메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 27, Issue 2, 2007, Pages 281-310

Theories of rights: Is there a third way?

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 34447623250     PISSN: 01436503     EISSN: 14643820     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1093/ojls/gqi039     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (60)

References (44)
  • 2
    • 27844431710 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Hybrid Theory of Claim-Rights
    • G. Sreenivasan, 'A Hybrid Theory of Claim-Rights' (2005) 25 OJLS 257.
    • (2005) 25 OJLS , pp. 257
    • Sreenivasan, G.1
  • 3
    • 34447617677 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In our reply, we take for granted a basic familiarity with the analysis of legal entitlements devised by the American jurist Wesley Hohfeld. That analysis is recounted in Wenar's article, and is expounded at length in Kramer, Rights without Trimmings, in M. Kramer, N. Simmonds and H. Steiner, A Debate over Rights 1998, hereinafter Debate at 7-60
    • In our reply, we take for granted a basic familiarity with the analysis of legal entitlements devised by the American jurist Wesley Hohfeld. That analysis is recounted in Wenar's article, and is expounded at length in Kramer, 'Rights without Trimmings', in M. Kramer, N. Simmonds and H. Steiner, A Debate over Rights (1998) [hereinafter Debate at 7-60.
  • 4
    • 34447651299 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hohfeld distinguished four types of entitlements: Claims or rights, liberties, power, and immunities. Like Hohfeld, but unlike most contemporary writers, Wenar uses the term 'privileges' in lieu of 'liberties, We have opted for the latter term and have silently altered his wording in our quotations. An early version of the first half of this essay was presented at a workshop on rights at the University of Edinburgh in February 2005. We are very grateful to the organizers of that workshop, Antony Hatzistavrou and Rowan Cruft. We are likewise grateful to Antony Duff, John Eekelaar, Neil MacCormick, Sandra Marshall, Saladin Meckled-Garcia, Victor Tadros, Leif Wenar and an anonymous OJLS reader for thier illuminating comments. We owe special thanks to Wenar for making his work readily available to us before it was published
    • Hohfeld distinguished four types of entitlements: Claims or rights, liberties, power, and immunities. Like Hohfeld, but unlike most contemporary writers, Wenar uses the term 'privileges' in lieu of 'liberties'. We have opted for the latter term and have silently altered his wording in our quotations. An early version of the first half of this essay was presented at a workshop on rights at the University of Edinburgh in February 2005. We are very grateful to the organizers of that workshop, Antony Hatzistavrou and Rowan Cruft. We are likewise grateful to Antony Duff, John Eekelaar, Neil MacCormick, Sandra Marshall, Saladin Meckled-Garcia, Victor Tadros, Leif Wenar and an anonymous OJLS reader for thier illuminating comments. We owe special thanks to Wenar for making his work readily available to us before it was published.
  • 5
    • 34447651098 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • After all, one of us (Kramer) is an Interest Theorist, while the other one of us (Steiner) is a Will Theorist
    • After all, one of us (Kramer) is an Interest Theorist, while the other one of us (Steiner) is a Will Theorist.
  • 6
    • 27844603413 scopus 로고
    • Legal Rights
    • at
    • H.L.A. Hart, 'Legal Rights' in Essays on Bentham (1982) 162 at 166-67.
    • (1982) Essays on Bentham , vol.162 , pp. 166-167
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 7
    • 34447638658 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wenar, above n 1 at 228 n 6
    • Wenar, above n 1 at 228 n 6.
  • 8
    • 34447632432 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at
    • Ibid at 246.
  • 9
    • 34447643368 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We include the words 'while accepting that John exists' simply in order to forestall any technical quibbles.
    • We include the words 'while accepting that John exists' simply in order to forestall any technical quibbles.
  • 10
    • 34447624105 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wenar, above n 1 at 231
    • Wenar, above n 1 at 231.
  • 11
    • 34447631984 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid.
  • 12
    • 34447628457 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid at 231 n 9.
    • Ibid at 231 n 9.
  • 13
    • 34447629165 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A legal duty D is effectuated if either of the following conditions is met: (1) violations of D are averted through preventative steps taken by legal officials; or (2) although D is violated, the violation is subsequently rectified through the application of some remedial measure(s) such as punishment, compensation, or restitution. The effectuation of legal duties occurs more frequently via the second of these two routes than via the first.
    • A legal duty D is effectuated if either of the following conditions is met: (1) violations of D are averted through preventative steps taken by legal officials; or (2) although D is violated, the violation is subsequently rectified through the application of some remedial measure(s) such as punishment, compensation, or restitution. The effectuation of legal duties occurs more frequently via the second of these two routes than via the first.
  • 14
    • 34447636194 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Although one or the other of the two default rules must be operative in application to each duty within any legal system, it is not perforce true that one or the other of the default rules will have been consciously adopted as such beforehand by legal officials or by anyone else, The operativeness of the applicable default rule might become apparent only after a duty has been breached
    • Although one or the other of the two default rules must be operative in application to each duty within any legal system, it is not perforce true that one or the other of the default rules will have been consciously adopted as such beforehand by legal officials (or by anyone else). The operativeness of the applicable default rule might become apparent only after a duty has been breached.
  • 15
    • 34447630940 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a full exposition of the Interest Theory, see Kramer, above n 1 at 60-101.
    • For a full exposition of the Interest Theory, see Kramer, above n 1 at 60-101.
  • 16
    • 34447625022 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wenar, above n 1 at 241
    • Wenar, above n 1 at 241.
  • 17
    • 34447649506 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid.
  • 18
    • 34447618388 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at
    • Ibid at 241-42.
  • 19
    • 34447635657 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kramer, above n 1 at 85-88
    • Kramer, above n 1 at 85-88.
  • 20
    • 34447632155 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wenar, above n 1 at 248
    • Wenar, above n 1 at 248.
  • 21
    • 34447645946 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note that the intrinsic effect in question is not the benefiting of any terminally ill person even pro tanto, Instead, it is the absence of penalties for any terminally ill person who commits or seeks to commit suicide. Of course, under any credible empirical assumptions, the absence of penalties will per se almost always be beneficial for a terminally ill person; but, strictly speaking, the intrinsic effect of the relevant legal norm is the lack of penalties rather than the pro-tanto benefit derived therefrom
    • Note that the intrinsic effect in question is not the benefiting of any terminally ill person (even pro tanto). Instead, it is the absence of penalties for any terminally ill person who commits or seeks to commit suicide. Of course, under any credible empirical assumptions, the absence of penalties will per se almost always be beneficial for a terminally ill person; but, strictly speaking, the intrinsic effect of the relevant legal norm is the lack of penalties rather than the pro-tanto benefit derived therefrom.
  • 22
    • 34447618387 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As we shall see in the second half of this article, the Interest Theory is sometimes criticized for being too far-reaching in its classification of people as right-holders. For example, suppose that two corporations have formed a legally binding agreement on the terms of a merger. Suppose further that the shareholders in each corporation will stand to benefit from the occurrence of the merger. According to the Interest Theory, then, each shareholder has a legal claim-right (vis-à-vis each corporation) to the consummation of the merger, even though each shareholder very likely does not have a legal power to seek or waive the enforcement of the duty correlative to that right. We do not feel that this classification of every shareholder as a right-holder is problematic for the Interest Theory. Perhaps, however, Wenar does view it as problematic. Even so, he will have left himself vulnerable to a 'tu quoque' recort. If there is nothing internal to the notion of a bene
    • As we shall see in the second half of this article, the Interest Theory is sometimes criticized for being too far-reaching in its classification of people as right-holders. For example, suppose that two corporations have formed a legally binding agreement on the terms of a merger. Suppose further that the shareholders in each corporation will stand to benefit from the occurrence of the merger. According to the Interest Theory, then, each shareholder has a legal claim-right (vis-à-vis each corporation) to the consummation of the merger - even though each shareholder very likely does not have a legal power to seek or waive the enforcement of the duty correlative to that right. We do not feel that this classification of every shareholder as a right-holder is problematic for the Interest Theory. Perhaps, however, Wenar does view it as problematic. Even so, he will have left himself vulnerable to a 'tu quoque' recort. If there is nothing internal to the notion of a benefit or an interest that will curb the wide-rangingness of the Interest Theory's criterion for the attribution of rights, there is likewise nothing internal to the notion of protection of secured provision or secured performanced - the distinctive functions of claim-rights, according to Wenar - that will curb the wide-rangingness of any criterion for the attribution of claim-rights that emerges from his Several-Functions Theory. If Wenar is inclined to avail himself of an extraneous limitation that will rein in his criterion, an Interest Theorist can equally legitimately do the same (though, as we have indicated, we believe that an Interest Theorist should not in fact take such a route). Hence, once again Wenar's theory turns out to be on a par with the Interest Theory. The former is a version of the latter.
  • 23
    • 34447628456 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course, we do not mean to suggest that every rendering of each theory is so restricted. For some capacious versions of the Will Theory, see Hart, above n 3 at 188-89
    • Of course, we do not mean to suggest that every rendering of each theory is so restricted. For some capacious versions of the Will Theory, see Hart, above n 3 at 188-89
  • 24
    • 34447623891 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • H.L.A. Hart, 'Definition and Theory in Jurisprudence' in Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosphy (1983) 21 at 35-36, n 15
    • H.L.A. Hart, 'Definition and Theory in Jurisprudence' in Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosphy (1983) 21 at 35-36, n 15
  • 25
    • 34447632336 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rights at the Cutting Edge
    • at
    • Simmonds, 'Rights at the Cutting Edge' in Debate, above n 1 at 211-25.
    • Debate, above , Issue.1 , pp. 211-225
    • Simmonds1
  • 26
    • 3843100630 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rights: Beyond Interest Theory and Will Theory?
    • For a recent caoacious version of the Interest Theory, see
    • For a recent caoacious version of the Interest Theory, see R. Cruft, 'Rights: Beyond Interest Theory and Will Theory?' (2004) 23 Law and Philosophy 347.
    • (2004) 23 Law and Philosophy , pp. 347
    • Cruft, R.1
  • 27
    • 34447616961 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wenar, above n 1 at 243
    • Wenar, above n 1 at 243.
  • 28
    • 34447636367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid.
  • 29
    • 34447634631 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at
    • Ibid at 238.
  • 30
    • 34447627832 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at
    • Ibid at 236.
  • 31
    • 34447632968 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at
    • Ibid at 237.
  • 32
    • 34447640654 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid at 229, n 7.
    • Ibid at 229, n 7.
  • 33
    • 34447620059 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wenar puzzlingly suggests that the Interest/Will division is derivative of the disputes between welfarists and Kantians within moral and political philosophy (ibid at 224, 250-51). His suggestion along these lines is puzzling because, although some Will Theorists have indeed been Kantians, hardly anyone among the main exponents of the Interest Theory is a welfarist. Wenar's position would make it very difficult to understand, for example, why John Firmis is both a champion of the Interest Theory and a scathing critic of welfarism.
    • Wenar puzzlingly suggests that the Interest/Will division is derivative of the disputes between welfarists and Kantians within moral and political philosophy (ibid at 224, 250-51). His suggestion along these lines is puzzling because, although some Will Theorists have indeed been Kantians, hardly anyone among the main exponents of the Interest Theory is a welfarist. Wenar's position would make it very difficult to understand, for example, why John Firmis is both a champion of the Interest Theory and a scathing critic of welfarism.
  • 34
    • 34447648494 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sreenivasan, above n 1 at 259, emphasis deleted
    • Sreenivasan, above n 1 at 259, emphasis deleted.
  • 35
    • 34447648321 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid at 259, n 9.
    • Ibid at 259, n 9.
  • 36
    • 34447621911 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Raz's main analyses of rights are in his 'Legal Rights' (1984) 4 OJLS 1
    • Raz's main analyses of rights are in his 'Legal Rights' (1984) 4 OJLS 1
  • 37
    • 34447640499 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and The Morality of Freedom (1986), 165-92.
    • and The Morality of Freedom (1986), 165-92.
  • 38
    • 34447641773 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sreenivasan, above n 1 at 263-64. Purely for stylistic reasons, we have substituted 'X's' for 'your' throughout this passage and our other quotations from Sreenivasan.
    • Sreenivasan, above n 1 at 263-64. Purely for stylistic reasons, we have substituted 'X's' for 'your' throughout this passage and our other quotations from Sreenivasan.
  • 39
    • 34447642291 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid at 266, emphases in original. Wenar agrees with Sreenivasan (and us) on this point;
    • Ibid at 266, emphases in original. Wenar agrees with Sreenivasan (and us) on this point;
  • 40
    • 34447630939 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see Wenar, above n 1 at 242.
    • see Wenar, above n 1 at 242.
  • 41
    • 34447621726 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sreenivasan, above n 1 at 264, emphases in original, footnotes omitted
    • Sreenivasan, above n 1 at 264, emphases in original, footnotes omitted.
  • 42
    • 34447622438 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Such a view underlies the analysis of freedom and time in Matthew H. Kramer, The Quality of Freedom (2003) at 76-91.
    • Such a view underlies the analysis of freedom and time in Matthew H. Kramer, The Quality of Freedom (2003) at 76-91.
  • 43
    • 34447651300 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sreenivasan, above n 1 at 271
    • Sreenivasan, above n 1 at 271.
  • 44
    • 34447632969 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid at 267, emphases in original
    • Ibid at 267, emphases in original


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.