메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 117, Issue 3, 2007, Pages 524-546

Is terrorism distinctively wrong?

(1)  McPherson, Lionel K a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 34250320992     PISSN: 00141704     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1086/512781     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (40)

References (50)
  • 1
    • 31544458531 scopus 로고
    • Terrorism, Rights, and Political Goals
    • See, most notably, ed. R. G. Frey and Christopher W. Morris Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • See, most notably, Virginia Held, "Terrorism, Rights, and Political Goals," in Violence, Terrorism, and Justice, ed. R. G. Frey and Christopher W. Morris (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 59-85.
    • (1991) Violence, Terrorism, and Justice , pp. 59-85
    • Held, V.1
  • 2
    • 33846399539 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Terrorism: A Critique of Excuses
    • See, e.g, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press
    • See, e.g., Michael Walzer, "Terrorism: A Critique of Excuses," in Arguing about War (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2004), 51-66.
    • (2004) Arguing about War , pp. 51-66
    • Walzer, M.1
  • 3
    • 34250372769 scopus 로고
    • See Adam Roberts and Richard Guelff, eds, 3rd ed, Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • See Adam Roberts and Richard Guelff, eds., Documents on the Laws of War, 3rd ed. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1982).
    • (1982) Documents on the Laws of War
  • 4
    • 21444455793 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Moral Response to Terrorism and Cosmopolitanism
    • ed. James P. Sterba New York: Oxford University Press
    • Louis P. Pojman, "The Moral Response to Terrorism and Cosmopolitanism," in Terrorism and International Justice, ed. James P. Sterba (New York: Oxford University Press, 2003), 135-57, 140.
    • (2003) Terrorism and International Justice , vol.135 -57 , pp. 140
    • Pojman, L.P.1
  • 5
    • 33747708895 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For the revisionist view of the relevance of moral innocence and noninnocence, see Lionel K. McPherson, Innocence and Responsibility in War, Canadian Journal of Philosophy 34 (2004): 485-506; and Jeff McMahan, The Ethics of Killing in War, Ethics 114 (2004): 693-733.
    • For the revisionist view of the relevance of moral innocence and noninnocence, see Lionel K. McPherson, "Innocence and Responsibility in War," Canadian Journal of Philosophy 34 (2004): 485-506; and Jeff McMahan, "The Ethics of Killing in War," Ethics 114 (2004): 693-733.
  • 6
    • 8744259741 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Terrorism without Intention
    • 752-71
    • David Rodin, "Terrorism without Intention," Ethics 114 (2004): 752-71, 755.
    • (2004) Ethics , vol.114 , pp. 755
    • Rodin, D.1
  • 8
    • 0004083066 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 3rd ed, New York: Basic
    • Michael Walzer, Just and Unjust Wars, 3rd ed. (New York: Basic, 1977), 255, 268.
    • (1977) Just and Unjust Wars , vol.255 , pp. 268
    • Walzer, M.1
  • 9
    • 8744293045 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Terrorism, Morality, and Supreme Emergency
    • Walzer's account of supreme emergency is controversial. For criticism of this alleged exception to the laws of war, see, e.g
    • Walzer's account of "supreme emergency" is controversial. For criticism of this alleged exception to the laws of war, see, e.g., C. A. J. Coady, "Terrorism, Morality, and Supreme Emergency," Ethics 114 (2004): 772-89.
    • (2004) Ethics , vol.114 , pp. 772-789
    • Coady, C.A.J.1
  • 10
    • 34250328138 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Terrorism and Innocence
    • See, 37-58
    • See C. A. J. Coady, "Terrorism and Innocence," Journal of Ethics 8 (2004): 37-58, 40.
    • (2004) Journal of Ethics , vol.8 , pp. 40
    • Coady, C.A.J.1
  • 12
    • 34250371970 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Since the fear-effects clause is not tied to the intentions of the agents using force, there is no issue about assessing an intention to cause fear. The intentions motivating use of force can be irrelevant to the production of fear
    • Since the fear-effects clause is not tied to the intentions of the agents using force, there is no issue about assessing an intention to cause fear. The intentions motivating use of force can be irrelevant to the production of fear.
  • 14
    • 0004083066 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an account of the just war that is widely cited and accepted, see
    • For an account of the just war that is widely cited and accepted, see Walzer, Just and Unjust Wars.
    • Just and Unjust Wars
    • Walzer1
  • 15
    • 34250380170 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Coady, Terrorism and Innocence, 39. Coady's definition refers to use of violence to attack non-combatants, where attack means that the violence against them is deliberate.
    • See, e.g., Coady, "Terrorism and Innocence," 39. Coady's definition refers to "use of violence to attack non-combatants," where "attack" means that the violence against them is deliberate.
  • 17
    • 0039666033 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g, Manchester: Manchester University Press
    • See, e.g., A.J. Coates, The Ethics of War (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1997), 80.
    • (1997) The Ethics of War , pp. 80
    • Coates, A.J.1
  • 18
    • 34250376283 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I add the qualification nonstate since states have employed tactics (e.g, fire-bombing of cities) and weapons (e.g, chemical, biological, and nuclear) that could count as terrorist
    • I add the qualification "nonstate" since states have employed tactics (e.g., fire-bombing of cities) and weapons (e.g., chemical, biological, and nuclear) that could count as terrorist.
  • 20
    • 34250380567 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Judith Gail Gardam, Proportionality and Force in International Law, American Journal of International Law 87 (1993): 391-413, 410. To be clear, Gardam is not endorsing this interpretation. For a critical assessment of standard treatments of proportionality and an alternative approach, see Lionel K. McPherson, Excessive Force in War: A 'Golden Rule' Test, Theoretical Inquiries in Law 7 (2005): 81-95.
    • Judith Gail Gardam, "Proportionality and Force in International Law," American Journal of International Law 87 (1993): 391-413, 410. To be clear, Gardam is not endorsing this interpretation. For a critical assessment of standard treatments of proportionality and an alternative approach, see Lionel K. McPherson, "Excessive Force in War: A 'Golden Rule' Test," Theoretical Inquiries in Law 7 (2005): 81-95.
  • 21
    • 34250369857 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • James M. Dubik, Philosophy & Public Affairs 11 (1982): 354-71, 368. Dubik is responding to Walzer's more demanding requirement that combatants must accept greater costs to themselves for the sake of minimizing harm to noncombatants. See Walzer, Just and Unjust Wars, 155.
    • James M. Dubik, Philosophy & Public Affairs 11 (1982): 354-71, 368. Dubik is responding to Walzer's more demanding requirement that combatants must accept greater costs to themselves for the sake of minimizing harm to noncombatants. See Walzer, Just and Unjust Wars, 155.
  • 22
    • 34248036520 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Limits of the War Convention
    • For criticism of the war convention as a source of moral obligation, see
    • For criticism of the war convention as a source of moral obligation, see Lionel K. McPherson, "The Limits of the War Convention," Philosophy and Social Criticism 31 (2005): 147-63.
    • (2005) Philosophy and Social Criticism , vol.31 , pp. 147-163
    • McPherson, L.K.1
  • 23
    • 33645139106 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Terrorism and War
    • 59-75
    • Virginia Held, "Terrorism and War," Journal of Ethics 8 (2004): 59-75, 69.
    • (2004) Journal of Ethics , vol.8 , pp. 69
    • Held, V.1
  • 26
    • 34250381130 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sheridan Johns and R. Hunt Davis Jr., Conclusion: Mandela, Tambo, and the ANC in the 1990s, in their Mandela, Tambo, and the African National Congress, 309-17, 312.
    • Sheridan Johns and R. Hunt Davis Jr., "Conclusion: Mandela, Tambo, and the ANC in the 1990s," in their Mandela, Tambo, and the African National Congress, 309-17, 312.
  • 27
    • 34250360090 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Roberts and Guelff, Documents on the Laws of War, 489. Also see, e.g., Walzer, Just and Unjust Wars, 145-46.
    • Roberts and Guelff, Documents on the Laws of War, 489. Also see, e.g., Walzer, Just and Unjust Wars, 145-46.
  • 28
    • 8644286208 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Failures of Just War Theory: Terror, Harm, and Justice
    • See, e.g
    • See, e.g., F. M. Kamm, "Failures of Just War Theory: Terror, Harm, and Justice," Ethics 114 (2004): 650-92, 652-53.
    • (2004) Ethics , vol.114
    • Kamm, F.M.1
  • 31
  • 32
    • 34250379382 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For arguments to a similar conclusion, see
    • For arguments to a similar conclusion, see Kamm, "Failures of Just War Theory," 664.
    • Failures of Just War Theory , vol.664
    • Kamm1
  • 34
    • 34250314758 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also Kamm, Failures of Just War Theory, 667-68; and T. M. Scanlon, Intention and Permissibility, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 74 (2000): S301-S317, S310-S312.
    • See also Kamm, "Failures of Just War Theory," 667-68; and T. M. Scanlon, "Intention and Permissibility," Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 74 (2000): S301-S317, S310-S312.
  • 35
    • 34250331008 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This response to Thomson was suggested to me by Jeff McMahan
    • This response to Thomson was suggested to me by Jeff McMahan.
  • 36
    • 34250354639 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • G. E. M. Anscombe, War and Murder, in her Ethics, Religion and Politics (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1981), 51-61, 58. It is tempting to believe that Thomson-type cases are peculiarly unrepresentative and thus misleading about the DDE's application to conventional war. In typical cases, combatants do not have prior knowledge of the evil effects of their acts. Instead, they foresee the risk of harm to noncombatants, and even foreseeable high risk is not knowledge. Yet the DDE does not invoke a distinction between prior knowledge of evil effects and risk of evil effects. The agent's intention is supposed to make a moral difference in its own right.
    • G. E. M. Anscombe, "War and Murder," in her Ethics, Religion and Politics (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1981), 51-61, 58. It is tempting to believe that Thomson-type cases are peculiarly unrepresentative and thus misleading about the DDE's application to conventional war. In typical cases, combatants do not have prior knowledge of the evil effects of their acts. Instead, they foresee the risk of harm to noncombatants, and even foreseeable high risk is not knowledge. Yet the DDE does not invoke a distinction between prior knowledge of evil effects and risk of evil effects. The agent's intention is supposed to make a moral difference in its own right.
  • 38
    • 34250352560 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A similar point, albeit against the DDE and its requirements of necessity and proportionality, is made by Rodin, Terrorism without Intention, 765.
    • A similar point, albeit against the DDE and its requirements of necessity and proportionality, is made by Rodin, "Terrorism without Intention," 765.
  • 39
    • 84971922657 scopus 로고
    • The Reasons We Can Share: An Attack on the Distinction between Agent-Relative and Agent-Neutral Values
    • 24-51
    • Christine M. Korsgaard, "The Reasons We Can Share: An Attack on the Distinction between Agent-Relative and Agent-Neutral Values," Social Philosophy and Policy 10 (1993): 24-51, 46.
    • (1993) Social Philosophy and Policy , vol.10 , pp. 46
    • Korsgaard, C.M.1
  • 40
    • 34250375465 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan (1651), ed. C. B. Macpherson (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1968), chaps. 13-14. Also see Charles R. Beitz, Political Theory and International Relations (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979), chaps. 2-4; and David Rodin, War and Self-Defense (New York: Oxford University Press, 2002), 144-48.
    • See Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan (1651), ed. C. B. Macpherson (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1968), chaps. 13-14. Also see Charles R. Beitz, Political Theory and International Relations (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979), chaps. 2-4; and David Rodin, War and Self-Defense (New York: Oxford University Press, 2002), 144-48.
  • 41
    • 0004168076 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • John Rawls, The Law of Peoples (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), 24.
    • (1999) The Law of Peoples , pp. 24
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 44
    • 34250328538 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The fact that combatants for an unjust war fight under domestic legal and patriotic duress and in personal self-defense is immaterial to the permissibility of conduct that otherwise would be objectively unjust. This is not at odds with acknowledging that their conduct typically is excusable to some degree
    • The fact that combatants for an unjust war fight under domestic legal and patriotic duress and in personal self-defense is immaterial to the permissibility of conduct that otherwise would be objectively unjust. This is not at odds with acknowledging that their conduct typically is excusable to some degree.
  • 45
    • 34250326548 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is compatible with recognizing that punishment can be appropriately imposed on the political leaders, who, in administering the state's authority and sending combatants to fight an unjust war, bear primary moral responsibility for the injustice done by the combatants on the battlefield
    • This is compatible with recognizing that punishment can be appropriately imposed on the political leaders, who, in administering the state's authority and sending combatants to fight an unjust war, bear primary moral responsibility for the injustice done by the combatants on the battlefield.
  • 47
    • 0003929983 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • Yael Tamir, Liberal Nationalism (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1993), 65.
    • (1993) Liberal Nationalism , pp. 65
    • Tamir, Y.1
  • 48
    • 34250362541 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sharon Street pressed me on this point
    • Sharon Street pressed me on this point.
  • 50
    • 34250378528 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jeff McMahan pressed me on this point
    • Jeff McMahan pressed me on this point.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.