메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 74, Issue 3, 2007, Pages 253-266

The decomposition of the corporate body: What Kant cannot contribute to business ethics

Author keywords

Bowie; Categorical imperative; Collective responsibility; Corporate internal decision procedure (CID); Corporate responsibility; Decision procedures; Deontological ethics; Kant; Maxims; Moral agency; Norman; Responsibility

Indexed keywords


EID: 34547904324     PISSN: 01674544     EISSN: 15730697     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1007/s10551-006-9233-z     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (31)

References (58)
  • 1
    • 0004051088 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Mass, Harvard University Press
    • Barbara Herman, The Practice, of Moral Judgment (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1983), 206;
    • (1983) The Practice, of Moral Judgment , pp. 206
    • Herman, B.1
  • 3
    • 34547872331 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • William M. Evan and R. Edward Freeman, A Stakeholder Theory of the Modern Corporation: Kantian Capitalism, in Ethical Theory and Business, ed. Tom L. Beauchamp and Norman E. Bowie, 4th ed, Englewood Cliffs, N.J, Prentice Hall, 1993, 75-84. The distinction between, stakeholders and shareholders has become commonplace in business ethics. Shareholders own part or all of a given company, and they are certainly affected by the performance of the business. However, there are many other people who are impacted by corporate behavior: employees, the community, suppliers, customers, etc. These people have a stake in the company's actions, even though they may not own any part of it. And, so the argument goes, if they are affected by the actions of the company, then the company has a moral responsibility to them
    • William M. Evan and R. Edward Freeman, 'A Stakeholder Theory of the Modern Corporation: Kantian Capitalism', in Ethical Theory and Business, ed. Tom L. Beauchamp and Norman E. Bowie, 4th ed. (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice Hall, 1993), 75-84. The distinction between, stakeholders and shareholders has become commonplace in business ethics. Shareholders own part or all of a given company, and they are certainly affected by the performance of the business. However, there are many other people who are impacted by corporate behavior: employees, the community, suppliers, customers, etc. These people have a stake in the company's actions, even though they may not own any part of it. And, so the argument goes, if they are affected by the actions of the company, then the company has a moral responsibility to them.
  • 4
    • 34547919611 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Norman E. Bowie is almost singlehandedly making up for the fact that Kant's philosophy was overlooked for so long in business ethics. Recent writings in which he explicitly references Kant include, among others, Business Ethics: A Kantian Perspective (Malden, Mass.: Blackwell, 1999);
    • Norman E. Bowie is almost singlehandedly making up for the fact that Kant's philosophy was overlooked for so long in business ethics. Recent writings in which he explicitly references Kant include, among others, Business Ethics: A Kantian Perspective (Malden, Mass.: Blackwell, 1999);
  • 6
    • 34547917965 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and 'Sweatshops and Respect for Persons' (with Denis Arnold), Business Ethics Quarterly 13 (2003), 221-242.
    • and 'Sweatshops and Respect for Persons' (with Denis Arnold), Business Ethics Quarterly 13 (2003), 221-242.
  • 7
    • 34547861673 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Corporate responsibility is one kind of collective responsibility. Although some people attribute group intentions and collective responsibility to such loose groups of people as crowds and unaffiliated members of a particular profession, more often collective responsibility is only attributed to groups whose members' behavior is governed by established rules and which has a particular body to carry out the group action, such as an elected government or a board of directors. In any event, the claims made in this paper apply both to the broader category of collective agency and to corporate agency. Kant cannot make sense of collective agency generally, and thus cannot accommodate corporate agency in particular
    • Corporate responsibility is one kind of collective responsibility. Although some people attribute group intentions and collective responsibility to such loose groups of people as crowds and unaffiliated members of a particular profession, more often collective responsibility is only attributed to groups whose members' behavior is governed by established rules and which has a particular body to carry out the group action, such as an elected government or a board of directors. In any event, the claims made in this paper apply both to the broader category of collective agency and to corporate agency. Kant cannot make sense of collective agency generally, and thus cannot accommodate corporate agency in particular.
  • 8
    • 0000739884 scopus 로고
    • Is Business Bluffing Ethical?
    • Albert Carr, 'Is Business Bluffing Ethical?' Harvard Business Review 46 (1968), 143-153.
    • (1968) Harvard Business Review , vol.46 , pp. 143-153
    • Carr, A.1
  • 9
    • 0001788578 scopus 로고
    • The Social Responsibility of Business Is to Increase Its Profits
    • 13 Sept
    • Milton Friedman, 'The Social Responsibility of Business Is to Increase Its Profits', New York Times Magazine, 13 Sept. 1970.
    • (1970) New York Times Magazine
    • Friedman, M.1
  • 10
    • 0001703294 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Does Business Ethics Rest on a Mistake?
    • John R. Boatright, 'Does Business Ethics Rest on a Mistake?', Business Ethics Quarterly 9 (1999), 586-587.
    • (1999) Business Ethics Quarterly , vol.9 , pp. 586-587
    • Boatright, J.R.1
  • 11
    • 34547857766 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Immanuel Kant, 'Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals', in Practical Philosophy, trans. and ed. Mary J. Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 393. As is standard in Kant scholarship, references to Kant's works cite the pagination of the Royal Prussian Academy edition, which is indicated in the margins of the translations.
    • Immanuel Kant, 'Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals', in Practical Philosophy, trans. and ed. Mary J. Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 393. As is standard in Kant scholarship, references to Kant's works cite the pagination of the Royal Prussian Academy edition, which is indicated in the margins of the translations.
  • 13
    • 34547877606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reflective Endorsement
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Christine M. Korsgaard, 'Reflective Endorsement', in The Sources of Normativity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 49-130.
    • (1996) The Sources of Normativity , pp. 49-130
    • Korsgaard, C.M.1
  • 14
    • 0000998166 scopus 로고
    • The Corporation as a Moral Person
    • Peter French, 'The Corporation as a Moral Person', American Philosophical Quarterly 16 (1979), 207-215.
    • (1979) American Philosophical Quarterly , vol.16 , pp. 207-215
    • French, P.1
  • 16
    • 0004224668 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Englewood Cliffs, N.J, Prentice-Hall
    • and Thomas Donaldson, Corporations and Morality (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1982), 30-32.
    • (1982) Corporations and Morality , pp. 30-32
    • Donaldson, T.1
  • 17
    • 34547891874 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kevin Gibson makes a slightly weaker claim: corporations are not moral agents, but because of their decision, procedures, the fact that there is a corporate culture (a continuing 'spirit, that persists despite employee turnover, they are enough like agents (quasi-persons) to have moral responsibilities. Thus the corporation can be held to account, but without assigning intentionality to a nonhuman entity, The Moral Basis of Stakeholder Theory, journal of Business Ethics [2000, 251-252, 254, For the purposes of this paper, the distinction between French's stronger claim and Gibson's weaker claim, is not important. As I will show, under Kant's deontological theory, a corporation, is neither an agent nor enough like an agent to be held morally responsible for its actions
    • Kevin Gibson makes a slightly weaker claim: corporations are not moral agents, but because of their decision, procedures - the fact that there is a corporate culture (a "continuing 'spirit'") that persists despite employee turnover - they are enough like agents ("quasi-persons") to have moral responsibilities. Thus the corporation can be held to account, but without "assigning intentionality to a nonhuman entity" ('The Moral Basis of Stakeholder Theory', journal of Business Ethics [2000] : 251-252, 254). For the purposes of this paper, the distinction between French's stronger claim and Gibson's weaker claim, is not important. As I will show, under Kant's deontological theory, a corporation, is neither an agent nor enough like an agent to be held morally responsible for its actions.
  • 19
    • 34547911771 scopus 로고
    • The Moral Perplexities of Famine Relief
    • ed. Tom Regan Philadelphia: Temple University Press
    • Onora O'Neill, 'The Moral Perplexities of Famine Relief, in Matters of Life and Death, ed. Tom Regan (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1980),
    • (1980) Matters of Life and Death
    • O'Neill, O.1
  • 20
    • 34547874264 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Similarly, David T. Ozar compares businesses to clubs and nations, which have rules that govern their actions. See his 'The Moral Responsibility of Corporations', in Ethical Issues in Business: A Philosophical Approach, ed. Thomas Donaldson and Patricia H. Werhane (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1979), 294-300.
    • Similarly, David T. Ozar compares businesses to clubs and nations, which have rules that govern their actions. See his 'The Moral Responsibility of Corporations', in Ethical Issues in Business: A Philosophical Approach, ed. Thomas Donaldson and Patricia H. Werhane (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1979), 294-300.
  • 21
    • 34547866705 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Although one could blame only the corporation and not the people in it, one could also hold each person involved in the decision fully responsible, or could assign proportional blame depending on how involved each person was. The options are spelled out by Richard T. De George, Can Corporations Have Moral Responsibility, in Ethical Theory and Business, ed. Tom L. Beauchamp and Norman E. Bowie, 2d ed, Englewood Cliffs, N.J, Prentice Hall, 1983, 63-65
    • Although one could blame only the corporation and not the people in it, one could also hold each person involved in the decision fully responsible, or could assign proportional blame depending on how involved each person was. The options are spelled out by Richard T. De George, 'Can Corporations Have Moral Responsibility?', in Ethical Theory and Business, ed. Tom L. Beauchamp and Norman E. Bowie, 2d ed. (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice Hall, 1983), 63-65.
  • 22
    • 0039785631 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Metaphysics of Morals
    • Immanuel Kant, The Metaphysics of Morals, in Practical Philosophy, 219.
    • Practical Philosophy , pp. 219
    • Kant, I.1
  • 24
    • 34547889913 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 402.
    • Kant1
  • 25
    • 34547898042 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 429.
    • Kant1
  • 26
    • 34547897410 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Immanuel Kant, Religion Within the Boundaries of Mere Reason, trans. George di Giovanni, in Religion and Rational Theology, ed. Allen W. Wood and George di Giovanni (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 26-28.
    • Immanuel Kant, Religion Within the Boundaries of Mere Reason, trans. George di Giovanni, in Religion and Rational Theology, ed. Allen W. Wood and George di Giovanni (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 26-28.
  • 27
    • 34547909619 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kant also says that we have a third predisposition, a predisposition to humanity. This is our tendency to compare ourselves to others, which is really just a different kind of self-love. When Kant talks about humanity in the Religion, he is describing a natural predisposition we have rather than our rational capacity to set ends, which is what he calls humanity in the Groundwork and the Metaphysics of Morals.
    • Kant also says that we have a third predisposition, a predisposition to "humanity." This is our tendency to compare ourselves to others, which is really just a different kind of self-love. When Kant talks about humanity in the Religion, he is describing a natural predisposition we have rather than our rational capacity to set ends, which is what he calls humanity in the Groundwork and the Metaphysics of Morals.
  • 29
    • 34547854749 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 425.
    • Kant1
  • 30
    • 0004183724 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Critique of Practical Reason
    • Immanuel Kant, 'Critique of Practical Reason', in Practical Philosophy, 47.
    • Practical Philosophy , pp. 47
    • Kant, I.1
  • 31
    • 34547866491 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bowie, Business Ethics, 83-84; italics mine. By Bowie's count, the second formulation of the categorical imperative is the formula of the end in itself.
    • Bowie, Business Ethics, 83-84; italics mine. By Bowie's count, the second formulation of the categorical imperative is the formula of the end in itself.
  • 32
    • 0004183724 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For Kant, the condition of all other goods is simply adherence to the moral law. This is the supreme good. But for morality to make sense to us, for it to be complete, happiness and virtue must be united somehow. This is the highest good, which is only achievable if freedom, the immortal soul, and God are not just possible but actual. See
    • For Kant, the condition of all other goods is simply adherence to the moral law. This is the supreme good. But for morality to make sense to us, for it to be complete, happiness and virtue must be united somehow. This is the highest good, which is only achievable if freedom, the immortal soul, and God are not just possible but actual. See Kant, 'Critique of Practical Reason', 110-111.
    • Critique of Practical Reason , pp. 110-111
    • Kant1
  • 33
    • 34547863146 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As Manuel G. Velasquez notes, the corporation and its employees are not related in the same way that a person, is related to her body. Only in the latter case does the intention of the agent directly bring about the action ('Why Corporations Are Not Morally Responsible for Anything They Do', Business and Professional Ethics Journal 2, no. 3 [fall 1983]: 1-18).
    • As Manuel G. Velasquez notes, the corporation and its employees are not related in the same way that a person, is related to her body. Only in the latter case does the intention of the agent directly bring about the action ('Why Corporations Are Not Morally Responsible for Anything They Do', Business and Professional Ethics Journal 2, no. 3 [fall 1983]: 1-18).
  • 34
    • 34547871282 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course, the person, must actually will the maxim. If it is a mere wish, then the maxim has not, strictly speaking, been adopted Kant, Groundwork, 394, For example, if I want to exercise more but I make no effort to get off the couch, then I do not intend to exercise. Instead, I want to have that intention
    • Of course, the person, must actually will the maxim. If it is a "mere wish," then the maxim has not, strictly speaking, been adopted (Kant, Groundwork, 394). For example, if I want to exercise more but I make no effort to get off the couch, then I do not intend to exercise. Instead, I want to have that intention.
  • 35
    • 0007139062 scopus 로고
    • Organizations as Non-Persons', journal of Value
    • Michael Keeley, 'Organizations as Non-Persons', journal of Value Inquiry 15 (1981), 149-155.
    • (1981) Inquiry , vol.15 , pp. 149-155
    • Keeley, M.1
  • 36
    • 34547875756 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is where Velasquez and I seem to overlap. He does not look at the setting of maxims, however. He focuses on the physical act of bringing about a particular end as one of the conditions of moral responsibility. He claims that a business cannot actually do anything, and thus any intentions it does have cannot be actualized: The intentions French attributes to corporations, then, do not mark out corporate acts as intentional because the intentions are attributed to one entity (the corporation) whereas the acts are carried out by another entity (the corporate members, Why Corporations Are Not Morally Responsible, 8, Businesspeople are agents of the corporation, but they are the ones who act. That is why the intentions of the corporation, are irrelevant. Unfortunately, Velasquez also notes that corporations 'as a whole' may legitimately be held causally responsible for an act or an effect, which (he notes) is a sense of responsibility distinct from mo
    • This is where Velasquez and I seem to overlap. He does not look at the setting of maxims, however. He focuses on the physical act of bringing about a particular end as one of the conditions of moral responsibility. He claims that a business cannot actually do anything, and thus any intentions it does have cannot be actualized: "The intentions French attributes to corporations, then, do not mark out corporate acts as intentional because the intentions are attributed to one entity (the corporation) whereas the acts are carried out by another entity (the corporate members)" ('Why Corporations Are Not Morally Responsible', 8). Businesspeople are agents of the corporation, but they are the ones who act. That is why the intentions of the corporation, are irrelevant. Unfortunately, Velasquez also notes that "corporations 'as a whole' may legitimately be held causally responsible for an act or an effect," which (he notes) is a sense of responsibility distinct from moral responsibility (14). Yet agreeing with French that corporations can have intentions and conceding that they can be causally responsible for a given action seems to imply that they meet the two conditions he sets out for moral responsibility: that the agent "personally brought about the wrongful, act" and that "he did so intentionally" (2). If he defines 'personally' in a nonquestion-begging way, Velasquez must concede that, according to his criteria, corporations can be morally responsible. By looking at responsibility through a Kantian lens, we can see that what seems to be an intention is actually just an artificial constraint that employees may or may not follow. Thus corporate responsibility is more effectively criticized by first explaining what is required for moral culpability, then by showing that businesses do not meet these conditions. That is the approach I take in this paper.
  • 38
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • rev. ed, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press
    • John Rawls, A Theory of Justice, rev. ed. (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 1999), 458.
    • (1999) A Theory of Justice , pp. 458
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 41
    • 84872966445 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See
    • See Kant, Religion, 91-147.
    • Religion , pp. 91-147
    • Kant1
  • 45
    • 34547854748 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Among other places, we see this in Hegel's treatment of the Oedipus story, where Oedipus finds out what he actually did by being held to account by others. See G. W. F. Hegel, Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. A. V. Miller (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977), §469.
    • Among other places, we see this in Hegel's treatment of the Oedipus story, where Oedipus finds out what he actually did by being held to account by others. See G. W. F. Hegel, Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. A. V. Miller (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977), §469.
  • 47
    • 34547888709 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • we are still left with two possibilities: Either we assign full blame to anyone who was necessary to carry out the wrong action, or we assign it proportionally based on how important each person's actions are
    • When we rule out corporate responsibility, See note 14 above
    • When we rule out corporate responsibility, we are still left with two possibilities: either we assign full blame to anyone who was necessary to carry out the wrong action, or we assign it proportionally based on how important each person's actions are. See note 14 above.
  • 48
    • 34547920709 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is O'Neill's influential rephrasing of the formula of the end in itself
    • O'Neill, 'The Moral Perplexities of Famine Relief, 286. This is O'Neill's influential rephrasing of the formula of the end in itself.
    • The Moral Perplexities of Famine Relief , vol.286
    • O'Neill1
  • 49
    • 34547875755 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It would go beyond the scope of this paper to talk more specifically about the obligations that agents of the corporation have. However, without collective agency, Kant's theory also cannot make sense of obligations to groups of people such as unions, which are not themselves deserving of respect even though their members are. If, as Gibson argues, stakeholder theory depends on collective responsibility, that is, it depends on groups having moral obligations to other groups, then deontological, ethics may undermine stakeholder theory in general, The Moral Basis of Stakeholder Theory, 245-257, Unfortunately, many stakeholder theorists claim, to be drawing on the formula of the end in itself to make their case. For example, R. Edward Freeman writes: Each of these stakeholder groups has a right not to be treated as a means to some end, and therefore must participate in determining the future direction of the firm in which they have a stake Strategic Management
    • It would go beyond the scope of this paper to talk more specifically about the obligations that agents of the corporation have. However, without collective agency, Kant's theory also cannot make sense of obligations to groups of people such as unions, which are not themselves deserving of respect even though their members are. If, as Gibson argues, stakeholder theory depends on collective responsibility - that is, it depends on groups having moral obligations to other groups - then deontological, ethics may undermine stakeholder theory in general ('The Moral Basis of Stakeholder Theory', 245-257). Unfortunately, many stakeholder theorists claim, to be drawing on the formula of the end in itself to make their case. For example, R. Edward Freeman writes: "Each of these stakeholder groups has a right not to be treated as a means to some end, and therefore must participate in determining the future direction of the firm in which they have a stake" (Strategic Management: A Stakeholder Approach [Boston: Ballinger, 1984], xx; italics mine). See also Evan and Freeman, "A Stakeholder Theory of the Modern Corporation," 76. Gibson's claim fails to convince me, however. Businesspeople are obligated to take into account the personhood of everyone who is affected by the business, even if they are not obligated to them as groups. If that is so, then Kant's individualistic view does not undermine stakeholder theory, but merely refocuses it on individual stakeholders.
  • 50
    • 34547902461 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • W. D. Ross's clearest statement of his moral philosophy is 'What Makes Right Acts Right?', in The Right and the Good (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1930), 16-47.
    • W. D. Ross's clearest statement of his moral philosophy is 'What Makes Right Acts Right?', in The Right and the Good (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1930), 16-47.
  • 51
    • 34547877220 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Shaw and Barry claim that there is no promissory relationship between investors and employees. Instead, shareholders simply buy stock that they expect to increase. They do not make an arrangement with management to increase profits, and managers are not given a choice (as, for example, financial advisors are) to refuse the offer (Moral Issues in Business, 207). This seems to assume a rather one-dimensional notion of consent. Employees are hired on the assumption that they will advance the interests of the company, and that includes (at least) the commitment to attract and reward investors by increasing profits. They tacitly consent to such a relationship by taking a position in a publicly traded company. That is not their only obligation, but it is certainly one of them.
    • Shaw and Barry claim that there is no "promissory relationship" between investors and employees. Instead, shareholders simply buy stock that they expect to increase. They do not make an arrangement with management to increase profits, and managers are not given a choice (as, for example, financial advisors are) to refuse the offer (Moral Issues in Business, 207). This seems to assume a rather one-dimensional notion of consent. Employees are hired on the assumption that they will advance the interests of the company, and that includes (at least) the commitment to attract and reward investors by increasing profits. They tacitly consent to such a relationship by taking a position in a publicly traded company. That is not their only obligation, but it is certainly one of them.
  • 52
    • 0343849619 scopus 로고
    • Respect for Persons, Management Theory, and Business Ethics
    • ed. R. Edward Freeman Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Daniel R. Gilbert, Jr., 'Respect for Persons, Management Theory, and Business Ethics', in Business Ethics: The State of the Art, ed. R. Edward Freeman (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991), 116.
    • (1991) Business Ethics: The State of the Art , pp. 116
    • Gilbert Jr., D.R.1
  • 53
    • 0346248725 scopus 로고
    • Moral Responsibility in the Age of Bureaucracy
    • August
    • David Luban, Alan Strudler, and David Wasserman, 'Moral Responsibility in the Age of Bureaucracy', Michigan Law Review 90 (August 1992): 2359.
    • (1992) Michigan Law Review , vol.90 , pp. 2359
    • Luban, D.1    Strudler, A.2    Wasserman, D.3
  • 55
    • 34547867770 scopus 로고
    • Looking Up and Looking Around
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • and Robert Jackall, 'Looking Up and Looking Around', in Moral Mazes: The World of Corporate Managers (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988), 75-100.
    • (1988) Moral Mazes: The World of Corporate Managers , pp. 75-100
    • Jackall, R.1
  • 56
    • 34547893843 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • John Stuart Mill distinguishes how we judge the action from how we judge the person who performed the action, whether she has a character that (on the whole) tends to aim at maximizing utility. See Mill, Utilitarianism Indianapolis: Hackett, 1979, 19-20. Bad actions can issue from people whose characters are good, so sometimes an action would be wrong without the person's being blameworthy. When we are talking about the actions of a business, we can say that the action is wrong without attributing the action to some blameworthy character. In such cases, there is no character to consider. When we talk about the character of the institution, we are referring to whether its policies encourage its employees to act rightly or not
    • John Stuart Mill distinguishes how we judge the action from how we judge the person who performed the action, whether she has a character that (on the whole) tends to aim at maximizing utility. See Mill, Utilitarianism (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1979), 19-20. Bad actions can issue from people whose characters are good, so sometimes an action would be wrong without the person's being blameworthy. When we are talking about the actions of a business, we can say that the action is wrong without attributing the action to some blameworthy character. In such cases, there is no character to consider. When we talk about the "character" of the institution, we are referring to whether its policies encourage its employees to act rightly or not.
  • 58
    • 34547906476 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Louis Althusser, 'Ideology and the State', in Lenin and Philosophy, and Other Essays, trans. Ben Brewster (New York: Monthly Review, 1971), 172.
    • Louis Althusser, 'Ideology and the State', in Lenin and Philosophy, and Other Essays, trans. Ben Brewster (New York: Monthly Review, 1971), 172.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.