메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 52, Issue 1, 2007, Pages 58-87

Ethics in stoic philosophy

Author keywords

Ethics; Foundations; Holism; Metaphysics; Nature; Physics; Virtue

Indexed keywords


EID: 34548731985     PISSN: 00318868     EISSN: 15685284     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1163/156852807X177968     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (51)

References (62)
  • 1
    • 34548797863 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Diogenes Laertius VII40
    • Diogenes Laertius VII40
  • 2
    • 34548783075 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Marcus is writing a diary for himself, and the works of Epictetus that we have arc most plausibly seen as records of his teachings to students who were also learning logic, physics and ethics in more technical ways
    • Marcus is writing a diary for himself, and the works of Epictetus that we have arc most plausibly seen as records of his teachings to students who were also learning logic, physics and ethics in more technical ways.
  • 3
    • 34548799012 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Diogenes Laertius VIII 39-41; cf. Sextus PH II 13.
    • Diogenes Laertius VIII 39-41; cf. Sextus PH II 13.
  • 4
    • 34548798439 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sextus, M VII 20-23
    • M , vol.7 , pp. 20-23
    • Sextus1
  • 5
    • 34548737473 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • translation from Sextus Empiricus, Against the Logicians, translated by Richard Bett, Cambridge University Press, 2005 (Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy). In the corresponding short passage at PH II 12-13 Sextus reports, without rationale, a Stoic order logic-physics-ethics, which is also the order which Sextus himself follows in both his works.
    • translation from Sextus Empiricus, Against the Logicians, translated by Richard Bett, Cambridge University Press, 2005 (Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy). In the corresponding short passage at PH II 12-13 Sextus reports, without rationale, a Stoic order logic-physics-ethics, which is also the order which Sextus himself follows in both his works.
  • 6
    • 34548727164 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Plutarch, de St. Rep. 1035 A-B. The passage will be discussed below. Chrysippus introduces the division as one of different kinds of theoremata.
    • Plutarch, de St. Rep. 1035 A-B. The passage will be discussed below. Chrysippus introduces the division as one of different kinds of theoremata.
  • 7
    • 34548749012 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Diogenes Laertius VII 84; the whole passage is 84-116. The division of Eudorus (Stobaeus II 42.7-45.10) differs in its organization, and appears to cover a variety of theories, but the topics covered are similar: impulse, action, ends and objectives, virtue and preferred things, as well as more specific topics such as skills and practices, friendship and love, pleasure, reputation and relationships.
    • Diogenes Laertius VII 84; the whole passage is 84-116. The division of Eudorus (Stobaeus II 42.7-45.10) differs in its organization, and appears to cover a variety of theories, but the topics covered are similar: impulse, action, ends and objectives, virtue and preferred things, as well as more specific topics such as skills and practices, friendship and love, pleasure, reputation and relationships.
  • 8
    • 34548763418 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Diogenes and Arius passages are compared, and parallel passages listed, in my Introduction to Ario Didimo, Diogene Laerzio: etica stoica, a cura di Carlo Natali, introduzione di Julia Annas, Laterza, 1999.
    • The Diogenes and Arius passages are compared, and parallel passages listed, in my Introduction to Ario Didimo, Diogene Laerzio: etica stoica, a cura di Carlo Natali, introduzione di Julia Annas, Laterza, 1999.
  • 10
    • 77249094654 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Katerina Ierodiakonou, 'The Stoic Division of Philosophy,' Phronesis XXXVIII/1 (1993), 57-74.1 have learnt much from this excellent article.
    • Katerina Ierodiakonou, 'The Stoic Division of Philosophy,' Phronesis XXXVIII/1 (1993), 57-74.1 have learnt much from this excellent article.
  • 12
    • 34548784740 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ierodiakonou pp. 61-67, especially p. 67
    • Ierodiakonou pp. 61-67, especially p. 67.
  • 13
    • 34548743264 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Stoic metaphors for philosophy bring out just how closely unified the parts are, comparing philosophy to an egg, with logic as its protecting shell, and different pairings of physics and ethics with the yolk and the white, or to an animal, with logic as its supporting bones and different pairings of physics and ethics with flesh and animating spirit. See Ierodiakonou, pp. 71-74.1 agree with her that the metaphor of a garden (and that of a city in the Diogenes passage, which she does not discuss) is less satisfactory for representing the unity of Stoic philosophy.
    • Stoic metaphors for philosophy bring out just how closely unified the parts are, comparing philosophy to an egg, with logic as its protecting shell, and different pairings of physics and ethics with the yolk and the white, or to an animal, with logic as its supporting bones and different pairings of physics and ethics with flesh and animating spirit. See Ierodiakonou, pp. 71-74.1 agree with her that the metaphor of a garden (and that of a city in the Diogenes passage, which she does not discuss) is less satisfactory for representing the unity of Stoic philosophy.
  • 14
    • 34548727161 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am very grateful to Brad Inwood for pointing out to me this very important passage, and for extensive helpful discussion of the issues raised in this paper
    • I am very grateful to Brad Inwood for pointing out to me this very important passage, and for extensive helpful discussion of the issues raised in this paper.
  • 15
    • 34548771576 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rem utilem desideras et ad sapientiam properanti necessariam, dividi philosophiam et ingens corpus eius in membra disponi. Facilius enim per partes in cognitionem totius adducimur. Utinam quidam quemadmodum universa mundi fades in conspectum venit, itaphilosophia tota nobis posset occurrere, simillimum mundo spectaculum. Profecto enim omnes mortales in admirationem sui raperet relictis its, quae nunc magna magnorum ignorantia credimus, Sapientis quidem animus totam molem eius amplectitur nee minus illam velociter obit quam caelum ocies nostra; nobis autem, quibusperrumpenda caligo est et quorum visus in proximo deficit, singula quaeque ostendifacilius possunt universi nondum capacibus. Seneca, Letter 89,1 -2. The idea of philosophy as a view of the big picture also dominates the following Letter 90, where Seneca relics on it to refute Posidonius' view that it was philosophy which discovered technological devices to improve human life. Far from this being the case
    • Rem utilem desideras et ad sapientiam properanti necessariam, dividi philosophiam et ingens corpus eius in membra disponi. Facilius enim per partes in cognitionem totius adducimur. Utinam quidam quemadmodum universa mundi fades in conspectum venit, itaphilosophia tota nobis posset occurrere, simillimum mundo spectaculum. Profecto enim omnes mortales in admirationem sui raperet relictis its, quae nunc magna magnorum ignorantia credimus... Sapientis quidem animus totam molem eius amplectitur nee minus illam velociter obit quam caelum ocies nostra; nobis autem, quibusperrumpenda caligo est et quorum visus in proximo deficit, singula quaeque ostendifacilius possunt universi nondum capacibus. Seneca, Letter 89,1 -2. The idea of philosophy as a view of the big picture also dominates the following Letter 90, where Seneca relics on it to refute Posidonius' view that it was philosophy which discovered technological devices to improve human life. Far from this being the case, Seneca claims, philosophy judges whether such devices when invented do in fact improve, rather than corrupting, human life. The need to integrate our beliefs in order to achieve knowledge is also stressed more informally in Letter 84.
  • 16
    • 34548752113 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • He criticises the Peripatetics for redundancy, the Epicureans and Cyrenaics for claiming to reject parts which they recognized in practice, and Aristo of Chios for wrongly limiting the philosopher's sphere of concern.
    • He criticises the Peripatetics for redundancy, the Epicureans and Cyrenaics for claiming to reject parts which they recognized in practice, and Aristo of Chios for wrongly limiting the philosopher's sphere of concern.
  • 17
    • 34548797475 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Letter 89, 14-18. Ethics is divided into correct estimation of value, ordering of impulse and harmonizing of action with the first two. Physics is the study of the corporeal and incorporeal. Logic is divided into dialectic and rhetoric.
    • Letter 89, 14-18. Ethics is divided into correct estimation of value, ordering of impulse and harmonizing of action with the first two. Physics is the study of the corporeal and incorporeal. Logic is divided into dialectic and rhetoric.
  • 18
    • 34548787614 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The MSS reading, has been restored in M. Marcovich's Tcubner text, and in Long and Sedlcy's text of the passage (26B in Long and Sedley, The Hellenistic Philosophers, vols 1 and 2, Cambridge, 1987). Cobct's conjecture has the merit of making the phrase concern a single issue, the mixing of the parts, whereas the MSS reading brings in two separate issues, that the parts are mixed and that none of them is preferred. There is no good reason, however, for rejecting the MSS reading, and no reason to think that the specifically Stoic doctrine of total mixture is at issue here.
    • The MSS reading, has been restored in M. Marcovich's Tcubner text, and in Long and Sedlcy's text of the passage (26B in Long and Sedley, The Hellenistic Philosophers, vols 1 and 2, Cambridge, 1987). Cobct's conjecture has the merit of making the phrase concern a single issue, the mixing of the parts, whereas the MSS reading brings in two separate issues, that the parts are mixed and that none of them is preferred. There is no good reason, however, for rejecting the MSS reading, and no reason to think that the specifically Stoic doctrine of total mixture is at issue here.
  • 19
    • 34548708886 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I Plutarch, de St. rep.1050b.
    • I Plutarch, de St. rep.1050b.
  • 20
    • 34548739974 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The passage traditionally numbered 6 in Stobacus Eclogae II (75.11-78,17), pp 36.25-42.8 in Arius Didymus: Epitome of Stoic Ethics, translated and edited by A. J. Pomeroy, Society of Biblical Literature Texts and Translations 44, Graeco-Roman 14, Atlanta, Ga., 1999.
    • The passage traditionally numbered 6 in Stobacus Eclogae II (75.11-78,17), pp 36.25-42.8 in Arius Didymus: Epitome of Stoic Ethics, translated and edited by A. J. Pomeroy, Society of Biblical Literature Texts and Translations 44, Graeco-Roman 14, Atlanta, Ga., 1999.
  • 21
    • 34548806798 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Stobaeus II, 75-11-76.8, Pomeroy 36.30-38.9 (however, I do not accept his 〈η〉 in line 76.3 (Pomeroy 38.2)).
    • Stobaeus II, 75-11-76.8, Pomeroy 36.30-38.9 (however, I do not accept his 〈η〉 in line 76.3 (Pomeroy 38.2)).
  • 22
    • 34548738796 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Stobaeus II 77.16-78.6 (Pomeroy 40.11-32).
    • Stobaeus II 77.16-78.6 (Pomeroy 40.11-32).
  • 23
    • 34548764745 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • They can well be made from within one part of philosophy, as these are in the ethical part; they simply call attention to the need to study another part fully to understand these claims
    • They can well be made from within one part of philosophy, as these are in the ethical part; they simply call attention to the need to study another part fully to understand these claims.
  • 24
    • 34548717408 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Stoics' eudaimonism is principally grounded in their beliefs about the relation in which human beings stand to a determinate and providentially governed world.' A.A. Long, 'Stoic Eudaimonism', pp. 179-201 of Long, Stoic Studies, University of California Press, 1996.
    • "The Stoics' eudaimonism is principally grounded in their beliefs about the relation in which human beings stand to a determinate and providentially governed world.' A.A. Long, 'Stoic Eudaimonism', pp. 179-201 of Long, Stoic Studies, University of California Press, 1996.
  • 25
    • 84963108176 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Stoic ethics is ultimately parasitical on physics,' A.A. Long, The Stoic Conception of Evil,' Philosophical Quarterly 18 (1968), 329-43, 341.
    • 'Stoic ethics is ultimately parasitical on physics,' A.A. Long, "The Stoic Conception of Evil,' Philosophical Quarterly 18 (1968), 329-43, 341.
  • 26
    • 34548745569 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'The foundations of Stoic ethics are to be sought.... in cosmology or theology.' Gisela Striker, 'Following Nature', in Striker, Essays on Hellenistic Epistemology and Ethics, Cambridge, 1996, pp. 221-280, p. 231.
    • 'The foundations of Stoic ethics are to be sought.... in cosmology or theology.' Gisela Striker, 'Following Nature', in Striker, Essays on Hellenistic Epistemology and Ethics, Cambridge, 1996, pp. 221-280, p. 231.
  • 27
    • 34548792685 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One example is A.A. Long in Hellenistic Philosophy, second edition, Duckworth, 1986, pp. 179-209. In contrast, R.W, Sharpies, in Stoics, Epicureans and Sceptics, Routledge, 1996, pp. 100-113, clearly discusses the topics of the ethical part of Stoic philosophy, in a eudaimonist framework, before raising the issue of their relation to Stoic physics.
    • One example is A.A. Long in Hellenistic Philosophy, second edition, Duckworth, 1986, pp. 179-209. In contrast, R.W, Sharpies, in Stoics, Epicureans and Sceptics, Routledge, 1996, pp. 100-113, clearly discusses the topics of the ethical part of Stoic philosophy, in a eudaimonist framework, before raising the issue of their relation to Stoic physics.
  • 28
    • 34548748453 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Meditations XI, 10, translated ny Robin Hard in C
    • Gill ed, Wordsworth Editions, Ware
    • Marcus Aurelius, Meditations XI, 10, translated ny Robin Hard in C. Gill (ed.), Marcus Aurelius, Meditations, Meditations, Wordsworth Editions, Ware, 1997.
    • (1997) Marcus Aurelius, Meditations, Meditations
    • Aurelius, M.1
  • 30
    • 34548760002 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • J. Cooper, 'Eudaimonism and the Appeal to Nature in the Morality of Happiness: Comments on Julia Annas' The Morality of Happiness', Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LV #3 (1995), 587-599, quotes from p. 596.
    • J. Cooper, 'Eudaimonism and the Appeal to Nature in the Morality of Happiness: Comments on Julia Annas' The Morality of Happiness', Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, vol. LV #3 (1995), 587-599, quotes from p. 596.
  • 31
    • 34548711626 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Similar claims can be found in N. White, Individualand Conflict in Greek Ethics, Oxford, 2002, p. 312: 'Grasping the goodness of the kosmos is essential, the Stoics maintain, for an understanding of the value of anything whatsoever', and Striker, 'Following Nature', pp. 230-231.
    • Similar claims can be found in N. White, Individualand Conflict in Greek Ethics, Oxford, 2002, p. 312: 'Grasping the goodness of the kosmos is essential, the Stoics maintain, for an understanding of the value of anything whatsoever', and Striker, 'Following Nature', pp. 230-231.
  • 32
    • 34548739375 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cooper secs as very limited any revisions brought about within the motivational set one brings to philosophy, augmented only by a commitment to a eudaimonistic structure; this leads him to identify appeal to Providence as an 'external' as opposed to an 'internal' reason in Bernard Williams' sense 1995, p. 590, Williams' view, however, is that I have a reason to do something if there is a sound deliberative route to my doing this from the set of motivations I already have, Sound deliberative route' is not limited to instrumental efficiency, and 'motivation' is not limited to desire, but Williams explicitly holds that I do not have an ethical reason if my motivational set does not antecedently contain ethical motivations. For Williams, external reasons are reasons where there is no sound deliberative route to my motivational set so understood, and he doubts that there arc any. In the context of ancient Stoicism, we reach claims about Williams' external reasons well within the ethical
    • Cooper secs as very limited any revisions brought about within the motivational set one brings to philosophy, augmented only by a commitment to a eudaimonistic structure; this leads him to identify appeal to Providence as an 'external' as opposed to an 'internal' reason in Bernard Williams' sense (1995, p. 590). Williams' view, however, is that I have a reason to do something if there is a sound deliberative route to my doing this from the set of motivations I already have. 'Sound deliberative route' is not limited to instrumental efficiency, and 'motivation' is not limited to desire, but Williams explicitly holds that I do not have an ethical reason if my motivational set does not antecedently contain ethical motivations. For Williams, external reasons are reasons where there is no sound deliberative route to my motivational set so understood, and he doubts that there arc any. In the context of ancient Stoicism, we reach claims about Williams' external reasons well within the ethical part of philosophy, in conclusions about virtue and emotion, for example. Williams' 'external reasons', then, have nothing to do with appeal to the cosmos as opposed to eudaimonistic thinking, See Williams, 'Internal Reasons and the Obscurity of Blame', pp, 35-45 of Williams, Making Sense of Humanity, Cambridge, 1995, and 'Internal and External Reasons' (a reply to John McDowell), pp, 186-194 of J.EJ. Altham and Ross Harrison (cds.), World, Mind and Ethics, Cambridge, 1995.
  • 34
    • 34548789926 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Panactius, for example, rejected divination and the conflagration (Testimonia 130-140, in Panezio di Rodi, Testimoniame, ed. F. Alcsse, Naples, Bibliopolis, 1997);
    • Panactius, for example, rejected divination and the conflagration (Testimonia 130-140, in Panezio di Rodi, Testimoniame, ed. F. Alcsse, Naples, Bibliopolis, 1997);
  • 35
    • 34548744982 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • sec chapter 3 of F. Alesse, Panezio di Rodi e la tradizione stoka. Panaetius' orthodoxy is vigorously defended in T. Tieleman, 'Panaetius' place in the history of Stoicism', forthcoming in the Proceedings of the Tenth Symposium Hellenisticum.
    • sec chapter 3 of F. Alesse, Panezio di Rodi e la tradizione stoka. Panaetius' orthodoxy is vigorously defended in T. Tieleman, 'Panaetius' place in the history of Stoicism', forthcoming in the Proceedings of the Tenth Symposium Hellenisticum.
  • 36
    • 34548705757 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As we shall see below, this thought encourages the assumption that physics will be the way to present Stoic ethics.
    • As we shall see below, this thought encourages the assumption that physics will be the way to present Stoic ethics.
  • 37
    • 34548763607 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The appeal, or not, of Providence to moderns is an entirely different issue. As we shall see below, one attraction of the foundationalist interpretation of Stoic ethics is that it enables scholars to make a neat contrast between Stoic ethics, taken to depend on accepting Providence, and modern ethical theories which do not, and thus to represent Stoic ethics as entirely distinct from modern ethical theories
    • The appeal, or not, of Providence to moderns is an entirely different issue. As we shall see below, one attraction of the foundationalist interpretation of Stoic ethics is that it enables scholars to make a neat contrast between Stoic ethics, taken to depend on accepting Providence, and modern ethical theories which do not, and thus to represent Stoic ethics as entirely distinct from modern ethical theories.
  • 38
    • 34548772717 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Does this point support the position argued for here, as opposed to that of the foundationalists ? It certainly explains why many modern scholars have thought that physics, particularly Providence, should be in some way essential for 'Stoic ethics' (an area which then no longer corresponds to the ethical part of Stoic philosophy as described in the ancient sources).
    • Does this point support the position argued for here, as opposed to that of the foundationalists ? It certainly explains why many modern scholars have thought that physics, particularly Providence, should be in some way essential for 'Stoic ethics' (an area which then no longer corresponds to the ethical part of Stoic philosophy as described in the ancient sources).
  • 39
    • 34548792145 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I have not here considered the possible role, in interpreting ancient Stoicism, of widespread assumptions in modern ethical debate to the effect that ethics should have foundations of a metaphysical kind. It is possible that scholars have brought these assumptions to the ancient texts. Modern debates about ethical foundations are too dissimilar to ancient concerns to be themselves usefully applied.
    • I have not here considered the possible role, in interpreting ancient Stoicism, of widespread assumptions in modern ethical debate to the effect that ethics should have foundations of a metaphysical kind. It is possible that scholars have brought these assumptions to the ancient texts. Modern debates about ethical foundations are too dissimilar to ancient concerns to be themselves usefully applied.
  • 40
    • 34548715047 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A.A. Long, 'Stoic eudaimonism', p, 186 and later; the phrase is repeated and emphasized, The phrase 'radical intuition' is on p, 185.
    • A.A. Long, 'Stoic eudaimonism', p, 186 and later; the phrase is repeated and emphasized, The phrase 'radical intuition' is on p, 185.
  • 41
    • 34548760601 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, T. Tieleman refers to 'repeated statements by Chrysippus to the effect that morality trickles down from the cosmic order and that philosophical ethics starts from theology', Chrysippus'On Affections, Brill, Leiden, 2003, p. 143.
    • For example, T. Tieleman refers to 'repeated statements by Chrysippus to the effect that morality trickles down from the cosmic order and that philosophical ethics starts from theology', Chrysippus'On Affections, Brill, Leiden, 2003, p. 143.
  • 42
    • 34548754834 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Diogenes Laertius VII 87-88; I use the Teubncr text of M. Marcovich (Stuttgart, 1999).
    • Diogenes Laertius VII 87-88; I use the Teubncr text of M. Marcovich (Stuttgart, 1999).
  • 43
    • 79956991692 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is a real contrast with the Arius passage, in which this topic is not treated. This may be due to clumsiness in the way the original has been abbreviated, however, and we should not draw far-reaching conclusions from it about the passages original structure and approach. Malcolm Schoficld, in 'Stoic Ethics, pp. 233-256 of B. Inwood (ed, The Cambridge Companion to the Stoics, Cambridge, 2003) finds the Arius passage to be an example of 'working through the key concepts of Stoic ethics' as opposed to explaining and arguing for some key Stoic thesis as Cicero does in deFinibus III
    • This is a real contrast with the Arius passage, in which this topic is not treated. This may be due to clumsiness in the way the original has been abbreviated, however, and we should not draw far-reaching conclusions from it about the passages original structure and approach. Malcolm Schoficld, in 'Stoic Ethics' (pp. 233-256 of B. Inwood (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to the Stoics, Cambridge, 2003) finds the Arius passage to be an example of 'working through the key concepts of Stoic ethics' as opposed to explaining and arguing for some key Stoic thesis (as Cicero does in deFinibus III).
  • 44
    • 34548707449 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Diogenes VII 87-88
    • Diogenes VII 87-88.
  • 45
    • 34548717409 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It has been under-appreciated that argument is needed to establish that the explication here in physical terms amounts to providing a foundation, perhaps because of a widespread modern assumption that explanation provides foundations, As we have seen, not only has no suitable notion of foundation been argued for here, but foundations do not fit into the Stoic project
    • It has been under-appreciated that argument is needed to establish that the explication here in physical terms amounts to providing a foundation - perhaps because of a widespread modern assumption that explanation provides foundations, As we have seen, not only has no suitable notion of foundation been argued for here, but foundations do not fit into the Stoic project.
  • 46
    • 34548753769 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course there are modern foundationalist theories which do claim this, by reducing or eliminating one kind of item in favour of its foundation, but this modern concern has no footing in ancient Stoicism
    • Of course there are modern foundationalist theories which do claim this, by reducing or eliminating one kind of item in favour of its foundation, but this modern concern has no footing in ancient Stoicism.
  • 47
    • 34548750732 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. C. Gill, The Stoic Theory of Ethical Development: In What Sense Is Nature a Norm?', pp. 101-125 of Jan Szaif and Matthias Lutz-Bachmann (eds.), Was ist fur den Menschen Gutef/What Is Good for a Human Being?, dc Gruytcr, Berlin/New York, 2004.
    • Cf. C. Gill, "The Stoic Theory of Ethical Development: In What Sense Is Nature a Norm?', pp. 101-125 of Jan Szaif and Matthias Lutz-Bachmann (eds.), Was ist fur den Menschen Gutef/What Is Good for a Human Being?, dc Gruytcr, Berlin/New York, 2004.
  • 48
    • 34548774328 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One example suggested to me in discussion of the paper at Oxford is the way that Cicero's De Fato opens with a fragmentary reference to ethics, followed by a fuller one to a problem arising from fate within logic. Gill's work stresses the way that the treatments of fate and determinism in the different parts of Stoic philosophy are mutually fortifying; cf, article in n, 43, pp. 114-116.
    • One example suggested to me in discussion of the paper at Oxford is the way that Cicero's De Fato opens with a fragmentary reference to ethics, followed by a fuller one to a problem arising from fate within logic. Gill's work stresses the way that the treatments of fate and determinism in the different parts of Stoic philosophy are mutually fortifying; cf, article in n, 43, pp. 114-116.
  • 49
    • 34548708887 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The whole passage is at De Stoicorum Repugnantiis, 1035 A-F, I use the text of H. Cherniss in the Loeb edition, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass., 1976.
    • The whole passage is at De Stoicorum Repugnantiis, 1035 A-F, I use the text of H. Cherniss in the Loeb edition, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass., 1976.
  • 50
    • 34548711097 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Russian source
    • Russian source
  • 51
    • 34548707745 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Russian source
    • Russian source
  • 52
    • 34548768573 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Even Long, a staunch foundationalist, accepts that 'we may be reading a good deal of Chrysippus in Arius Didymus', in passages which discuss ethical topics with no mention of physics. A. A Long, 'Arius Didymus and the Exposition of Stoic Ethics,' in Long, Stoic Studies, pp. 107-133.
    • Even Long, a staunch foundationalist, accepts that 'we may be reading a good deal of Chrysippus in Arius Didymus', in passages which discuss ethical topics with no mention of physics. A. A Long, 'Arius Didymus and the Exposition of Stoic Ethics,' in Long, Stoic Studies, pp. 107-133.
  • 53
    • 34548757711 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1035 C-D. Note that Cherniss translates in a way which builds Plutarch's view of the last quotation into the translation; see below n. 55
    • 1035 C-D. Note that Cherniss translates in a way which builds Plutarch's view of the last quotation into the translation; see below n. 55.
  • 54
    • 34548784738 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I do not know what Ierodiakonou has in mind by strict and highly scientific account, but, as we have seen, for the Stoics a 'scientific' account is not one in which ethics has foundations in the modern sense, but rather one in which ethics and physics arc integrated in a way ultimately progressing towards the viewpoint of the wise person
    • Ierodiakonou, "The Stoic Division of Philosophy', p. 71. I do not know what Ierodiakonou has in mind by strict and highly scientific account', but, as we have seen, for the Stoics a 'scientific' account is not one in which ethics has foundations in the modern sense, but rather one in which ethics and physics arc integrated in a way ultimately progressing towards the viewpoint of the wise person.
    • The Stoic Division of Philosophy , pp. 71
    • Ierodiakonou1
  • 55
    • 34548746699 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The phrase is Chcmiss translates 'as opportunity offers'
    • The phrase is Chcmiss translates 'as opportunity offers'
  • 56
    • 34548747278 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Russian source
    • Russian source
  • 57
    • 34548740566 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Though it is oddly introduced as a worse problem
    • Though it is oddly introduced as a worse problem
  • 58
    • 34548732242 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There is an under-scrutinized oddity in the fourth quotation, which says that we should attach the account of goods and evils to these things, for there is no other better starting-point and point of reference for them. Chemiss translates as Plutarch wants us to read this: 'since good and evil have no better beginning and point of reference, presumably 'than these things, assuming 'these things' to be physical principles. Yet this is followed by oδ which should introduce another consideration to the same effect as we have had, and what follows is a reason for giving ethics some kind of primacy: physical theorizing is undertaken for nothing other than discriminating goods and evils, What precedes the oδ should thus likewise be a reason for giving ethics, not physics, some kind of primacy. This is what we get if we read ov as referring not to goods and evils but rather to the preceding whatever they are, This gives a much less convoluted reading of the Gre
    • There is an under-scrutinized oddity in the fourth quotation, which says that we should attach the account of goods and evils to these things, for there is no other better starting-point and point of reference for them. Chemiss translates as Plutarch wants us to read this: 'since good and evil have no better beginning and point of reference' - presumably 'than these things', assuming 'these things' to be physical principles. Yet this is followed by oδ which should introduce another consideration to the same effect as we have had - and what follows is a reason for giving ethics some kind of primacy: physical theorizing is undertaken for nothing other than discriminating goods and evils, What precedes the oδ should thus likewise be a reason for giving ethics, not physics, some kind of primacy. This is what we get if we read ov as referring not to goods and evils but rather to the preceding (whatever they are). This gives a much less convoluted reading of the Greek sentence. If this is right, then Plutarch is forcing this quotation to appear more parallel to, or supportive of, the previous two than it really is.
  • 59
    • 34548789359 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Long puts extraordinary weight on the Diogenes passage, especially in The Logical Basis of Stoic Ethics,' where he says (p, 153) that it 'is almost certainly our most authoritative testimony for the primary principles'. I have myself countered that what we find in Cicero 'is a normal ancient presentation of Stoic ethics, different in kind from the metaphysically based discussions of which we have some fragments,' p. 607 of' Reply to Cooper, Philosophy and PhenomenologicalResearch LV #3 (1995), 599-610, on the grounds that Cicero is our most intelligent ancient source and his presentation is the result of debate and argument. Both approaches try to privilege one text over the other, a project which now seems to me a mistake.
    • Long puts extraordinary weight on the Diogenes passage, especially in "The Logical Basis of Stoic Ethics,' where he says (p, 153) that it 'is almost certainly our most authoritative testimony for the primary principles'. I have myself countered that what we find in Cicero 'is a normal ancient presentation of Stoic ethics, different in kind from the metaphysically based discussions of which we have some fragments,' p. 607 of' Reply to Cooper, Philosophy and PhenomenologicalResearch LV #3 (1995), 599-610, on the grounds that Cicero is our most intelligent ancient source and his presentation is the result of debate and argument. Both approaches try to privilege one text over the other, a project which now seems to me a mistake.
  • 60
    • 34548801687 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As for example in 'Stoic Ethics' by Brad Inwood and Pierluigi Donini, pp. 675-738 of K. Algract al. (cds.), The Cambridge History of Hellenistic Philosophy, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1999. Gisela Striker (n. 25) introduces physical foundations for Stoic ethics by way of meeting what she takes to be requirements on ethical theory. I critically discuss her reconstruction of Stoic ethics, which she judges harshly, in 'From Nature to Happiness,'Apeiron XXXI # 1 (1998), 59-73.
    • As for example in 'Stoic Ethics' by Brad Inwood and Pierluigi Donini, pp. 675-738 of K. Algract al. (cds.), The Cambridge History of Hellenistic Philosophy, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1999. Gisela Striker (n. 25) introduces physical foundations for Stoic ethics by way of meeting what she takes to be requirements on ethical theory. I critically discuss her reconstruction of Stoic ethics, which she judges harshly, in 'From Nature to Happiness,'Apeiron XXXI # 1 (1998), 59-73.
  • 61
    • 34548713288 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We should remember that 'mixed' presentations are in themselves no guarantee that the author has achieved this level of understanding. Physical and ethical propositions can be discussed together in mutually illuminating ways without the author having a full grasp of either of the parts of philosophy concerned. Marcus' Meditations illustrates this; see my 'Marcus Aurelius: Ethics and its Background'. Rhizai 2 (2004), 103-119.
    • We should remember that 'mixed' presentations are in themselves no guarantee that the author has achieved this level of understanding. Physical and ethical propositions can be discussed together in mutually illuminating ways without the author having a full grasp of either of the parts of philosophy concerned. Marcus' Meditations illustrates this; see my 'Marcus Aurelius: Ethics and its Background'. Rhizai 2 (2004), 103-119.
  • 62
    • 34548736343 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am very grateful to Brad Inwood, Christopher Gill, Bob Sharpies, Eric Brown and Clerk Shaw for discussion and written comments on earlier versions of this paper, I am also grateful to my audience for the version of this paper presented at the fiftieth meeting of the Southern Association for Ancient Philosophy at Corpus Christi College, Oxford in September 2005, and in particular Peter Adamson, Gabor Betegh, Sarah Broadie, David Sedley, Malcolm Schofield and David Charles.
    • I am very grateful to Brad Inwood, Christopher Gill, Bob Sharpies, Eric Brown and Clerk Shaw for discussion and written comments on earlier versions of this paper, I am also grateful to my audience for the version of this paper presented at the fiftieth meeting of the Southern Association for Ancient Philosophy at Corpus Christi College, Oxford in September 2005, and in particular Peter Adamson, Gabor Betegh, Sarah Broadie, David Sedley, Malcolm Schofield and David Charles.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.