-
1
-
-
0004305896
-
-
trans. Mary J. Gregor Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
Immanuel Kant, Practical Philosophy, trans. Mary J. Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 8:37.
-
(1996)
Practical Philosophy
, vol.8
, pp. 37
-
-
Kant, I.1
-
2
-
-
0005507859
-
-
trans. Pascale-Anne Brault and Michael Naas Stanford, Calif, Stanford University Press
-
Jacques Derrida, Adieu to Emmanuel Levinas, trans. Pascale-Anne Brault and Michael Naas (Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press, 1999), 115.
-
(1999)
Adieu to Emmanuel Levinas
, pp. 115
-
-
Derrida, J.1
-
3
-
-
35648993560
-
-
See, for example, Christopher Norris, What's Wrong with Postmodernism: Critical Theory and the Ends of Philosophy (Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press, 1990), 194-207, for a discussion of Derrida's relation to Kant's epistemological project;
-
See, for example, Christopher Norris, What's Wrong with Postmodernism: Critical Theory and the Ends of Philosophy (Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press, 1990), 194-207, for a discussion of Derrida's relation to Kant's epistemological project;
-
-
-
-
4
-
-
35648935481
-
-
Irene Harvey, Derrida and The Economy of Différance (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1986), who is concerned with the influence of Kant's notion of critique and conception of the limits of reason;
-
Irene Harvey, Derrida and The Economy of Différance (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1986), who is concerned with the influence of Kant's notion of critique and conception of the limits of reason;
-
-
-
-
5
-
-
35649027388
-
-
and Philip Rothfield, ed., Kant after Derrida (Manchester, UK: Clinamen, 2003), which is a collection of essays on a range of Kantian themes.
-
and Philip Rothfield, ed., Kant after Derrida (Manchester, UK: Clinamen, 2003), which is a collection of essays on a range of Kantian themes.
-
-
-
-
7
-
-
0004184643
-
-
trans. Mark Dooley and Michael Hughes London: Routledge
-
and Jacques Derrida, On Cosmopolitanism and Forgiveness, trans. Mark Dooley and Michael Hughes (London: Routledge, 2001).
-
(2001)
On Cosmopolitanism and Forgiveness
-
-
Derrida, J.1
-
8
-
-
35649003372
-
-
ed. John Caputo, Mark Dooley, and Michael J. Scanlon Bloomington: Indiana University Press
-
Jacques Derrida, Questioning God, ed. John Caputo, Mark Dooley, and Michael J. Scanlon (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2001), 66.
-
(2001)
Questioning God
, pp. 66
-
-
Derrida, J.1
-
10
-
-
35648996492
-
-
Levinas's influence on Derrida's ethics has been explored more thoroughly than Kant's. This work includes Simon Critchley, The Ethics of Deconstruction: Derrida and Levinas (West Lafayette, Ind.: Purdue University Press, 1999);
-
Levinas's influence on Derrida's ethics has been explored more thoroughly than Kant's. This work includes Simon Critchley, The Ethics of Deconstruction: Derrida and Levinas (West Lafayette, Ind.: Purdue University Press, 1999);
-
-
-
-
11
-
-
0005301213
-
-
London: Verso
-
Simon Critchley, Ethics, Politics, and Subjectivity: Essays on Derrida, Levinas, and Contemporary French Thought (London: Verso, 1999);
-
(1999)
Ethics, Politics, and Subjectivity: Essays on Derrida, Levinas, and Contemporary French Thought
-
-
Critchley, S.1
-
12
-
-
0038120421
-
A Singular Justice: Ethics and Politics between Levinas and Derrida
-
Diane Perpich, "A Singular Justice: Ethics and Politics between Levinas and Derrida," Philosophy Today 42, supp. (1998): 59-70;
-
(1998)
Philosophy Today
, vol.42
, Issue.SUPP.
, pp. 59-70
-
-
Perpich, D.1
-
13
-
-
35648945326
-
Derrida Brings Levinas to Kant: The Welcome, Ethics, and Cosmopolitical Law
-
who also considers the relation of both to Kant
-
and Miriam Bankovsky, "Derrida Brings Levinas to Kant: The Welcome, Ethics, and Cosmopolitical Law," Philosophy Today 49, no. 2 (2005): 156-71, who also considers the relation of both to Kant.
-
(2005)
Philosophy Today
, vol.49
, Issue.2
, pp. 156-171
-
-
Bankovsky, M.1
-
14
-
-
35648959299
-
-
Derrida discusses Levinas in Jacques Derrida, Writing and Difference, trans. Alan Bass (London: Routledge, 2001);
-
Derrida discusses Levinas in Jacques Derrida, Writing and Difference, trans. Alan Bass (London: Routledge, 2001);
-
-
-
-
16
-
-
35648993559
-
Not Just Visitors: Cosmopolitanism, Hospitality, and Refugees
-
On Kant and Derrida on hospitality, see
-
On Kant and Derrida on hospitality, see Marguerite La Caze, "Not Just Visitors: Cosmopolitanism, Hospitality, and Refugees," Philosophy Today 48, no. 3 (2004): 313-24.
-
(2004)
Philosophy Today
, vol.48
, Issue.3
, pp. 313-324
-
-
Caze, M.L.1
-
17
-
-
35648937591
-
-
Beards worth analyses the relation between Kant and Derrida on law and violence in Richard Beardsworth, Derrida and the Political London: Routledge 1996, 46-70
-
Beards worth analyses the relation between Kant and Derrida on law and violence in Richard Beardsworth, Derrida and the Political (London: Routledge 1996), 46-70.
-
-
-
-
18
-
-
35649013262
-
-
I prefer the term ethics to morality as it seems less focused on individual mores to the contemporary ear.
-
I prefer the term ethics to morality as it seems less focused on individual mores to the contemporary ear.
-
-
-
-
19
-
-
35648978164
-
Toward Perpetual Peace, in Kant
-
Immanuel Kant, "Toward Perpetual Peace," in Kant, Practical Philosophy, 8:380.
-
Practical Philosophy
, vol.8
, pp. 380
-
-
Kant, I.1
-
20
-
-
35648990941
-
-
This position follows from his view that ought to implies can in Immanuel Kant, Critique of Practical Reason, in Kant, Practical Philosophy
-
This position follows from his view that ought to implies can in Immanuel Kant, Critique of Practical Reason, in Kant, Practical Philosophy.
-
-
-
-
21
-
-
35648974787
-
-
Kant says that our awareness of the moral law when we construct maxims of the will leads us to the concept of freedom. Furthermore, our experience confirms this concept of freedom when we remember that we can act against our strongest desires and even our love of life in order to act ethically (ibid., 5:30).
-
Kant says that our awareness of the moral law when we construct maxims of the will leads us to the concept of freedom. Furthermore, our experience confirms this concept of freedom when we remember that we can act against our strongest desires and even our love of life in order to act ethically (ibid., 5:30).
-
-
-
-
22
-
-
35648942776
-
-
By contrast, in the Groundwork (in Kant, Practical Philosophy),
-
By contrast, in the Groundwork (in Kant, Practical Philosophy),
-
-
-
-
23
-
-
35648948938
-
-
Kant argues that because we are autonomous we are bound by the moral law: 'If, therefore, freedom of the will is presupposed, morality together with its principle follows from it by mere analysis of its concept' (ibid., 4:447).
-
Kant argues that because we are autonomous we are bound by the moral law: 'If, therefore, freedom of the will is presupposed, morality together with its principle follows from it by mere analysis of its concept' (ibid., 4:447).
-
-
-
-
24
-
-
35649025392
-
-
Elsewhere, in a review of Schulz's '[a]ttempt at an introduction to a doctrine of morals,' he asserts that without this possibility of freedom, any imperative is absurd and the only position we can adopt is fatalism (ibid., 8:13).
-
Elsewhere, in a review of Schulz's '[a]ttempt at an introduction to a doctrine of morals,' he asserts that without this possibility of freedom, any imperative is absurd and the only position we can adopt is fatalism (ibid., 8:13).
-
-
-
-
26
-
-
35649027387
-
-
Kant defines right as 'the sum. of the conditions under which the choice of one can be united with the choice of another in accordance with a universal law of freedom' (ibid., 6:230). He further distinguishes between natural or private right, which includes rights to property, rights to contracts, and domestic right, and public or civil right, which concerns the rights of a state, the rights of nations, and cosmopolitan right. The doctrine of virtue includes duties to ourselves and the duties to others of love and respect.
-
Kant defines right as 'the sum. of the conditions under which the choice of one can be united with the choice of another in accordance with a universal law of freedom' (ibid., 6:230). He further distinguishes between natural or private right, which includes rights to property, rights to contracts, and domestic right, and public or civil right, which concerns the rights of a state, the rights of nations, and cosmopolitan right. The doctrine of virtue includes duties to ourselves and the duties to others of love and respect.
-
-
-
-
27
-
-
35648979553
-
-
The doctrine of right concerns the a priori basis of ethical laws. One might disagree with Kant's view that politics is the doctrine of right put into practice and argue, for example, that ethics and politics are two separate spheres, as Arendt does in Hannah Arendt, Responsibility and Judgment, ed. Jerome Kohn (New York: Schocken, 2003), 147-58.
-
The doctrine of right concerns the a priori basis of ethical laws. One might disagree with Kant's view that politics is the doctrine of right put into practice and argue, for example, that ethics and politics are two separate spheres, as Arendt does in Hannah Arendt, Responsibility and Judgment, ed. Jerome Kohn (New York: Schocken, 2003), 147-58.
-
-
-
-
29
-
-
35648966573
-
-
According to Kant, the aims of moral evil are self-contradictory and self-destructive, whereas those of moral goodness are consistent and conducive to happiness, so evil gives way to the moral principle of goodness (Kant, Practical Philosophy, 8:379).
-
According to Kant, the aims of moral evil are self-contradictory and self-destructive, whereas those of moral goodness are consistent and conducive to happiness, so evil gives way to the moral principle of goodness (Kant, Practical Philosophy, 8:379).
-
-
-
-
30
-
-
35649014335
-
-
See Kant's discussion of radical evil in Immanuel Kant, Religion within the Limits of Reason Alone, in Religion and Rational Theology, trans. and ed. Allen W. Wood and George di Giovanni (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996).
-
See Kant's discussion of radical evil in Immanuel Kant, "Religion within the Limits of Reason Alone," in Religion and Rational Theology, trans. and ed. Allen W. Wood and George di Giovanni (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996).
-
-
-
-
32
-
-
35649008416
-
-
Jacques Derrida, Negotiations: Interventions and Interviews, 1971-2001, trans. Elizabeth Rottenberg (Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press, 2002), 295-314. The essay was first given as a talk in 1987.
-
Jacques Derrida, Negotiations: Interventions and Interviews, 1971-2001, trans. Elizabeth Rottenberg (Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press, 2002), 295-314. The essay was first given as a talk in 1987.
-
-
-
-
36
-
-
85010745973
-
-
Levinas also believes that we have to negotiate between ethics and politics. Robert Bernasconi says that Levinas is not concerned to resolve conflicts between ethics and politics, yet 'the task of negotiating in practice the conflicting demands under which I find myself, involves the use of reason, that is, the third person, perspective' ; Robert Bernasconi, The Third Party: Levinas on the Intersection of the Ethical and the Political, Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 30, no. 1 (1999): 81. In his view, while Levinas 'favors' ethics over politics, they are not in opposition for him.
-
Levinas also believes that we have to negotiate between ethics and politics. Robert Bernasconi says that Levinas is not concerned to resolve conflicts between ethics and politics, yet 'the task of negotiating in practice the conflicting demands under which I find myself, involves the use of reason, that is, the third person, perspective' ; Robert Bernasconi, "The Third Party: Levinas on the Intersection of the Ethical and the Political," Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 30, no. 1 (1999): 81. In his view, while Levinas 'favors' ethics over politics, they are not in opposition for him.
-
-
-
-
37
-
-
60949782425
-
Ethics and Politics Today
-
Jacques Derrida, Stanford, Calif, Stanford University Press, Both these approaches have been used in response to the taking of foreign hostages in Iraq. In that circumstance, I think it would be hard to justify a refusal to negotiate as there is not enough order for one to argue that such negotiation would 'create a precedent
-
Jacques Derrida, "Ethics and Politics Today," in Jacques Derrida, Negotiations (Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press, 2002), 305. Both these approaches have been used in response to the taking of foreign hostages in Iraq. In that circumstance, I think it would be hard to justify a refusal to negotiate as there is not enough order for one to argue that such negotiation would 'create a precedent.'
-
(2002)
Negotiations
, pp. 305
-
-
Derrida, J.1
-
38
-
-
0002404574
-
Force of Law: The 'Mystical Foundation of Authority,'
-
trans, ed, and, London: Routledge, 14
-
Jacques Derrida, "Force of Law: The 'Mystical Foundation of Authority,'" trans. Mary Quaintance, in Deconstruction and the Possibility of Justice, ed. Drucilla Cornell, Michel Rosenfeld, and David Gray Carlson (London: Routledge, 1992), 14.
-
(1992)
Deconstruction and the Possibility of Justice
-
-
Derrida, J.1
-
40
-
-
33947370466
-
The Problem of the Promise: Derrida on Levinas on the Cities of Refuge
-
For another reading of Levinas's essay, in relation to the idea of political utopianism, see
-
For another reading of Levinas's essay, in relation to the idea of political utopianism, see Oona Eisenstadt, "The Problem of the Promise: Derrida on Levinas on the Cities of Refuge," Cross Currents 52, no. 4 (2003): 474-82.
-
(2003)
Cross Currents
, vol.52
, Issue.4
, pp. 474-482
-
-
Eisenstadt, O.1
-
41
-
-
35648991999
-
-
Derrida, Adieu to Emmanuel Levinas, 112. Levinas's idea of justice appears to be very different from Derrida's. For Derrida, justice is the ultimate ethical ideal, the undeconstructible, that goes beyond particular laws (Derrida, Force of Law, 14). For Levinas, justice is the political necessity of weighing different competing claims, contrasted with the infinite responsibility for the particular other that is the ethical relation. In Derrida's outlook, justice takes this concern with singularity.
-
Derrida, Adieu to Emmanuel Levinas, 112. Levinas's idea of justice appears to be very different from Derrida's. For Derrida, justice is the ultimate ethical ideal, the undeconstructible, that goes beyond particular laws (Derrida, "Force of Law," 14). For Levinas, justice is the political necessity of weighing different competing claims, contrasted with the infinite responsibility for the particular other that is the ethical relation. In Derrida's outlook, justice takes this concern with singularity.
-
-
-
-
43
-
-
35649002578
-
-
In 'On the common saying: That may be correct in theory, but it is of no use in practice,' Kant defines the principles of a civil state as (1) the freedom of every member of the society as a human being, (2) his equality with every other as a subject, and (3) the independence of every member of a commonwealth as a citizen (ibid., 8:290);
-
In 'On the common saying: That may be correct in theory, but it is of no use in practice,' Kant defines the principles of a civil state as (1) the freedom of every member of the society as a human being, (2) his equality with every other as a subject, and (3) the independence of every member of a commonwealth as a citizen (ibid., 8:290);
-
-
-
-
44
-
-
35649012786
-
-
and likewise in Immanuel Kant, The Metaphysics of Morals
-
and likewise in Immanuel Kant, The Metaphysics of Morals
-
-
-
-
45
-
-
35648978163
-
-
(in ibid., 6:314),
-
(in ibid., 6:314),
-
-
-
-
46
-
-
35649011498
-
-
and in Immanuel Kant, Perpetual Peace, Kant says that the principles of a Republican state are freedom, equality, and the dependence 'of all upon a single common legislation (as subjects)' (in ibid., 8:350). A comparison of Kant's republicanism with Derrida's idea of democracy is one I do not have the space to pursue here.
-
and in Immanuel Kant, Perpetual Peace, Kant says that the principles of a Republican state are freedom, equality, and the dependence 'of all upon a single common legislation (as subjects)' (in ibid., 8:350). A comparison of Kant's republicanism with Derrida's idea of democracy is one I do not have the space to pursue here.
-
-
-
-
47
-
-
84970786374
-
-
Ibid., 8:381.
-
, vol.8
, pp. 381
-
-
Kant1
-
48
-
-
35648963149
-
-
The second transcendental principle of public right is as follows:, Kant's argument for this principle is that if maxims can only be successful through publicity, they must correspond to the universal public end, which is happiness, and for him this is what politics must do
-
The second transcendental principle of public right is as follows: 'All maxims which need publicity (in order not to fail in their end) harmonize with right and politics combined' (ibid., 8:386). Kant's argument for this principle is that if maxims can only be successful through publicity, they must correspond to the universal public end, which is happiness, and for him this is what politics must do.
-
All maxims which need publicity (in order not to fail in their end) harmonize with right and politics combined' (ibid
, vol.8
, pp. 386
-
-
-
49
-
-
35649021298
-
-
Ibid., 8:385.
-
, vol.8
, pp. 385
-
-
-
50
-
-
35648938721
-
-
Ibid., 8:381.
-
, vol.8
, pp. 381
-
-
-
51
-
-
35649002024
-
-
Ibid., 8:380.
-
, vol.8
, pp. 380
-
-
-
52
-
-
35648954648
-
-
There has been a great deal of interest in Kant's condemnation of rebellion here, particularly since he is a well-known supporter of the French Revolution; ibid., 6:320-23.
-
There has been a great deal of interest in Kant's condemnation of rebellion here, particularly since he is a well-known supporter of the French Revolution; ibid., 6:320-23.
-
-
-
-
53
-
-
0003597322
-
-
See, for example, London: Routledge
-
See, for example, Kimberly Hutchings, Kant, Critique, and Politics (London: Routledge, 1996), 46;
-
(1996)
Kant, Critique, and Politics
, pp. 46
-
-
Hutchings, K.1
-
54
-
-
35648995954
-
-
ed. Ronald Beiner Chicago: University of Chicago Press
-
and Hannah Arendt, Lectures on Kant's Political Philosophy, ed. Ronald Beiner (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1982), 44-51.
-
(1982)
Lectures on Kant's Political Philosophy
, pp. 44-51
-
-
Arendt, H.1
-
56
-
-
35648965255
-
-
Kant's examples of ethical constraints on politics between, states include the nonacquisition of existing states, the abolition of standing armies, no national debts with regard to external affairs, non-interference with the governments of other states, and not using duplicitous means in war; definitive articles recommend republicanism, for all states, a federalism of free states, and the cosmopolitan right of hospitality. Kant examines three cases of apparent conflict between politics and morals in international right and presents their resolution: where one nation promises to aid another nation but decides to release itself from the promise because of the effects that keeping the promise would have on its own well-being, where lesser nations could not make public the idea that they intend to attack a greater power preemptively, and where a large nation could not make it known that it would absorb smaller nations if it thought that necessary to its preservation Kant, Practical Phi
-
Kant's examples of ethical constraints on politics between, states include the nonacquisition of existing states, the abolition of standing armies, no national debts with regard to external affairs, non-interference with the governments of other states, and not using duplicitous means in war; definitive articles recommend republicanism, for all states, a federalism of free states, and the cosmopolitan right of hospitality. Kant examines three cases of apparent conflict between politics and morals in international right and presents their resolution: where one nation promises to aid another nation but decides to release itself from the promise because of the effects that keeping the promise would have on its own well-being, where lesser nations could not make public the idea that they intend to attack a greater power preemptively, and where a large nation could not make it known that it would absorb smaller nations if it thought that necessary to its preservation (Kant, Practical Philosophy, 8:383-84). Third, Kant says that cosmopolitan right's maxims work by analogy to those of international right. Cosmopolitan right is interesting since the power imbalance between individuals and states is enormous.
-
-
-
-
57
-
-
35648979032
-
-
Ibid., 8:385.
-
, vol.8
, pp. 385
-
-
-
58
-
-
35649012784
-
-
Another example Kant gives is that it cannot be demanded of a state that it give up its constitution even though this is a despotic one (which is, for all that, the stronger kind in relation to external enemies), so long as it runs the risk of being at once devoured by other states; hence, as for that resolution, it must also be permitted to postpone putting it into effect until a more favorable time. (Ibid., 8:373)
-
Another example Kant gives is that it cannot be demanded of a state that it give up its constitution even though this is a despotic one (which is, for all that, the stronger kind in relation to external enemies), so long as it runs the risk of being at once devoured by other states; hence, as for that resolution, it must also be permitted to postpone putting it into effect until a more favorable time. (Ibid., 8:373)
-
-
-
-
59
-
-
35648940793
-
-
Thus, it is reasonable to wait until the state is secure from invasion before rectifying injustice if that injustice is protecting the state
-
Thus, it is reasonable to wait until the state is secure from invasion before rectifying injustice if that injustice is protecting the state.
-
-
-
-
63
-
-
35649019255
-
-
Another way Kant puts this point is that although respect 'is a mere duty of virtue, it is regarded as narrow in comparison with a duty of love, and it is the latter that is considered a wide duty';
-
Another way Kant puts this point is that although respect 'is a mere duty of virtue, it is regarded as narrow in comparison with a duty of love, and it is the latter that is considered a wide duty';
-
-
-
-
64
-
-
35648963692
-
-
ibid., 6:450.
-
, vol.6
, pp. 450
-
-
Kant1
-
65
-
-
35648983494
-
-
Ibid., 8:301.
-
, vol.8
, pp. 301
-
-
Kant1
-
66
-
-
35648999556
-
-
Ibid., 6:371.
-
, vol.6
, pp. 371
-
-
Kant1
-
67
-
-
79951520946
-
Doctrine of Right
-
ed, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, XIX
-
Immanuel Kant, "Doctrine of Right," in The Metaphysics of Morals, ed. Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), XIX, 594-95,
-
(1996)
The Metaphysics of Morals
, pp. 594-595
-
-
Kant, I.1
-
68
-
-
35648964228
-
-
quoted in Robert J. Dostal, Judging Human Action: Arendt's Appropriation of Kant, Review of Metaphysics 37 (1984): 732.
-
quoted in Robert J. Dostal, "Judging Human Action: Arendt's Appropriation of Kant," Review of Metaphysics 37 (1984): 732.
-
-
-
-
71
-
-
36648998531
-
Remarks on Derrida and Habermas
-
Simon Critchley, "Remarks on Derrida and Habermas," Constellations 7, no. 4 (2000): 461-62.
-
(2000)
Constellations
, vol.7
, Issue.4
, pp. 461-462
-
-
Critchley, S.1
-
75
-
-
35649014334
-
-
Another way that Derrida expresses this problem is by writing, as shown above in the text, 'The hiatus, the silence of this non-response concerning the schemas between the ethical and the political, remains. It is a fact that it remains, and this fact is not some empirical contingency, it is a Faktum'
-
Another way that Derrida expresses this problem is by writing, as shown above in the text, 'The hiatus, the silence of this non-response concerning the schemas between the ethical and the political, remains. It is a fact that it remains, and this fact is not some empirical contingency, it is a Faktum'
-
-
-
-
76
-
-
35648981918
-
-
(ibid., 116).
-
(ibid., 116).
-
-
-
-
80
-
-
27844452337
-
-
trans. Pascale-Anne Brault and Michael Naas Stanford, Calif, Stanford University Press
-
Derrida, Rogues: Two Essays on Reason, trans. Pascale-Anne Brault and Michael Naas (Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press, 2005), 86.
-
(2005)
Rogues: Two Essays on Reason
, pp. 86
-
-
Derrida1
-
81
-
-
35648989038
-
-
Critchley has a very good, albeit brief, discussion of what Derrida means by democracy to come in Remarks on Derrida and Habermas, 463-64.
-
Critchley has a very good, albeit brief, discussion of what Derrida means by democracy to come in "Remarks on Derrida and Habermas," 463-64.
-
-
-
-
82
-
-
35648937035
-
-
Jacques Derrida, Limited, Inc., ed. Gerald Graff (Evanston, 111.: Northwestern University Press 1988), 152.
-
Jacques Derrida, Limited, Inc., ed. Gerald Graff (Evanston, 111.: Northwestern University Press 1988), 152.
-
-
-
-
85
-
-
35648999038
-
-
trans. Norman Kemp Smith London: Macmillan
-
Immanuel Kant, The Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Norman Kemp Smith (London: Macmillan, 1986), A669-704, B697-732.
-
(1986)
The Critique of Pure Reason
, vol.A669-704
-
-
Kant, I.1
-
86
-
-
35648964229
-
-
Ibid., A686, B714.
-
, vol.A686
-
-
Kant, I.1
-
87
-
-
35649012785
-
-
Borradori, Philosophy in a Time of Terror, 134. Derrida also says he hesitates to conflate his idea of justice with a Kantian regulative idea (Derrida, Force of Law, 25).
-
Borradori, Philosophy in a Time of Terror, 134. Derrida also says he hesitates to conflate his idea of justice with a Kantian regulative idea (Derrida, "Force of Law," 25).
-
-
-
-
88
-
-
35648933000
-
-
He repeats his reservations in Derrida, Rogues (83-85), in a discussion concerning democracy.
-
He repeats his reservations in Derrida, Rogues (83-85), in a discussion concerning democracy.
-
-
-
-
92
-
-
35648949436
-
-
Kant's description of moral ideas in the Critique of Practical Reason also seems helpful: [I]f I understand by an idea a perfection to which nothing adequate can be given in experience, the moral ideas, are not, on that account, something transcendent, that is, something of which we cannot even determine the concept sufficiently or of which it is uncertain whether there is any object corresponding to it at all, as is the case with the ideas of speculative reason;
-
Kant's description of moral ideas in the Critique of Practical Reason also seems helpful: [I]f I understand by an idea a perfection to which nothing adequate can be given in experience, the moral ideas, are not, on that account, something transcendent, that is, something of which we cannot even determine the concept sufficiently or of which it is uncertain whether there is any object corresponding to it at all, as is the case with the ideas of speculative reason;
-
-
-
-
93
-
-
35648990940
-
-
instead, the moral ideas, as archetypes of practical perfection, serve as the indispensable rule of moral conduct and also as the standard of comparison. (Kant, Practical Philosophy, 5:127). Here Kant is referring to moral virtues such as wisdom, and holiness. This idea seems quite close to Derrida's in the fact that they are impossible - nothing in experience can match them - but are not transcendent, and can be used as a standard.
-
instead, the moral ideas, as archetypes of practical perfection, serve as the indispensable rule of moral conduct and also as the standard of comparison. (Kant, Practical Philosophy, 5:127). Here Kant is referring to moral virtues such as wisdom, and holiness. This idea seems quite close to Derrida's in the fact that they are impossible - nothing in experience can match them - but are not transcendent, and can be used as a standard.
-
-
-
-
99
-
-
35649024861
-
-
and Olivia Custer, Kant after Derrida: Inventing Oneself out of an Impossible Choice, in Rothfield, Kant after Derrida, 171-204.
-
and Olivia Custer, "Kant after Derrida: Inventing Oneself out of an Impossible Choice," in Rothfield, Kant after Derrida, 171-204.
-
-
-
-
101
-
-
35649004945
-
Should Radical Evil Be Forgiven?
-
See, ed. Tom Mason Totowa, N.J, Humana Press, where I argue that Derrida's view of forgiveness implies that the onus is on the victim to forgive, although he does not argue for it explicitly
-
See Marguerite La Caze, "Should Radical Evil Be Forgiven?" in Forensic Psychiatry: Influences of Evil, ed. Tom Mason (Totowa, N.J.: Humana Press, 2006), 273-93, where I argue that Derrida's view of forgiveness implies that the onus is on the victim to forgive, although he does not argue for it explicitly.
-
(2006)
Forensic Psychiatry: Influences of Evil
, pp. 273-293
-
-
Caze, M.L.1
-
104
-
-
35649026341
-
-
Kant, Practical Philosophy, 4:403. Kant observed that even experts could lack judgment in his essay on theory and practice: [T]here can be theoreticians who can never in their lives become practical because they are lacking in judgment, for example, physicians or jurists who did well in their schooling but who are at a loss when they have to give an expert opinion.
-
Kant, Practical Philosophy, 4:403. Kant observed that even experts could lack judgment in his essay on theory and practice: [T]here can be theoreticians who can never in their lives become practical because they are lacking in judgment, for example, physicians or jurists who did well in their schooling but who are at a loss when they have to give an expert opinion.
-
-
-
-
105
-
-
35648969202
-
-
(Ibid., 8:275) He thinks that this is due to a lack of the 'natural talent' of judgment. But, as Kant makes clear, this difficulty in judgment applies to certain professional fields, not to ethics.
-
(Ibid., 8:275) He thinks that this is due to a lack of the 'natural talent' of judgment. But, as Kant makes clear, this difficulty in judgment applies to certain professional fields, not to ethics.
-
-
-
-
106
-
-
35648987187
-
-
Ibid., 4:407-8.
-
, vol.4
, pp. 407-408
-
-
Derrida1
-
112
-
-
35648929382
-
-
Ibid., 6:314-15. Kant makes a distinction between active citizens, who are independent and can vote, and passive ones, who he argues are dependent on the will of others.
-
Ibid., 6:314-15. Kant makes a distinction between active citizens, who are independent and can vote, and passive ones, who he argues are dependent on the will of others.
-
-
-
-
113
-
-
35648932503
-
-
Ibid., 6:320, 6:333.
-
Ibid., 6:320, 6:333.
-
-
-
-
114
-
-
0141627481
-
Kant and Capital Punishment Today
-
Nelson Potter, "Kant and Capital Punishment Today," Journal of Value Inquiry 36, nos. 2/3 (2002): 267-82.
-
(2002)
Journal of Value Inquiry
, vol.36
, Issue.2-3
, pp. 267-282
-
-
Potter, N.1
-
115
-
-
20444451885
-
-
trans. Jeff Fort Stanford, Calif, Stanford University Press
-
Jacques Derrida and Elisabeth Roudinesco, For What Tomorrow ... a Dialogue, trans. Jeff Fort (Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press, 2004), 148.
-
(2004)
For What Tomorrow ... a Dialogue
, pp. 148
-
-
Derrida, J.1
Roudinesco, E.2
-
116
-
-
35648990939
-
-
I do not have the space to argue for my position here, but I think it is important to indicate the points where I think Kant is misguided. Of course there are other points, such as his view of the status of wives and servants (Kant, Practical Philosophy, 6:277, 6:315), which are deeply problematic; I have only focused on two important issues.
-
I do not have the space to argue for my position here, but I think it is important to indicate the points where I think Kant is misguided. Of course there are other points, such as his view of the status of wives and servants (Kant, Practical Philosophy, 6:277, 6:315), which are deeply problematic; I have only focused on two important issues.
-
-
-
-
118
-
-
35648988545
-
-
Arendt contends that ethics involves a concern with the self whereas politics involves a concern with the world; Arendt, Responsibility and Judgment, 153. Michel Foucault believes that subjects must be free to practice ethical relations with themselves and others;
-
Arendt contends that ethics involves a concern with the self whereas politics involves a concern with the world; Arendt, Responsibility and Judgment, 153. Michel Foucault believes that subjects must be free to practice ethical relations with themselves and others;
-
-
-
|