메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 13, Issue 3, 2007, Pages 293-318

Animal rights and animal experiments: An interest-based approach

Author keywords

Animals; Autonomy; Continued life; Experiments; Freedom; Interests; Prudential value; Rights; Sentience; Suffering; Well being

Indexed keywords


EID: 34548137303     PISSN: 13564765     EISSN: 15728692     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1007/s11158-007-9037-8     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (18)

References (46)
  • 1
    • 34548110114 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I say 'at least two camps', because there are in fact various philosophical resources with which to oppose animal experimentation. I focus on Peter Singer's utilitarian and Tom Regan's rights-based accounts, because they have been the most influential and garnered the greatest response (justifiably, in my view). For a good recent review of the literature on animal ethics within a broadly analytic approach see, Robert Garner, Animal Ethics (Cambridge: Polity, 2005).
    • I say 'at least two camps', because there are in fact various philosophical resources with which to oppose animal experimentation. I focus on Peter Singer's utilitarian and Tom Regan's rights-based accounts, because they have been the most influential and garnered the greatest response (justifiably, in my view). For a good recent review of the literature on animal ethics within a broadly analytic approach see, Robert Garner, Animal Ethics (Cambridge: Polity, 2005).
  • 2
    • 27944452642 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For approaches to animal ethics within the continental tradition, see Matthew Calarco and Peter Atterton, eds, New York: Continuum
    • For approaches to animal ethics within the continental tradition, see Matthew Calarco and Peter Atterton, (eds.), Animal Philosophy: Essential Readings in Continental Thought (New York: Continuum, 2004).
    • (2004) Animal Philosophy: Essential Readings in Continental Thought
  • 3
    • 0003956640 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • Joseph Raz, The Morality of Freedom (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1988), p. 166.
    • (1988) The Morality of Freedom , pp. 166
    • Raz, J.1
  • 4
    • 34548113364 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course, adopting a rights-based account is by no means the only means of tackling these types of ethical problems. For a taxonomy and critical evaluation of different approaches to tackling interest conflicts within animal ethics see Elisa Aaltola, Animal Ethics and Interest Conflicts, Ethics and the Environment 10/1 (2005) 19-48
    • Of course, adopting a rights-based account is by no means the only means of tackling these types of ethical problems. For a taxonomy and critical evaluation of different approaches to tackling interest conflicts within animal ethics see Elisa Aaltola, 'Animal Ethics and Interest Conflicts', Ethics and the Environment 10/1 (2005) 19-48.
  • 5
    • 0347908331 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a useful debate on the merits of the interest-based approach, to rights, including Raz's framework and the choice-based alternative, see, Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • For a useful debate on the merits of the interest-based approach, to rights, including Raz's framework and the choice-based alternative, see Matthew H. Kramer, Nigel E. Simmonds and Hillel Steiner, A Debate Over Rights, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998).
    • (1998) A Debate Over Rights
    • Kramer, M.H.1    Simmonds, N.E.2    Steiner, H.3
  • 6
    • 84963099598 scopus 로고
    • Rights
    • For one view that animals cannot possess rights, see
    • For one view that animals cannot possess rights, see H. J. McCloskey, 'Rights', The Philosophical Quarterly 15/59 (1965) 115-127.
    • (1965) The Philosophical Quarterly 15/59 , pp. 115-127
    • McCloskey, H.J.1
  • 7
    • 0004808243 scopus 로고
    • The Rights of Animals and Unborn Generations
    • For an alternative view claiming that animals can possess rights, see, William T. Blackstone ed, Athens: University of Georgia Press
    • For an alternative view claiming that animals can possess rights, see Joel Feinberg, 'The Rights of Animals and Unborn Generations', in William T. Blackstone (ed.), Philosophy and Environmental Crisis, (Athens: University of Georgia Press, 1974) 43-68.
    • (1974) Philosophy and Environmental Crisis , pp. 43-68
    • Feinberg, J.1
  • 8
    • 34548697287 scopus 로고
    • The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Joel Feinberg, The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law: Vol. 1 Harm to Others, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984), p. 34.
    • (1984) Harm to Others , vol.1 , pp. 34
    • Feinberg, J.1
  • 9
    • 84869944327 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Well-Being
    • Edward N. Zalta ed, Summer
    • Roger Crisp, 'Well-Being' in Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer, 2003), http://plato.stanford.edu/ archives/sum2003/entries/ well-being,
    • (2003) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
    • Crisp, R.1
  • 11
    • 34548130470 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This account of the strength of an interest is greatly influenced, by Jeff McMahan's account of the strength of what he calls 'time-relative interests, However, as I make clear later in the paper, my account differs in one important regard. See Jeff McMahan, The Ethics of Killing Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002, p. 80
    • This account of the strength of an interest is greatly influenced, by Jeff McMahan's account of the strength of what he calls 'time-relative interests'. However, as I make clear later in the paper, my account differs in one important regard. See Jeff McMahan, The Ethics of Killing (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002), p. 80.
  • 12
    • 34548127359 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 233.
  • 13
    • 34548130472 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 39.
  • 14
    • 0004259456 scopus 로고
    • See for example, 2nd edn London: Pimlico
    • See for example, Peter Singer, Animal Liberation, 2nd edn (London: Pimlico, 1995), pp. 7-17.
    • (1995) Animal Liberation , pp. 7-17
    • Singer, P.1
  • 16
    • 0344611278 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a philosophical argument calling into question the benefits of animal experiments, see, London: Routledge
    • For a philosophical argument calling into question the benefits of animal experiments, see Hugh LaFollette and Niall Shanks, Brute Science: Dilemmas of Animal Experimentation (London: Routledge, 1996).
    • (1996) Brute Science: Dilemmas of Animal Experimentation
    • LaFollette, H.1    Shanks, N.2
  • 17
    • 84929067399 scopus 로고
    • Rights in Conflict
    • Rights have been referred to as 'limits, trumps, and 'side-constraints' on aggregative policies. For examples, see
    • Rights have been referred to as 'limits', 'trumps', and 'side-constraints' on aggregative policies. For examples, see: Jeremy Waldron, 'Rights in Conflict', Ethics, 99/3 (1989) 503-519;
    • (1989) Ethics , vol.99 , Issue.3 , pp. 503-519
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 20
    • 34548113359 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Another important advocate of this relationship-based approach is Mary Midgley; see her Animals and Why they Matter, (Athens: University of Georgia Press, 1984).
    • Another important advocate of this relationship-based approach is Mary Midgley; see her Animals and Why they Matter, (Athens: University of Georgia Press, 1984).
  • 24
    • 0022549517 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The idea that humans are simply worth more than animals is so entrenched in the history of Western moral thought that I do not have the space to reference all who have said it. Such claims were initially based on the fact that humans have souls and animals do not, and then on the fact that humans have reason and animals do not. Since these claims are now controversial, current arguments usually relate to something like Steinbock's notion of 'moral autonomy, something that humans possess, but animals do not. For other examples in this latter camp see, Carl Cohen, The Case for the Use of Animals in Biomedical Research, The New England Journal of Medicine 315/14 (October 2, 1986) 865-870
    • The idea that humans are simply worth more than animals is so entrenched in the history of Western moral thought that I do not have the space to reference all who have said it. Such claims were initially based on the fact that humans have souls and animals do not, and then on the fact that humans have reason and animals do not. Since these claims are now controversial, current arguments usually relate to something like Steinbock's notion of 'moral autonomy': something that humans possess, but animals do not. For other examples in this latter camp see, Carl Cohen, 'The Case for the Use of Animals in Biomedical Research', The New England Journal of Medicine 315/14 (October 2, 1986) 865-870,
  • 25
    • 30144437709 scopus 로고
    • Animal Liberation: A Critique
    • January
    • and Michael Fox, 'Animal Liberation: a Critique', Ethics 88/2 (January, 1978) 106-118.
    • (1978) Ethics , vol.88 , Issue.2 , pp. 106-118
    • Fox, M.1
  • 26
    • 84971154355 scopus 로고
    • Speciesism and the Idea of Equality
    • 247-256, pp
    • Bonnie Steinbock, 'Speciesism and the Idea of Equality', Philosophy 53 (1978) 247-256, pp. 253-254.
    • (1978) Philosophy , vol.53 , pp. 253-254
    • Steinbock, B.1
  • 27
    • 34548116384 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This type of claim, that we should treat non-humans how we treat humans with similar capacities, is often called, the argument from marginal cases, See Daniel Dombrowski, Babies and Beasts: The Argument from Marginal Cases Urbana: Illinois University Press, 1997
    • This type of claim - that we should treat non-humans how we treat humans with similar capacities - is often called, 'the argument from marginal cases'. See Daniel Dombrowski, Babies and Beasts: The Argument from Marginal Cases (Urbana: Illinois University Press, 1997).
  • 28
    • 34548116383 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Animal Rights and the Values of Nonhuman Life
    • For an attack on this type of reasoning, see, Cass R. Sunstein and Martha C. Nussbaum eds, Oxford: Oxford University Press, Anderson's argument essentially rests on the premise that species membership is morally significant, and thus is open to the same criticisms levelled in the previous section
    • For an attack on this type of reasoning, see Elizabeth Anderson, 'Animal Rights and the Values of Nonhuman Life', in Cass R. Sunstein and Martha C. Nussbaum (eds), Animal Rights: Current Debates and New Directions (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004). Anderson's argument essentially rests on the premise that species membership is morally significant, and thus is open to the same criticisms levelled in the previous section.
    • (2004) Animal Rights: Current Debates and New Directions
    • Anderson, E.1
  • 30
    • 33845252574 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ontario: Broadview Press
    • Angus Taylor, Animals and Ethics (Ontario: Broadview Press, 2003), p. 127.
    • (2003) Animals and Ethics , pp. 127
    • Taylor, A.1
  • 32
    • 34548110109 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I say 'ordinarily' because of course an animal might have a disease that means it will necessarily have painful experiences for the rest of its life. In such cases, there seems little reason to attribute to the animal an interest in continued life.
    • I say 'ordinarily' because of course an animal might have a disease that means it will necessarily have painful experiences for the rest of its life. In such cases, there seems little reason to attribute to the animal an interest in continued life.
  • 33
    • 34548113361 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This view is put forward by David DeGrazia, Animal Rights: a Very Short Introduction Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002, pp. 59-64
    • This view is put forward by David DeGrazia, Animal Rights: a Very Short Introduction (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002), pp. 59-64,
  • 35
    • 0003453764 scopus 로고
    • Philadelphia: Temple University Press
    • and Steve F. Sapontzis, Morals, Reason and Animals, (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1987), p. 169.
    • (1987) Morals, Reason and Animals , pp. 169
    • Sapontzis, S.F.1
  • 36
    • 34548122577 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Again, I say 'ordinarily' because in some cases individuals will have no prospect for future valuable experiences or projects: consider individuals with debilitating illnesses that cause severe and relentless pain, for example. Under my account, such individuals will naturally have a much weaker interest in continued life. This is a conclusion I am willing to accept.
    • Again, I say 'ordinarily' because in some cases individuals will have no prospect for future valuable experiences or projects: consider individuals with debilitating illnesses that cause severe and relentless pain, for example. Under my account, such individuals will naturally have a much weaker interest in continued life. This is a conclusion I am willing to accept.
  • 37
    • 0036291829 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some philosophers claim that granting rights to animals on the basis of the capacities they share with humans is anthropocentric and speciesist. Since moral reasoning has to start somewhere, and that somewhere must be with humans and human experience, I am not persuaded by such claims. For a useful discussion of these points see, Elisa Aaltola, Other animal ethics and the demand for difference, Environmental Values 11/2 (2002) 193-209
    • Some philosophers claim that granting rights to animals on the basis of the capacities they share with humans is anthropocentric and speciesist. Since moral reasoning has to start somewhere, and that somewhere must be with humans and human experience, I am not persuaded by such claims. For a useful discussion of these points see, Elisa Aaltola, '"Other animal ethics" and the demand for difference', Environmental Values 11/2 (2002) 193-209.
  • 38
    • 34548122574 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • R. G. Frey has faced up to the possibility of using human (and animal) nonpersons in medical experiments based on the potential benefits to human persons. See his contribution in R.G. Frey and Sir William Paton, 'Vivisection, Morals and Medicine: An Exchange', in Helga Kushe and Peter Singer (eds), Bioethics: An Anthology, (Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 2002).
    • R. G. Frey has faced up to the possibility of using human (and animal) nonpersons in medical experiments based on the potential benefits to human persons. See his contribution in R.G. Frey and Sir William Paton, 'Vivisection, Morals and Medicine: An Exchange', in Helga Kushe and Peter Singer (eds), Bioethics: An Anthology, (Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 2002).
  • 39
    • 84924274915 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • However, he categorically rejects the use of humans in R. G. Frey, 'Animals', in Hugh LaFollette (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Practical Ethics, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005) 161-187.
    • However, he categorically rejects the use of humans in R. G. Frey, 'Animals', in Hugh LaFollette (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Practical Ethics, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005) 161-187.
  • 41
    • 34548113363 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I say almost certain because it is conceivable that an 'experiment' could be conducted that simply involved observing the animal in its natural environment without interference. Whether such field work should properly be referred to as an experiment, I do not know.
    • I say almost certain because it is conceivable that an 'experiment' could be conducted that simply involved observing the animal in its natural environment without interference. Whether such field work should properly be referred to as an experiment, I do not know.
  • 42
    • 0003345977 scopus 로고
    • Two Concepts of Liberty
    • For the classic exposition of the distinction between negative and positive liberty see, Anthony Quinton ed, Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • For the classic exposition of the distinction between negative and positive liberty see, Isaiah Berlin, 'Two Concepts of Liberty', in Anthony Quinton (ed.), Political Philosophy, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1967), pp. 141-152.
    • (1967) Political Philosophy , pp. 141-152
    • Berlin, I.1
  • 43
    • 34548127356 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I say 'most animals' to leave open the possibility that some animals are in fact autonomous creatures with capacities to reflect on, choose and pursue their own goals. Potential candidates for such animals are great apes and cetaceans. On this matter, I have no firm belief either way, and leave it to those more knowledgeable on animal minds than myself to determine.
    • I say 'most animals' to leave open the possibility that some animals are in fact autonomous creatures with capacities to reflect on, choose and pursue their own goals. Potential candidates for such animals are great apes and cetaceans. On this matter, I have no firm belief either way, and leave it to those more knowledgeable on animal minds than myself to determine.
  • 44
    • 0004288674 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • Paul W. Taylor, Respect for Nature, (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1986), pp. 106-109.
    • (1986) Respect for Nature , pp. 106-109
    • Taylor, P.W.1
  • 45
    • 34548116382 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course such policies are pursued in many zoos and wildlife parks around the world. Rare species are taken into captivity and bred, in the hope that the resulting offspring will have a better chance of survival
    • Of course such policies are pursued in many zoos and wildlife parks around the world. Rare species are taken into captivity and bred, in the hope that the resulting offspring will have a better chance of survival.
  • 46
    • 34548116385 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thanks to Cécile Fabre for pointing this out to me
    • Thanks to Cécile Fabre for pointing this out to me.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.