-
1
-
-
61849174181
-
Indirect Language and the Voices of Silence
-
trans. Michael B. Smith, ed. Galen Johnson (Evanston, Ill.)
-
Maurice Merleau-Ponty, "Indirect Language and the Voices of Silence," The Merleau-Ponty Aesthetics Reader: Philosophy and Painting, trans. Michael B. Smith, ed. Galen Johnson (Evanston, Ill., 1993), p. 103
-
(1993)
The Merleau-Ponty Aesthetics Reader: Philosophy and Painting
, pp. 103
-
-
Merleau-Ponty, M.1
-
2
-
-
61249326525
-
-
Ithaca, N.Y, 1987
-
See The Concept of Style, ed. Berel Lang (1979; Ithaca, N.Y, 1987), which remains the best treatment
-
(1979)
The Concept of Style
-
-
Lang, B.1
-
5
-
-
60950654996
-
-
New York
-
The classic treatment of the subject in art history is Meyer Schapiro, "Style," Theory and Philosophy of Art: Style, Artist, and Society (New York, 1994), pp. 51-102
-
(1994)
Style, Theory and Philosophy of Art: Style, Artist, and Society
, pp. 51-102
-
-
Schapiro, M.1
-
6
-
-
84987402587
-
From Stilus to Style: Reflections on the Fate of a Notion
-
Sept.
-
On the term style, see Willibald Saurländer, "From Stilus to Style: Reflections on the Fate of a Notion," Art History 6 (Sept. 1983) : 253-70
-
(1983)
Art History
, vol.6
, pp. 253-270
-
-
Saurländer, W.1
-
8
-
-
80054181049
-
-
and "Problems in Connoisseurship," a special issue of Source 24, no. 2 (2005) for recent treatments that, it is hoped, signal renewed interest in the subject
-
(2005)
Problems in Connoisseurship
, Issue.2
-
-
-
9
-
-
34547317030
-
Restitutions of the Truth in Pointing
-
trans. Geoff Bennington and Ian McLeod Chicago, 371
-
This last view (connoisseurship as fetishism) is sometimes attributed to Derrida's essay, "Restitutions of the Truth in Pointing" - the single best discussion of connoisseurship in recent memory. It is true that Derrida does associate attribution with the fetishist's desire for plenitude, hence gratification. But that association is only half his argument. More important for present purposes is the association of connoisseurship's dismissal with historical crime and the conclusion of the discussion with a simple es gibt / il y' a. See Jacques Derrida, "Restitutions of the Truth in Pointing," Truth in Painting, trans. Geoff Bennington and Ian McLeod (Chicago, 1987), pp. 329-30,371
-
(1987)
Truth in Painting
, pp. 329-330
-
-
Derrida, J.1
-
10
-
-
60949211861
-
-
ed. Andrzej Warminski Minneapolis
-
Paul de Man, Aesthetic Ideology, ed. Andrzej Warminski (Minneapolis, 1996), p. 90
-
(1996)
Aesthetic Ideology
, pp. 90
-
-
De Man, P.1
-
12
-
-
0004110142
-
-
Oxford
-
On criteria in this Wittgensteinian sense, see Stanley Cavell, The Claim of Reason: Wittgenstein, Skepticism, Morality, and Tragedy (Oxford, 1979), pp. 3-48; hereafter abbreviated CR. He describes "criteria as necessary before the identification or knowledge of an object, and as prelude to that knowledge" (CR, p. 17)
-
(1979)
The Claim of Reason: Wittgenstein, Skepticism, Morality, and Tragedy
, pp. 3-48
-
-
Cavell, S.1
-
13
-
-
61249357813
-
Establishing Group Boundaries: Toward Methodological Refinement in the Determination of Sets as a Prior Condition to the Analysis of Cultural Contact and/or Innovation in First Millennium B.C.E. Ivory Carving
-
ed. C. E. Suter and C. Uehlinger Freiburg
-
A point recently emphasized by Irene Winter, "Establishing Group Boundaries: Toward Methodological Refinement in the Determination of Sets as a Prior Condition to the Analysis of Cultural Contact and/or Innovation in First Millennium B.C.E. Ivory Carving," in Crafts and Images in Contact: Studies on Eastern Mediterranean Art of the First Millennium B.C.E., ed. C. E. Suter and C. Uehlinger (Freiburg, 2005), pp. 23-42
-
(2005)
Crafts and Images in Contact:Studies on Eastern Mediterranean Art of the First Millennium B.C.E
, pp. 23-42
-
-
Winter, I.1
-
15
-
-
84898238349
-
-
trans. Martin Ryle and Kate Soper London
-
Carlo Ginzburg, The Enigma of Piero, trans. Martin Ryle and Kate Soper (London, 2000), p.xxiv
-
(2000)
The Enigma of Piero
, pp. 24
-
-
Ginzburg, C.1
-
16
-
-
79956786419
-
The Getty Kouros: Background of the Problem
-
Athens
-
On the history of the Getty kouros, see Marion True, "The Getty Kouros: Background of the Problem," in The Getty Kouros Colloquium (Athens, 1993), pp. 11-15
-
(1993)
The Getty Kouros Colloquium
, pp. 11-15
-
-
M. True1
-
18
-
-
60949746067
-
Tall Tales: Celts, Connoisseurs, and the Fabrication of Archaeological Context
-
More recently, see the treatment of similar cases in Elizabeth Simpson, "Tall Tales: Celts, Connoisseurs, and the Fabrication of Archaeological Context," Source 24, no. 2 (2005): 28-41
-
(2005)
Source
, vol.24
, Issue.2
, pp. 28-41
-
-
Simpson, E.1
-
19
-
-
84907524299
-
Proof? The Case of the Getty Kouros
-
Fall
-
Kenneth D. S. Lapatin, "Proof? The Case of the Getty Kouros," Source 20 (Fall 2000) : 51
-
(2000)
Source
, vol.20
, pp. 51
-
-
Lapatin, K.D.S.1
-
20
-
-
80054181040
-
Lorenzo Valla on the 'Donation of Constantine,'
-
Hanover, N.H
-
See the excellent discussion in Ginzburg, "Lorenzo Valla on the 'Donation of Constantine,'" History, Rhetoric, and Proof (Hanover, N.H., 1999), pp. 54-70
-
(1999)
History, Rhetoric, and Proof
, pp. 54-70
-
-
Ginzburg1
-
21
-
-
60950611009
-
Style and the Products and Processes of Art
-
See Kendall L. Walton, "Style and the Products and Processes of Art," in The Concept of Style, p. 73
-
The Concept of Style
, pp. 73
-
-
Walton, K.L.1
-
23
-
-
0004065337
-
-
(Cambridge, Mass) , 42, 48
-
Compare Danto, The Transfiguration of the Commonplace: A Philosophy of Art (Cambridge, Mass., 1981), pp. 31-32, 42, 48, on the possibility of a random spattering of paint producing a simulacrum of the Polish Riderin the Frick Collection
-
(1981)
The Transfiguration of the Commonplace: A Philosophy of Art
, pp. 31-32
-
-
Danto, C.1
-
24
-
-
80054134339
-
-
trans. J. H. Bernard (London, 1892)
-
Immanuel Kant, Kritik of Judgment, trans. J. H. Bernard (London, 1892), §43, p. 183
-
Kritik of Judgment
, pp. 183
-
-
Kant, I.1
-
25
-
-
84894465457
-
-
University Park, Pa.
-
The interest of the Berekhat Ram figurine has been discussed most thoroughly in Whitney Davis, Replications: Archaeology, Art History, Psychoanalysis (University Park, Pa., 1996), pp. 157-60
-
(1996)
Replications: Archaeology, Art History, Psychoanalysis
, pp. 157-160
-
-
Davis, W.1
-
26
-
-
33645015528
-
-
New York
-
For a related discussion, see James Elkins, Our Beautiful, Dry, and Distant Texts: Art History as Writing (New York, 2000), pp. 62-102
-
(2000)
Our Beautiful, Dry, and Distant Texts: Art History as Writing
, pp. 62-102
-
-
Elkins, J.1
-
27
-
-
0346980172
-
Paleolithic Ivory Sculptures from Southwestern Germany and the Origins of Figurative Art
-
18 Dec.
-
See a more recent account of a similar case in Nicholas Conard, "Paleolithic Ivory Sculptures from Southwestern Germany and the Origins of Figurative Art," Nature, 18 Dec. 2003, pp. 830-32, a reference I owe to Jim Porter
-
(2003)
Nature
, pp. 830-832
-
-
Conard, N.1
-
29
-
-
77956278737
-
-
1934; Cambridge, Mass., 412, §589
-
Charles Saunders Peirce, Pragmatism and Pragmaticism, vol. 5 of Collected Papers of Charles Saunders Peirce, ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss, 2 vols, in 1 (1934; Cambridge, Mass., 1963), pp. 411,412, §589
-
(1963)
Pragmatism and Pragmaticism
, pp. 411
-
-
Peirce, C.S.1
-
30
-
-
0004112370
-
-
A similar metaphorics of ground, groundedness, and the groundless underwrites the famous Heidegger-Schapiro-Derrida exchange on attribution and restitution; see, for instance, Derrida, The Truth in Painting, pp. 287-92. Heidegger's insistence, echoed by Derrida, that the discourse of attribution is not simply grounded or groundless - not simply the subjectivization of the world, a transformation of hypokeimenon into subjectum - is located at just this topos
-
The Truth in Painting
, pp. 287-292
-
-
Derrida1
-
31
-
-
0004186684
-
-
Cambridge
-
I refer here to the so-called Typology Debate between James Ford and Albert Spaulding, "the first substantial manifestation of the concern of American archaeologists to articulate and make explicit the analytical basis of their discipline" (Bruce Trigger, A History of Archaeological Thought [Cambridge, 1989], p. 203)
-
(1989)
A History of Archaeological Thought
, pp. 203
-
-
Trigger, B.1
-
33
-
-
60950374614
-
Northumbrian Sculpture (the Ruthwell and Bewcastle Monuments): Questions of Difference
-
ed. Jane Hawkes and Susan Mills New York
-
Compare Fred Orton, "Northumbrian Sculpture (the Ruthwell and Bewcastle Monuments): Questions of Difference," in Northumbria's Golden Age, ed. Jane Hawkes and Susan Mills (New York, 1999), pp. 216-26
-
(1999)
Northumbria's Golden Age
, pp. 216-226
-
-
Fred Orton, C.1
-
34
-
-
80054146806
-
Rethinking the Ruthwell and Bewcastle Monuments: Some Strictures on Similarity; Some Questions of History
-
ed. Catherine Karkov and Orton, Morgantown, W.Va.
-
and "Rethinking the Ruthwell and Bewcastle Monuments: Some Strictures on Similarity; Some Questions of History," in Theorizing Anglo-Saxon Stone Sculpture, ed. Catherine Karkov and Orton (Morgantown, W.Va., 2003), pp. 65-92 for a more moderate version of this position. Like the old Ford-Spaulding debate, these avowedly postmodern critiques retain, willy-nilly, the basic distinction between emic and etic categories. The gist of the critique is invariably that archaeology naturalizes its own etic categories as real, historical, emic ones. It is difficult to understand what other sorts of category archaeologists are supposed to use; what might be called the emic category an sich proves to be elusive
-
(2003)
Theorizing Anglo-Saxon Stone Sculpture
, pp. 65-92
-
-
-
35
-
-
84974075324
-
Style and the Design of a Perfume Jar from an Archaic Greek City State
-
Spring
-
Shanks, "Style and the Design of a Perfume Jar from an Archaic Greek City State," Journal of European Archaeology 1 (Spring 1993): 77
-
(1993)
Journal of European Archaeology
, vol.1
, pp. 77
-
-
Shanks1
-
40
-
-
61249521380
-
Style as Inclusion, Style as Exclusion
-
ed. Caroline A. Jones and Peter Galison New York
-
and Ginzburg, "Style as Inclusion, Style as Exclusion," Picturing Science, Producing Art, ed. Caroline A. Jones and Peter Galison (New York, 1998), pp. 28-54
-
(1998)
Picturing Science, Producing Art
, pp. 28-54
-
-
Ginzburg1
-
42
-
-
0348212092
-
Pictorial Style: Two Views
-
See Richard Wollheim, "Pictorial Style: Two Views," in The Concept of Style, pp. 183-202
-
The Concept of Style
, pp. 183-202
-
-
Wollheim, R.1
-
45
-
-
79956847367
-
-
Baltimore
-
Here it is important to specify that not everything that is stylistic is also etiological. Saying that something is baroque suggests nothing about its origins. A Pergamene relief or a painting by David Reed can each be baroque, and a fake Tiepolo is, potentially, just as baroque as a real one. Likewise, not everything about a painting that has etiological significance is also stylistic. The collector's stamp that appears on a Rembrandt drawing may be an important clue as to provenance and thus as to the authenticity of the work; but it is not a stylistic trait for all that. On Reed, see Going for Baroque: Eighteen Contemporary Artists Fascinated with the Baroque, ed. Lisa Corrin and Joaneath Spicer (Baltimore, 1995)
-
(1995)
Going for Baroque: Eighteen Contemporary Artists Fascinated with the Baroque
-
-
Corrin, L.1
Spicer, J.2
-
49
-
-
85039127957
-
-
For a recent, compelling argument to the effect that supraindividual styles may be identified in cases where the posited stylistic connection explains why individual artists "have the same brief," see Gilmore, The life of a Style, p. 55
-
The life of a Style
, pp. 55
-
-
Gilmore1
-
51
-
-
0038075008
-
-
Berkeley
-
For those unfamiliar with Smithson's art, one way to think of it is as the literalization of the Naturgeschichte of Adorno and Benjamin. On which, see Beatrice Hanssen, Walter Benjamin's Other History: Of Stones, Animals, Human Beings, and Angels (Berkeley, 1998)
-
(1998)
Walter Benjamin's Other History: Of Stones, Animals, Human Beings, and Angels
-
-
Hanssen, B.1
-
52
-
-
60950413643
-
A Sedimentation of the Mind: Earth Projects
-
ed. Jack Flam Berkeley
-
Robert Smithson, "A Sedimentation of the Mind: Earth Projects," Robert Smithson: The Collected Writings, ed. Jack Flam (Berkeley, 1996), p. 100
-
(1996)
Robert Smithson: The Collected Writings
, pp. 100
-
-
Smithson, R.1
-
53
-
-
0042817023
-
-
trans. Allison Brown Princeton, N.J
-
On Bacon, art, and natural history, see Horst Bredekamp, The Lure of Antiquity and the Cult of the Machine: The Kunstkammer and the Evolution of Nature, Art, and Technology, trans. Allison Brown (Princeton, N.J., 1995), pp. 63-80
-
(1995)
The Lure of Antiquity and the Cult of the Machine: The Kunstkammer and the Evolution of Nature, Art, and Technology
, pp. 63-80
-
-
Bredekamp, H.1
-
56
-
-
85039088325
-
The Transfiguration of the Commonplace, and Wollheim
-
Princeton, N.J
-
See Danto, The Transfiguration of the Commonplace, and Wollheim, Painting as an Art (Princeton, N.J., 1987), pp. 89-96
-
(1987)
Painting as an Art
, pp. 89-96
-
-
Danto1
-
57
-
-
33748042408
-
-
(New York)
-
Compare Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, trans. G. E. M. Anscombe (New York, 1958), p. 199, for the same basic argument in very compact form; hereafter abbreviated PI
-
(1958)
Philosophical Investigations
, pp. 199
-
-
Anscombe, G.E.M.1
-
59
-
-
61049392784
-
Goodman, Forgery, and the Aesthetic
-
Spring
-
Contra Goodman, see, for example, Louise Morton and Thomas Foster, "Goodman, Forgery, and the Aesthetic," Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 49 (Spring 1991): 155-59
-
(1991)
Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism
, vol.49
, pp. 155-159
-
-
Morton, L.1
Foster, T.2
-
60
-
-
6044260933
-
-
See Mulhall, On Being in the World, pp. 15-28, on continuous aspect-perception and "regarding-as."
-
On Being in the World
, pp. 15-28
-
-
Mulhall1
-
62
-
-
85039124719
-
-
Incidentally, reading Goodman in these Wittgensteinian terms tends to vitiate the critiques leveled against him in Morton and Foster, "Goodman, Forgery, and the Aesthetic."
-
Goodman, Forgery, and the Aesthetic
-
-
-
64
-
-
80054180992
-
Wittgenstein, Kripke, and the 'Paradox' of Meaning
-
ed. Teghrarian, Bristol
-
and Sauren Teghrarian, "Wittgenstein, Kripke, and the 'Paradox' of Meaning," in Wittgenstein and Contemporary Philosophy, ed. Teghrarian (Bristol, 1994)
-
(1994)
Wittgenstein and Contemporary Philosophy
-
-
Teghrarian, S.1
-
67
-
-
84984115046
-
-
Mar.
-
Morelli may, in fact, have been too conscientious; Hayden Macginnis, "The Role of Perceptual Learning in Connoisseurship: Morelli, Berenson, and Beyond," ArtHistory l3 (Mar. 1990): 104-17, argues that he wound up misrepresenting his actual practice
-
(1990)
The Role of Perceptual Learning in Connoisseurship: Morelli, Berenson, and Beyond, ArtHistory
, vol.13
, pp. 104-117
-
-
Macginnis, H.1
-
69
-
-
84899240726
-
-
See Schapiro, "Style," pp. 53-56
-
Style
, pp. 53-56
-
-
Schapiro1
-
73
-
-
80054146752
-
-
trans. Anscombe, ed. Anscombe and G. H. von Wright, 2 vols. (Oxford) §63
-
Wittgenstein, Remarks on the Philosophy of Psychology, trans. Anscombe, ed. Anscombe and G. H. von Wright, 2 vols. (Oxford, 1980), 2:13, §63
-
(1980)
Remarks on the Philosophy of Psychology
, vol.2
, pp. 13
-
-
Wittgenstein1
-
74
-
-
33751163101
-
Beazley and the Language of Connoisseurship
-
On the role of quality in attribution, see Neer, "Beazley and the Language of Connoisseurship," Hephaistos 15 (1997): 7-30
-
(1997)
Hephaistos
, vol.15
, pp. 7-30
-
-
Neer1
-
78
-
-
85039133315
-
-
PI
-
For the public nature of aspect-perceptions - the fact that they demand some form of expression, a "cry of recognition" - see PI, p. 198
-
cry of recognition
, pp. 198
-
-
-
79
-
-
60949968043
-
-
Compare PI, p. 183: "Thus the atmosphere that is inseparable from its object - is not an atmosphere," that is, is not an ethereal, geistig ideality; there is an intersection here between Wittgenstein and Benjamin's account of the aura, literally the "breeze." See also Merleau-Ponty, "Indirect Language and the Voices of Silence," p. 104: "The presence of style ... is one with the fact of our corporeality and does not call for any occult explanation." Within the domain of art history (or, more precisely, at its margins) the most extensive employment of the Smithsonian theme is Adrian Stokes's Stones of Rimini
-
Indirect Language and the Voices of Silence
, pp. 104
-
-
Merleau-Ponty1
-
84
-
-
85039102350
-
-
See also CR, pp. 358-59
-
CR
, pp. 358-359
-
-
-
85
-
-
0004000126
-
-
Compare Cavell, Must We Mean What We Say? pp. 86-96. One can, for instance, argue about the internal consistency of connoisseur's arguments: does Beazley, for instance, make a coherent argument for why he applies the criteria he does? I have argued that he does not in Neer, "Beazley and the Language of Connoisseurship."
-
Must We Mean What We Say?
, pp. 86-96
-
-
Cavell, C.1
-
86
-
-
33745445096
-
Showing Seeing: A Critique of Visual Culture
-
ed. Michael Ann Holly and Keith Moxey Williamstown, Mass
-
For a recent, related critique of visual culture, see W. J. T. Mitchell, "Showing Seeing: A Critique of Visual Culture," in Art History, Aesthetics, and Visual Studies, ed. Michael Ann Holly and Keith Moxey (Williamstown, Mass., 2002), pp. 231-50
-
(2002)
Art History, Aesthetics, and Visual Studies
, pp. 231-250
-
-
Mitchell, W.J.T.1
|