correct) normative principles. In order to be a reason for an action, it is enough that the reason is relevant. In order to actually give normative support to the action, the reason must also be valid.
  • 35
    • 36649026488 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moderate anti-paternalists may want to discount paternalistic reasons in some fashion, rather than reject them outright. Louis Groarke argues against absolute anti-paternalism and suggests that for any interference the value of 'care' should be subtracted from the value of freedom - 'Paternalism and Egregious Harm
    • Moderate anti-paternalists may want to discount paternalistic reasons in some fashion, rather than reject them outright. Louis Groarke argues against absolute anti-paternalism and suggests that for any interference the value of 'care' should be subtracted from the value of freedom - 'Paternalism and Egregious Harm', Public Affairs Quarterly 16/3 (2002) 203-30.
    • (2002) Public Affairs Quarterly , vol.16 , Issue.3 , pp. 203-230
  • 36
    • 36648998728 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • However, he believes that '[pjaternalism would be permissible only in those cases where the net value was largely or perhaps very largely negative' - p. 219, emphasis added.
    • However, he believes that '[pjaternalism would be permissible only in those cases where the net value was largely or perhaps very largely negative' - p. 219, emphasis added.
  • 37
    • 36649013449 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the other hand, extreme anti-paternalists may suggest that paternalism is so degrading that the fact that an interference protects or promotes the good of a person should not only not count as a valid reason for that interference but should actually count as a reason against it. The fact that (part of) the rationale for an interference is the good of the person interfered with 'adds insult to injury, so to speak see Kleinig, Paternalism pp. 70-2 for ideas along these lines, Interfering with a person for selfish purposes could thus be morally better than interfering in the same way out of benevolence. To encompass this view, the rejection of an action-reason may be taken to give rise to an antipaternalistic reason against the action, with whatever weight necessary to account for the strength of the extreme anti-paternalism
    • On the other hand, extreme anti-paternalists may suggest that paternalism is so degrading that the fact that an interference protects or promotes the good of a person should not only not count as a valid reason for that interference but should actually count as a reason against it. The fact that (part of) the rationale for an interference is the good of the person interfered with 'adds insult to injury', so to speak (see Kleinig, Paternalism pp. 70-2 for ideas along these lines). Interfering with a person for selfish purposes could thus be morally better than interfering in the same way out of benevolence. To encompass this view, the rejection of an action-reason may be taken to give rise to an antipaternalistic reason against the action, with whatever weight necessary to account for the strength of the extreme anti-paternalism.
  • 38
    • 36649009544 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It follows from this interpretation that anti-paternalism cannot be dismissed with the simple observation that it is all but impossible to identify any action (and especially, perhaps, any state policy) that interferes with certain persons and promotes their good, without affecting the interests of others. This is as it should be
    • It follows from this interpretation that anti-paternalism cannot be dismissed with the simple observation that it is all but impossible to identify any action (and especially, perhaps, any state policy) that interferes with certain persons and promotes their good, without affecting the interests of others. This is as it should be.
  • 39
    • 36649002853 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Whether or not it is an interference depends on how interference is fleshed out as part of a more detailed conception of paternalism. Most such conceptions would consider the seizing of another's property (against her will) an interference
    • Whether or not it is an interference depends on how interference is fleshed out as part of a more detailed conception of paternalism. Most such conceptions would consider the seizing of another's property (against her will) an interference.
  • 40
    • 0002433504 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Paternalism
    • In general, nothing prevents direct involvement with one person counting as interference with another. It could in some cases be an interference with P to seize Q's cigarettes. More commonly, it may be an interference with P to prevent Q from selling cigarettes to P. Such interference is an example of what Dworkin calls 'impure' paternalism and Feinberg a 'two-party-case, see
    • In general, nothing prevents direct involvement with one person counting as interference with another. It could in some cases be an interference with P to seize Q's cigarettes. More commonly, it may be an interference with P to prevent Q from selling cigarettes to P. Such interference is an example of what Dworkin calls 'impure' paternalism and Feinberg a 'two-party-case' - see Dworkin, 'Paternalism', Monist, p. 68;
    • Monist , pp. 68
    • Dworkin1
  • 42
    • 36649001603 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An alternative would be to introduce subreasons and 'effect-subreasons, which would be paternalistic if and only if the subreason referred to the good of a person and the effect was an interference with the same person
    • An alternative would be to introduce subreasons and 'effect-subreasons', which would be paternalistic if and only if the subreason referred to the good of a person and the effect was an interference with the same person.
  • 46
    • 36649033625 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On most action-focused accounts, the good-promotion or -protection is taken to be believed rather than actual. As for the action component, some authors focus on actual interference (e.g. Dworkin 'Paternalism', Stanford Encyclopedia), while others place the interference as well as the protection or promotion of good entirely in the head of the agent - see Gert and Culver, 'Paternalistic behaviour' pp. 49-50.
    • On most action-focused accounts, the good-promotion or -protection is taken to be believed rather than actual. As for the action component, some authors focus on actual interference (e.g. Dworkin 'Paternalism', Stanford Encyclopedia), while others place the interference as well as the protection or promotion of good entirely in the head of the agent - see Gert and Culver, 'Paternalistic behaviour' pp. 49-50.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.