메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 101, Issue 11, 2004, Pages 574-593

An inconsistency in direct reference theory
[No Author Info available]

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 34548551561     PISSN: 0022362X     EISSN: 19398549     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.5840/jphil20041011139     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (15)

References (10)
  • 1
    • 0009079214 scopus 로고
    • Rationality and Believing the Impossible
    • June
    • I do not include Ruth Marcus on this list because her views on propositions and the attitudes differ sharply from those of the others and would require a different style of response - see, for example, her "Rationality and Believing the Impossible," this JOURNAL, LXXV, 6 (June 1983): 321-37.
    • (1983) JOURNAL , vol.75 , Issue.6 , pp. 321-337
  • 2
    • 79956815340 scopus 로고
    • Semantics" and "pragmatics
    • New York: Oxford, and 166-176
    • I myself defended a form of direct reference theory (in "Semantics" and "Pragmatics," Quality and Concept (New York: Oxford 1982) pp. 157-66 and 166-76)
    • (1982) Quality and Concept , pp. 157-166
  • 3
    • 33744772257 scopus 로고
    • The Need for Abstract Entities
    • In what follows 'A' and 'B' are to be understood as proper names or common nouns. For convenience, I will often use single quotation marks where corner quotation marks are strictly called for
    • Alonzo Church, "The Need for Abstract Entities," American Academy of Arts and Sciences Proceedings, LXXX (1951): 100-13. In what follows 'A' and 'B' are to be understood as proper names or common nouns. For convenience, I will often use single quotation marks where corner quotation marks are strictly called for.
    • (1951) American Academy of Arts and Sciences Proceedings , vol.80 , pp. 100-113
    • Church, A.1
  • 4
    • 0004178922 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Harvard
    • Naming and Necessity (Cambridge: Harvard, 1980), pp. 142-44.
    • (1980) Naming and Necessity , pp. 142-144
  • 5
    • 13844251144 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chapter 8, New York: Oxford
    • Cf. chapter 8 in Scott Soames, Beyond Rigidity (New York: Oxford, 2002).
    • (2002) Beyond Rigidity
  • 6
    • 13844251144 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Soames, Beyond Rigidity, pp. 39-50. A similar problem befalls paraphrases that invoke other rigidifying devices (for example, "thick words"; see note 23). Likewise, it is not the case that what you learned was that 'Necessarily, Hesperus = Phosphorus' is true in English.
    • Beyond Rigidity , pp. 39-50
    • Soames, C.1
  • 7
    • 33748200063 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Propositions, Numbers, and the Problem of Arbitrary Identification
    • August
    • See also Joseph Moore, "Propositions, Numbers, and the Problem of Arbitrary Identification," Synthese, CXX, 2 (August 1999): 229-63;
    • (1999) Synthese , vol.120 , Issue.2 , pp. 229-263
    • Moore, J.1
  • 8
    • 33646878682 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Propositions and Objects of Thought
    • May
    • and Michael Jubien, "Propositions and Objects of Thought," Philosophical Studies, CIV, 1 (May 2001): 47-62.
    • (2001) Philosophical Studies , vol.104 , Issue.1 , pp. 47-62
    • Jubien, M.1
  • 9
    • 21244472093 scopus 로고
    • Essence and Modality
    • See my "A Solution to Frege's Puzzle"; and Kit Fine, "Essence and Modality," Philosophical Perspectives, VIII (1994): 1-16.
    • (1994) Philosophical Perspectives , vol.8 , pp. 1-16
    • Fine, K.1
  • 10
    • 33751580410 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Objectual Attitudes
    • April
    • See, for example, Graeme Forbes, "Objectual Attitudes," Linguistics and Philosophy, XXIII, 2, (April 2000): 141-83, for the idea of treating 'under mode of presenta-tion m′ as an operator.
    • (2000) Linguistics and Philosophy , vol.23 , Issue.2 , pp. 141-183
    • Forbes, G.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.