-
1
-
-
34250001046
-
On Liberty
-
Mary Warnock, ed, London: Fontana, at p
-
John Stuart Mill, 'On Liberty', in Mary Warnock, ed., Utilitarianism (London: Fontana, 1987), pp. 126-250, at p. 135.
-
(1987)
Utilitarianism
-
-
Stuart Mill, J.1
-
2
-
-
84972609043
-
-
For excellent introductions to this issue, see Bernard Manin, 'On Legitimacy and Political Deliberation', Political Theory, 15 (1987), 338-68; and Thomas Nagel, 'Moral Conflict and Political Legitimacy', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 16 (1987), 215-40.
-
For excellent introductions to this issue, see Bernard Manin, 'On Legitimacy and Political Deliberation', Political Theory, 15 (1987), 338-68; and Thomas Nagel, 'Moral Conflict and Political Legitimacy', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 16 (1987), 215-40.
-
-
-
-
5
-
-
34250003000
-
-
See, for example, Keith Ansell-Pearson, ed, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
See, for example, Keith Ansell-Pearson, ed., F. Nietzsche, On the Genealogy of Morality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994), pp. 21-2.
-
(1994)
F. Nietzsche, On the Genealogy of Morality
, pp. 21-22
-
-
-
6
-
-
34250017327
-
-
For examples of this recent trend, see Peter Berkowitz, Nietzsche: The Ethics of an Immoralist (Cambridge, Mass, Harvard University Press, 1995, Duncan Kelly, The State of the Political: Conceptions of Politics and the State in the Thought of Max Weber, Carl Schmitt and Franz Neumann (Oxford: Oxford University Press for the British Academy, 2003, Jan Muller, A Dangerous Mind: Carl Schmitt in Post-War European Thought New Haven, Conn, Yale University Press, 2003
-
For examples of this recent trend, see Peter Berkowitz, Nietzsche: The Ethics of an Immoralist (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1995); Duncan Kelly, The State of the Political: Conceptions of Politics and the State in the Thought of Max Weber, Carl Schmitt and Franz Neumann (Oxford: Oxford University Press for the British Academy, 2003); Jan Muller, A Dangerous Mind: Carl Schmitt in Post-War European Thought (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 2003).
-
-
-
-
7
-
-
0003439118
-
-
For a fuller account of the notion of 'family resemblances' and the way in which the idea may be put to work in mapping contributions to political thought, see, Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
For a fuller account of the notion of 'family resemblances' and the way in which the idea may be put to work in mapping contributions to political thought, see Michael Freeden, Ideologies and Political Theory: A Conceptual Approach (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996).
-
(1996)
Ideologies and Political Theory: A Conceptual Approach
-
-
Freeden, M.1
-
8
-
-
34249995917
-
-
There is some ambiguity of terminology in this regard. For some, liberalism aims at a politics 'without coercion, for others it aims to ensure that all coercion that is employed is 'legitimate, Within liberalism, however, the difference is only semantic. The first usage is intended to imply that the legitimate or acceptable use of political power is by definition not coercive, whilst the second usage defines political power of all sorts as inherently 'coercive' and insists that the crucial distinction rests between whether such coercion as is employed is 'legitimate' or not. This article adopts the first usage for reasons of clarity but the argument would be unaffected by the adoption of the second. For examples of each and for a demonstration of their interchangeability compare the uses of 'coercion' in John Rawls, The Idea of Public Reason Revisited' in his The Law of Peoples Cambridge, Mass, Harvard University Press, 2002, pp. 131-80, at pp. 136- 40, with John Dryzek
-
There is some ambiguity of terminology in this regard. For some, liberalism aims at a politics 'without coercion', for others it aims to ensure that all coercion that is employed is 'legitimate'. Within liberalism, however, the difference is only semantic. The first usage is intended to imply that the legitimate or acceptable use of political power is by definition not coercive, whilst the second usage defines political power of all sorts as inherently 'coercive' and insists that the crucial distinction rests between whether such coercion as is employed is 'legitimate' or not. This article adopts the first usage for reasons of clarity but the argument would be unaffected by the adoption of the second. For examples of each and for a demonstration of their interchangeability compare the uses of 'coercion' in John Rawls, 'The Idea of Public Reason Revisited' in his The Law of Peoples (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2002), pp. 131-80, at pp. 136- 40, with John Dryzek, Deliberative Democracy and Beyond: Liberals, Critics, Contestations (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), pp. 68-71.
-
-
-
-
9
-
-
34249984060
-
-
The question as to whether early forms of thinking now appropriated by liberals should themselves be described as liberal or are better known as proto-liberal is taken up in Freeden, Ideologies and Political Theory, pp. 141-2
-
The question as to whether early forms of thinking now appropriated by liberals should themselves be described as liberal or are better known as proto-liberal is taken up in Freeden, Ideologies and Political Theory, pp. 141-2.
-
-
-
-
11
-
-
34250021816
-
-
For a brief introduction to this form of resistance to the social contract tradition, see Roger Crisp, Mill on Utilitarianism (London: Routledge, 1997), esp. pp. 67-72. See too Ross Harrison, ed., Jeremy Bentham: A Fragment on Government (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), esp. pp. 3-32; and John Stuart Mill, 'Utilitarianism' in Warnock, ed., Utilitarianism, pp. 288-95.
-
For a brief introduction to this form of resistance to the social contract tradition, see Roger Crisp, Mill on Utilitarianism (London: Routledge, 1997), esp. pp. 67-72. See too Ross Harrison, ed., Jeremy Bentham: A Fragment on Government (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), esp. pp. 3-32; and John Stuart Mill, 'Utilitarianism' in Warnock, ed., Utilitarianism, pp. 288-95.
-
-
-
-
12
-
-
34250018739
-
-
For examples and discussion, see John Stuart Mill, 'Bentham' in Warnock, ed., Utilitarianism, pp. 78-125, esp. at pp. 99-107.
-
For examples and discussion, see John Stuart Mill, 'Bentham' in Warnock, ed., Utilitarianism, pp. 78-125, esp. at pp. 99-107.
-
-
-
-
13
-
-
0004267415
-
-
For a more thorough overview, see the account in, London: Routledge
-
For a more thorough overview, see the account in John Gray, Mill On Liberty; A Defence (London: Routledge, 1996), pp. 70-89.
-
(1996)
Mill On Liberty; A Defence
, pp. 70-89
-
-
Gray, J.1
-
14
-
-
34250006741
-
-
John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993), p. 37. Further excellent discussions of the critique can be found in John Tomasi, Liberalism Beyond Justice: Citizens, Society and the Boundaries of Political Theory (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 2001), and Charles Larmore, The Morals of Modernity (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1996).
-
John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993), p. 37. Further excellent discussions of the critique can be found in John Tomasi, Liberalism Beyond Justice: Citizens, Society and the Boundaries of Political Theory (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 2001), and Charles Larmore, The Morals of Modernity (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1996).
-
-
-
-
17
-
-
34250016751
-
-
That does not mean, of course, that all citizens would self-consciously accept the precise terms of every single action of the liberal state at every single moment, but it does imply that when a state constructed on agreed principles nonetheless compels citizens to act in accordance with its wishes not theirs, they do not have to understand its commands as coercive because they could appreciate that they have emerged from a political process and a political order to which they have, in some meaningful sense, agreed. I thank Andrew Sabl for this point
-
That does not mean, of course, that all citizens would self-consciously accept the precise terms of every single action of the liberal state at every single moment, but it does imply that when a state constructed on agreed principles nonetheless compels citizens to act in accordance with its wishes not theirs, they do not have to understand its commands as coercive because they could appreciate that they have emerged from a political process and a political order to which they have, in some meaningful sense, agreed. I thank Andrew Sabl for this point.
-
-
-
-
19
-
-
34249987857
-
-
On the move from idealized standards of justification to actual citizen practices of reasonable persuasion, see Nagel, Moral Conflict and Political Legitimacy, esp. pp. 232-4
-
On the move from idealized standards of justification to actual citizen practices of reasonable persuasion, see Nagel, 'Moral Conflict and Political Legitimacy', esp. pp. 232-4.
-
-
-
-
22
-
-
0004048289
-
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1972), p. 370.
-
(1972)
A Theory of Justice
, pp. 370
-
-
Rawls, J.1
-
23
-
-
3042562870
-
Rawls on Justification
-
For an overview, see, S. Freeman, ed, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
For an overview, see Thomas M. Scanlon, 'Rawls on Justification' in S. Freeman, ed., The Cambridge Companion to Rawls (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003), pp. 139-67.
-
(2003)
The Cambridge Companion to Rawls
, pp. 139-167
-
-
Scanlon, T.M.1
-
24
-
-
0007310158
-
-
For the connections between Rawls's position and deliberative democracy, see, esp. pp
-
For the connections between Rawls's position and deliberative democracy, see Rawls, 'Idea of Public Reason Revisited', esp. pp. 135-9.
-
Idea of Public Reason Revisited
, pp. 135-139
-
-
Rawls1
-
25
-
-
3042660162
-
The Scope of Public Reason
-
For an excellent guide to this disagreement, see
-
For an excellent guide to this disagreement, see Jonathan Quong, 'The Scope of Public Reason', Political Studies, 52 (2004), pp. 233-50.
-
(2004)
Political Studies
, vol.52
, pp. 233-250
-
-
Quong, J.1
-
28
-
-
34249986008
-
-
Dryzek, Deliberative Democracy and Beyond, p. v. See also, David Miller, Citizenship and National Identity (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2000), p. 159.
-
Dryzek, Deliberative Democracy and Beyond, p. v. See also, David Miller, Citizenship and National Identity (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2000), p. 159.
-
-
-
-
31
-
-
34249992490
-
-
Jeremy Waldron, Law and Disagreement (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), p. 158. For other statements of a similar position, see Jane Mansbridge, 'Using Power/Fighting Power', in Seyla Benhabib, ed., Democracy and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, pp. 46-66, esp. at p. 54, and Glen Newey, After Politics: The Rejection of Politics in Contemporary Liberal Philosophy (Basingstoke, Hants.: Palgrave, 2001).
-
Jeremy Waldron, Law and Disagreement (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), p. 158. For other statements of a similar position, see Jane Mansbridge, 'Using Power/Fighting Power', in Seyla Benhabib, ed., Democracy and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, pp. 46-66, esp. at p. 54, and Glen Newey, After Politics: The Rejection of Politics in Contemporary Liberal Philosophy (Basingstoke, Hants.: Palgrave, 2001).
-
-
-
-
33
-
-
34249987566
-
-
In 'The Idea of Public Reason Revisited, Rawls himself addresses this concern by arguing that his version of public reason is immune to the charge that it 'mistakenly tries to settle political questions in advance' as it does not presume broad agreement on matters of political controversy in modern societies prior to discussion p. 142, He does, however, contend that 'public justification' of the sort he demands from citizens is a form of 'argument addressed to others' which 'proceeds correctly from premises we accept and think others could reasonably accept to conclusions we think they could also reasonably accept, p. 155, Put in these terms, there is still a difference between the Rawlsian and the theorist of compulsion, as the latter rejects the idea that such shared 'premises' can exist in contemporary societies
-
In 'The Idea of Public Reason Revisited', Rawls himself addresses this concern by arguing that his version of public reason is immune to the charge that it 'mistakenly tries to settle political questions in advance' as it does not presume broad agreement on matters of political controversy in modern societies prior to discussion (p. 142). He does, however, contend that 'public justification' of the sort he demands from citizens is a form of 'argument addressed to others' which 'proceeds correctly from premises we accept and think others could reasonably accept to conclusions we think they could also reasonably accept' (p. 155). Put in these terms, there is still a difference between the Rawlsian and the theorist of compulsion, as the latter rejects the idea that such shared 'premises' can exist in contemporary societies.
-
-
-
-
34
-
-
0003352078
-
Democracy and Territoriality
-
Frederick Dolan and Thomas Dumm, eds, Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, at p
-
William Connolly, 'Democracy and Territoriality', in Frederick Dolan and Thomas Dumm, eds, Rhetorical Republic: Governing Representation in American Politics (Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1993), pp. 249-67, at p. 251.
-
(1993)
Rhetorical Republic: Governing Representation in American Politics
-
-
Connolly, W.1
-
35
-
-
0032799567
-
The Agonic Freedom of Citizens
-
See, for example
-
See, for example, James Tully, 'The Agonic Freedom of Citizens', Economy and Society, 28 (1999), 161-82.
-
(1999)
Economy and Society
, vol.28
, pp. 161-182
-
-
Tully, J.1
-
36
-
-
34250007864
-
-
See, for variants on this frequent theme, Michael Walzer, 'Deliberation, and What Else?' in Stephen Macedo, ed., Deliberative Politics: Essays on Democracy and Disagreement (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), pp. 58-69; and C. Wright Mills, The Power Elite (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000).
-
See, for variants on this frequent theme, Michael Walzer, 'Deliberation, and What Else?' in Stephen Macedo, ed., Deliberative Politics: Essays on Democracy and Disagreement (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), pp. 58-69; and C. Wright Mills, The Power Elite (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000).
-
-
-
-
38
-
-
27844557852
-
The Concept of the State
-
Quentin Skinner and Bo Strath, eds, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, at p
-
David Runciman, 'The Concept of the State', in Quentin Skinner and Bo Strath, eds, States and Citizens: History, Theory, Prospects (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003), pp. 28-38, at p. 29.
-
(2003)
States and Citizens: History, Theory, Prospects
-
-
Runciman, D.1
-
39
-
-
34250022817
-
-
James Scott, Seeing Like A State: How Certain Schemes to Improve the Human Condition Have Failed (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1998). Scott proposes a solution to these difficulties similar to that propounded by 'agonists' such as Honig, Mouffe and Tully: a solution grounded in maintaining spirited resistances to state authorities. Whether such a suggestion is itself likely to achieve the ends he desires is, of course, itself moot.
-
James Scott, Seeing Like A State: How Certain Schemes to Improve the Human Condition Have Failed (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1998). Scott proposes a solution to these difficulties similar to that propounded by 'agonists' such as Honig, Mouffe and Tully: a solution grounded in maintaining spirited resistances to state authorities. Whether such a suggestion is itself likely to achieve the ends he desires is, of course, itself moot.
-
-
-
-
40
-
-
34250028350
-
-
This dispute is best captured in the early twentieth-century argument between Walter Lippmann and John Dewey on the status of 'public opinion' in democratic societies, for which see the masterful contributions of Walter Lippmann, Public Opinion (New York: The Free Press, 1997, and John Dewey, The Public and its Problems Athens, Ga, Swallow Press, 1991
-
This dispute is best captured in the early twentieth-century argument between Walter Lippmann and John Dewey on the status of 'public opinion' in democratic societies, for which see the masterful contributions of Walter Lippmann, Public Opinion (New York: The Free Press, 1997), and John Dewey, The Public and its Problems (Athens, Ga.: Swallow Press, 1991).
-
-
-
-
42
-
-
0036946366
-
Ideas, Institutions, and Political Order: Explaining Political Change
-
at p
-
Robert Lieberman, 'Ideas, Institutions, and Political Order: Explaining Political Change', American Political Science Review, 96 (2002), 691-712, at p. 109.
-
(2002)
American Political Science Review
, vol.96
-
-
Lieberman, R.1
-
43
-
-
34250029743
-
-
Lieberman, 'Ideas', p. 709.
-
Lieberman, 'Ideas', p. 709.
-
-
-
-
45
-
-
34249993433
-
Simone Chambers' s insightful review of After Politics
-
A point well noted in, 96 2002
-
A point well noted in Simone Chambers' s insightful review of After Politics in American Political Science Review, 96 (2002), 808-9.
-
American Political Science Review
, pp. 808-809
-
-
-
47
-
-
34250026634
-
-
Mouffe, Return of the Political, p. 153. See also, Honig, Political Theory, p. 14, and Tully, 'Agonic Freedom of Citizens', esp. pp. 170-1.
-
Mouffe, Return of the Political, p. 153. See also, Honig, Political Theory, p. 14, and Tully, 'Agonic Freedom of Citizens', esp. pp. 170-1.
-
-
-
-
48
-
-
34250000771
-
-
See Geoffrey Hawthorn, 'The Promise of Civil Society in the South', in S. Kaviraj and S. Khilnani, eds, Civil Society: History and Possibilities (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), pp. 269-86. John Dryzek appears to have some sympathy for this position, arguing that it is 'very hard for deliberation to reach' state officials and that, as such, deliberative practices should be encouraged outside of the state at least in the first instance. See Dryzek, Deliberative Democracy and Beyond, p. 29, and pp. 81-114. See also, Mark Warren, 'What Can Democratic Participation Mean Today?' Political Theory, 30 (2002), 677-701.
-
See Geoffrey Hawthorn, 'The Promise of "Civil Society" in the South', in S. Kaviraj and S. Khilnani, eds, Civil Society: History and Possibilities (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), pp. 269-86. John Dryzek appears to have some sympathy for this position, arguing that it is 'very hard for deliberation to reach' state officials and that, as such, deliberative practices should be encouraged outside of the state at least in the first instance. See Dryzek, Deliberative Democracy and Beyond, p. 29, and pp. 81-114. See also, Mark Warren, 'What Can Democratic Participation Mean Today?' Political Theory, 30 (2002), 677-701.
-
-
-
-
54
-
-
34249984058
-
-
See, for examples of this critique, Daniel Bell, The End of Ideology: On the Exhaustion of Political Ideas in the Fifties (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2000); Mark Lilla, The Reckless Mind: Intellectuals in Politics (London: Granta Press, 2001); and David Runciman, The Politics of Good Intentions: History, Fear and Hypocrisy in the New World Order (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 2006). The historical emergence of this argument is sketched in Albert Hirschman, The Passions and the Interests: Political Arguments for Capitalism Before its Triumph (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1997).
-
See, for examples of this critique, Daniel Bell, The End of Ideology: On the Exhaustion of Political Ideas in the Fifties (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2000); Mark Lilla, The Reckless Mind: Intellectuals in Politics (London: Granta Press, 2001); and David Runciman, The Politics of Good Intentions: History, Fear and Hypocrisy in the New World Order (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 2006). The historical emergence of this argument is sketched in Albert Hirschman, The Passions and the Interests: Political Arguments for Capitalism Before its Triumph (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1997).
-
-
-
-
55
-
-
0002112280
-
The Minimalist Conception of Democracy: A Defence
-
See, Ian Shapiro and Casiano Hacker-Cordon, eds, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
See Adam Pzeworski, 'The Minimalist Conception of Democracy: A Defence', in Ian Shapiro and Casiano Hacker-Cordon, eds, Democracy's Value (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), pp. 23-55.
-
(2000)
Democracy's Value
, pp. 23-55
-
-
Pzeworski, A.1
-
59
-
-
0005850904
-
Deliberative Democracy and Majority Rule
-
Harold Hongju and Ronald Slye, eds, New Haven, Conn, Yale University Press, at p
-
Amy Gutmann, 'Deliberative Democracy and Majority Rule', in Harold Hongju and Ronald Slye, eds, Deliberative Democracy and Human Rights (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1999), pp. 227-34, at p. 230.
-
(1999)
Deliberative Democracy and Human Rights
-
-
Gutmann, A.1
-
60
-
-
84884004917
-
-
See, Princeton, N.J, Princeton University Press
-
See Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson, Why Deliberative Democracy? (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 2004), pp. 1-4.
-
(2004)
Why Deliberative Democracy
, pp. 1-4
-
-
Gutmann, A.1
Thompson, D.2
-
61
-
-
18844382138
-
-
Miller, Citizenship, p. 159. For a less dramatic example along similar lines, see Archon Fung, 'Deliberation Before the Revolution: Toward an Ethics of Deliberative Democracy in an Unjust World'. Political Theory, 33 (2005), 397-419.
-
Miller, Citizenship, p. 159. For a less dramatic example along similar lines, see Archon Fung, 'Deliberation Before the Revolution: Toward an Ethics of Deliberative Democracy in an Unjust World'. Political Theory, 33 (2005), 397-419.
-
-
-
-
62
-
-
13444304357
-
Social Movements and Deliberative Democratic Theory
-
53-75, p
-
John Medearis, 'Social Movements and Deliberative Democratic Theory', British Journal of Political Science, 35 (2004), 53-75, p. 55.
-
(2004)
British Journal of Political Science
, vol.35
, pp. 55
-
-
Medearis, J.1
-
63
-
-
16344391982
-
-
See John Dryzek, 'Deliberative Democracy in Divided Societies: Alternatives to Agonism and Analgesia, Political Theory, 33 (2005), 218-42, at p. 224. See also Lynn M. Sanders, 'Against Deliberation', Political Theory, 25 (1997), 347-76; and Iris Marion Young, 'Activist Challenges to Deliberative Democracy', Political Theory. 29 (2001), 670-90.
-
See John Dryzek, 'Deliberative Democracy in Divided Societies: Alternatives to Agonism and Analgesia", Political Theory, 33 (2005), 218-42, at p. 224. See also Lynn M. Sanders, 'Against Deliberation', Political Theory, 25 (1997), 347-76; and Iris Marion Young, 'Activist Challenges to Deliberative Democracy', Political Theory. 29 (2001), 670-90.
-
-
-
-
65
-
-
34249991106
-
-
Medearis, 'Social Movements and Deliberative Democratic Theory', p. 69. See also, Mansbridge, 'Using Power/Fighting Power', esp. p. 66.
-
Medearis, 'Social Movements and Deliberative Democratic Theory', p. 69. See also, Mansbridge, 'Using Power/Fighting Power', esp. p. 66.
-
-
-
-
66
-
-
77951897375
-
-
Jeremy Waldron, 'Theoretical Foundations of Liberalism', Philosophical Quarterly, 37 (1987), 127-59, p. 128. I think Andrew Sabl again for persuading me of the importance of this article in the development of contemporary liberal thought.
-
Jeremy Waldron, 'Theoretical Foundations of Liberalism', Philosophical Quarterly, 37 (1987), 127-59, p. 128. I think Andrew Sabl again for persuading me of the importance of this article in the development of contemporary liberal thought.
-
-
-
|