-
1
-
-
61049150109
-
-
ed. M. J. Wreen and D. M Callen Cornell University Press
-
Monroe Beardsley, The Aesthetic Point of View, ed. M. J. Wreen and D. M Callen (Cornell University Press, 1982), p. 211
-
(1982)
The Aesthetic Point of View
, pp. 211
-
-
Beardsley, M.1
-
2
-
-
24944459812
-
The Evaluation of Art
-
ed. Oswald Hanfling Blackwell
-
Colin Lyas, "The Evaluation of Art," in Philosophical Aesthetics, ed. Oswald Hanfling (Blackwell, 1992), pp. 353-354
-
(1992)
Philosophical Aesthetics
, pp. 353-354
-
-
Lyas, C.1
-
4
-
-
61049383493
-
The Character and Role of Principles in the Evaluation of Art
-
James Shelley, "The Character and Role of Principles in the Evaluation of Art," The British Journal of Aesthetics 42 (2002): 37
-
(2002)
The British Journal of Aesthetics
, vol.42
, pp. 37
-
-
Shelley, J.1
-
5
-
-
61049136594
-
General Criteria and Reasons in Aesthetics
-
Oxford University Press
-
Frank Sibley, "General Criteria and Reasons in Aesthetics" in Approaches to Aesthetics (Oxford University Press, 2001), pp. 104-118
-
(2001)
Approaches to Aesthetics
, pp. 104-118
-
-
Sibley, F.1
-
6
-
-
79954299843
-
-
Temple University Press
-
George Dickie, Evaluating Art (Temple University Press, 1988), p. 158
-
(1988)
Evaluating Art
, pp. 158
-
-
Dickie, G.1
-
7
-
-
61049492478
-
-
This would be akin to proving there are no Platonic forms. But we need not prove there can be no forms to establish that Plato conceived his evaluative principles incorrectly
-
This would be akin to proving there are no Platonic forms. But we need not prove there can be no forms to establish that Plato conceived his evaluative principles incorrectly
-
-
-
-
8
-
-
61049202862
-
-
We can speak of both the fitness of the individual organism, insofar as it is able to survive and reproduce, and the fitness of types, species, genera, and so on, insofar as we can generalize about their features, environments, and abilities
-
We can speak of both the fitness of the individual organism - insofar as it is able to survive and reproduce - and the fitness of types - species, genera, and so on - insofar as we can generalize about their features, environments, and abilities
-
-
-
-
9
-
-
61049472426
-
-
What will constitute the context will depend on which persons or group of persons we wish to consider. We can consider those who actually experience an artwork, for instance, or a person or group that might experience a work, or even an abstract person or group
-
What will constitute the context will depend on which persons or group of persons we wish to consider. We can consider those who actually experience an artwork, for instance, or a person or group that might experience a work, or even an abstract person or group
-
-
-
-
11
-
-
80054601194
-
-
Here the evolutionary analogy breaks down somewhat. For art, the internal context always depends on the external context - those who experience the correlation of parts. In evolution we can consider the fitness conferred by internal context independent of external context
-
Here the evolutionary analogy breaks down somewhat. For art, the internal context always depends on the external context - those who experience the "correlation of parts." In evolution we can consider the fitness conferred by internal context independent of external context
-
-
-
-
14
-
-
0008438277
-
Categories of Art
-
Kendall. L. Walton, "Categories of Art," The Philosophical Review 79 (1970): 340. Walton goes further than I do, claiming that knowledge of these categories is essential to aesthetic judgment (p. 337). In my view, this kind of knowledge is clearly desirable, and makes for better judgment, but is not always essential
-
(1970)
The Philosophical Review
, vol.79
, pp. 340
-
-
Walton, K.L.1
-
17
-
-
80054601301
-
-
This is not to say that bad works do not engage these faculties. The difference between good and bad work relative to these faculties is the functional effect in the experience of the work
-
This is not to say that bad works do not engage these faculties. The difference between good and bad work relative to these faculties is the functional effect in the experience of the work
-
-
-
-
18
-
-
80052308912
-
Of the Standard of Taste
-
ed. T. H. Green and T. H. Grose, London: Scientia Verlag Aalen
-
David Hume, "Of the Standard of Taste" in Essays Moral, Political, and Literary, ed. T. H. Green and T. H. Grose, vol. 1 (London: Scientia Verlag Aalen, 1964), p. 278
-
(1964)
Essays Moral, Political, and Literary
, vol.1
, pp. 278
-
-
Hume, D.1
-
19
-
-
80054601284
-
-
I am not suggesting that we cannot also evaluate an artwork in terms of the intentions of the creator. But we should not confuse the evaluation of the context with the evaluation of the intentional creative act
-
I am not suggesting that we cannot also evaluate an artwork in terms of the intentions of the creator. But we should not confuse the evaluation of the context with the evaluation of the intentional creative act
-
-
-
-
20
-
-
0042364690
-
Beauty and Evil: The Case of Leni Riefenstahl's Triumph of the Will
-
ed. Jerrold Levinson (Cambridge University Press)
-
Like other critics, Mary Devereaux, in her "Beauty and Evil: The Case of Leni Riefenstahl's Triumph of the Will" in Aesthetics and Ethics, ed. Jerrold Levinson (Cambridge University Press, 1998), seems to have difficulty in keeping distinct the role of the various functional contexts. She asks what role the evil of the portrayed events should play in evaluation, but neglects to consider how functioning might vary according to context. Consequently, she conflates cases where the evil is most relevant and where it is less so - among cinematographers for instance
-
(1998)
Aesthetics and Ethics
-
-
Devereaux, M.1
-
21
-
-
1942511098
-
-
Routledge
-
Beauty has long been regarded as an aesthetic property and criterion, but others have recently been identified. Noël Carroll, for instance, identifies three basic types of aesthetic properties - expressive, sensuous, and formal. See Noël Carroll, Philosophy of Art (Routledge, 1999), p. 168. I will not try to identify what counts as an aesthetic property or criterion, nor do I think it is necessary here. What is important is that some functioning is on the basis of factors that are not typically regarded as aesthetic - moral, political, religious, and pragmatic
-
(1999)
Philosophy of Art
, pp. 168
-
-
Carroll, N.1
-
22
-
-
80054578416
-
On Defining and Interpreting Art Intentionalistically
-
For an account of the distinctive functioning associated with artworks, see Susan Feagin, "On Defining and Interpreting Art Intentionalistically, " The British Journal of Aesthetics 17 (1977): 65-77
-
(1977)
The British Journal of Aesthetics
, vol.17
, pp. 65-77
-
-
Feagin, S.1
-
25
-
-
0003934790
-
-
University of Illinois Press
-
In their "diagnosis" of species, most contemporary taxonomists ("cladists") follow the example of Willi Hennig in his Phylogenetic Systematics (University of Illinois Press, 1979), p. 67
-
(1979)
Phylogenetic Systematics
, pp. 67
-
-
Hennig, W.1
-
26
-
-
0000216233
-
A Hierarchy of Species Concepts
-
ed. Michael F. Claridge, H.A. Dawah, and M.R. Wilson (London: Chapman and Hall)
-
See also Richard Mayden, "A Hierarchy of Species Concepts," in Species, the Units of Biodiversity, ed. Michael F. Claridge, H.A. Dawah, and M.R. Wilson (London: Chapman and Hall, 1997)
-
Species, the Units of Biodiversity
-
-
Mayden, R.1
-
27
-
-
80054607148
-
-
This paper has benefited greatly from the helpful criticism and suggestions of the Editor, Susan Feagin, and the anonymous referees. I am also indebted to Peter Achinstein, Max Hocutt, and James Otteson for their insight and criticism
-
This paper has benefited greatly from the helpful criticism and suggestions of the Editor, Susan Feagin, and the anonymous referees. I am also indebted to Peter Achinstein, Max Hocutt, and James Otteson for their insight and criticism
-
-
-
|