메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 59, Issue 1, 1997, Pages 97-125

Leo Strauss's confrontation with Max Weber: A search for a genuine social science

(1)  Behnegar, Nasser a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 34248099896     PISSN: 00346705     EISSN: 17486858     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S0034670500027170     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (11)

References (92)
  • 1
    • 2642673387 scopus 로고
    • trans. David Farrell Krell (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, emphasis added
    • Martin Heidegger, Nietzsche: The Will to Power as Art. trans. David Farrell Krell (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1981), pp. 4-5, emphasis added.
    • (1981) Nietzsche: The Will to Power As Art , pp. 4-5
    • Heidegger, M.1
  • 2
    • 0003687723 scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago, All unspecified references in the text are to this work
    • Strauss, Natural Right and History (Chicago: University of Chicago, 1950). All unspecified references in the text are to this work.
    • (1950) Natural Right and History
    • Strauss1
  • 3
    • 0004671733 scopus 로고
    • "Positivism necessarily transforms itself into historicism" , Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • "Positivism necessarily transforms itself into historicism" (Leo Strauss, What Is Political Philosophy? And Other Studies [Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1959], p. 26).
    • (1959) What Is Political Philosophy? and Other Studies , pp. 26
    • Strauss, L.1
  • 4
    • 77954124488 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • According to Strauss, positivistic political science is inferior to historicism in every respect except one: it has the merit of asserting, though in an inadequate manner, "the notion of the one truth, or as it would probably prefer to call it, of objectivity" ("The Crisis of Political Theory," in The Predicament of Modern Politics, ed. Harold J. Spaeth [Detroit: University of Detroit Press, 1964], p. 92)
    • According to Strauss, positivistic political science is inferior to historicism in every respect except one: it has the merit of asserting, though in an inadequate manner, "the notion of the one truth, or as it would probably prefer to call it, of objectivity" ("The Crisis of Political Theory," in The Predicament of Modern Politics, ed. Harold J. Spaeth [Detroit: University of Detroit Press, 1964], p. 92).
  • 5
    • 84971146922 scopus 로고
    • The new revolution in political science
    • 1051,1055
    • David Easton, "The New Revolution in Political Science," American Political Science Review 63 (1969): 1061, 1051, 1055
    • (1969) American Political Science Review , vol.63 , pp. 1061
    • Easton, D.1
  • 7
    • 77954120337 scopus 로고
    • ed. and trans. Edward Shils and Henry Finch (Glencoe, IL: Free Press, 50-51 [hereafterMSS]; "'Wissenshaft' is a far more inclusive term than 'science
    • Max Weber, Max Weber on the Methodology of Social Sciences, ed. and trans. Edward Shils and Henry Finch (Glencoe, IL: Free Press, 1949), pp. 18-19, 50-51 [hereafterMSS]; "'Wissenshaft' is a far more inclusive term than 'science.'
    • (1949) Max Weber on the Methodology of Social Sciences , pp. 18-19
    • Weber, M.1
  • 8
    • 0003585939 scopus 로고
    • Strauss's translation, 'philosophy or science/ correctly brings out the point that Weber's negative thesis-the denial of ultimate rationality to all moral and political choices-is far more sweeping than the slogan 'value-free science' indicates" , London: Routledge & Kegan Paul
    • Strauss's translation, 'philosophy or science/ correctly brings out the point that Weber's negative thesis-the denial of ultimate rationality to all moral and political choices-is far more sweeping than the slogan 'value-free science' indicates" (S. P. Turner and R. A. Factor, Max Weber and the Dispute over Reason and Value: A Study in Philosophy, Ethics, and Politics [London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1984], p. 183).
    • (1984) Max Weber and the Dispute over Reason and Value: A Study in Philosophy, Ethics, and Politics , pp. 183
    • Turner, S.P.1    Factor, R.A.2
  • 9
    • 0003476414 scopus 로고
    • "That science today is irreligious no one will doubt in his innermost being, even if he will not admit it to himself", ed. and trans, by H. H. Gerth and C. Wright Mills [New York: Oxford University Press, [hereafter MWES])
    • "That science today is irreligious no one will doubt in his innermost being, even if he will not admit it to himself" (Max Weber, From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology, ed. and trans, by H. H. Gerth and C. Wright Mills [New York: Oxford University Press, 1946], p. 142 [hereafter MWES]).
    • (1946) From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology , pp. 142
    • Weber, M.1
  • 10
    • 77954138160 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MWES, p. 148
    • MWES, p. 148
  • 11
    • 0003579903 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Roscher and knies: The logical problems of historical economics
    • Max Weber, Roscher and Knies: The Logical Problems of Historical Economics, trans. Guy Oakes (New York: Free Press, 1975), p. 116.
    • (1975) Trans. Guy Oakes (New York: Free Press , pp. 116
    • Weber, M.1
  • 13
    • 77954097545 scopus 로고
    • Why wasn't weber a nihilist?
    • ed. Kenneth L. Deutsch and Walter Soffer (New York: State University of New York Press
    • Robert Eden, "Why Wasn't Weber a Nihilist?," in The Crisis of Liberal Democracy: a Straussian perspective, ed. Kenneth L. Deutsch and Walter Soffer (New York: State University of New York Press, 1987), p. 212
    • (1987) The Crisis of Liberal Democracy: A Straussian Perspective , pp. 212
    • Eden, R.1
  • 14
    • 77954132126 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Weber and Nietzsche: Questioning the Liberation of Social Sciences from Historicism," in Max Weber and his Contemporaries, ed. Wolfgang J. Mommsen and Juergen Osterhammel (London: Allen & Unwin, 1987), p. 418
    • "Weber and Nietzsche: Questioning the Liberation of Social Sciences from Historicism," in Max Weber and his Contemporaries, ed. Wolfgang J. Mommsen and Juergen Osterhammel (London: Allen & Unwin, 1987), p. 418.
  • 15
    • 77954107503 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It would of course be foolish to take Strauss's conclusion for granted. There are, however, in principle only two legitimate responses: one must either show that modern science does not reject revelation or show that its rejection of revelation is based on sufficient reasons.
    • It would of course be foolish to take Strauss's conclusion for granted. There are, however, in principle only two legitimate responses: one must either show that modern science does not reject revelation or show that its rejection of revelation is based on sufficient reasons.
  • 16
    • 84971165964 scopus 로고
    • Review essay: Essays on the scientific study of politics: A critique
    • John H. Schaar and Sheldon S. Wolin, "Review Essay: Essays on the Scientific Study of Politics: A Critique," American Political Science Review 57 (1963): 125-150
    • (1963) American Political Science Review , vol.57 , pp. 125-150
    • Schaar, J.H.1    Wolin, S.S.2
  • 17
    • 0003761894 scopus 로고
    • trans. Michael S. Steinberg (Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • Wolfgang J. Mommsen, Max Weber and German Politics, trans. Michael S. Steinberg (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), p. 427.
    • (1984) Max Weber and German Politics , pp. 427
    • Mommsen, W.J.1
  • 18
    • 84857460887 scopus 로고
    • On reading plato today
    • Christopher Bruell's discussion of the contemporary obstacles to understanding Plato is especially useful for this task, ed. Michael Palmer and Thomas Pangle. (Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield
    • Christopher Bruell's discussion of the contemporary obstacles to understanding Plato is especially useful for this task. "On Reading Plato Today," in Political Philosophy and the Human Soul: Essays in Memory of Allan Bloom, ed. Michael Palmer and Thomas Pangle. (Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield, 1995), pp. 95-108.
    • (1995) Political Philosophy and the Human Soul: Essays in Memory of Allan Bloom , pp. 95-108
  • 20
    • 77954100177 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Xenophon Cynegeticus 13.6 quoted in Leo Strauss, Persecution and the Art of Writing (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1952), p. 29n.
    • Xenophon Cynegeticus 13.6 quoted in Leo Strauss, Persecution and the Art of Writing (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1952), p. 29n.
  • 22
    • 77954131857 scopus 로고
    • Max weber's position on science
    • ed. Peter Lassman, Irving Velody and Hermino Martins (London: Unwin Hyman
    • Karl Lowith, "Max Weber's Position on Science," in Max Weber's Science as a Vocation, ed. Peter Lassman, Irving Velody and Hermino Martins (London: Unwin Hyman, 1989), p. 153.
    • (1989) Max Weber's Science As A Vocation , pp. 153
    • Lowith, K.1
  • 24
    • 0002356824 scopus 로고
    • Strauss's natural right and history
    • Richard Kennington, "Strauss's Natural Right and History," Review of Metaphysics 35 (1981): 68.
    • (1981) Review of Metaphysics , vol.35 , pp. 68
    • Kennington, R.1
  • 25
    • 77954130676 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., pp. 69-70
    • Ibid., pp. 69-70.
  • 26
    • 0004243325 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • Leo Strauss, The City and Man (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1964), p. 74.
    • (1964) The City and Man , pp. 74
    • Strauss, L.1
  • 27
    • 77954122371 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Plato Republic 41 le; Strauss, The City and Man, pp. 74, 78, 84-85.
    • Plato Republic 41 le; Strauss, The City and Man, pp. 74, 78, 84-85.
  • 29
    • 77954103150 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 74
    • Ibid., p. 74.
  • 30
    • 77954110524 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 78
    • Ibid., p. 78.
  • 32
    • 77954105003 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 116
    • Ibid., p. 116.
  • 33
    • 77954139797 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Homer The Odyssey XII106-110
    • Homer The Odyssey XII106-110.
  • 34
    • 77954137062 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MSS, p. 12
    • MSS, p. 12.
  • 35
    • 77954107783 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MWES, p. 147
    • MWES, p. 147.
  • 36
    • 77954112248 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Although Strauss is known for his insistence that one should understand a thinker as he understood himself, his work on Weber shows clearly that he does not believe that social science should confine itself to this approach, for otherwise the social scientist "would have to bow without murmur to the self-interpretation of his subjects" (pp. 55-56). This approach is merely preparatory: before judging or explaining a doctrine in sociological or other terms, one must understand it exactly as its originator understood it (p. 57). But if self-interpretations can be erroneous, understanding a thinker better than he understood himself may be the true understanding
    • Although Strauss is known for his insistence that one should understand a thinker as he understood himself, his work on Weber shows clearly that he does not believe that social science should confine itself to this approach, for otherwise the social scientist "would have to bow without murmur to the self-interpretation of his subjects" (pp. 55-56). This approach is merely preparatory: before judging or explaining a doctrine in sociological or other terms, one must understand it exactly as its originator understood it (p. 57). But if self-interpretations can be erroneous, understanding a thinker better than he understood himself may be the true understanding.
  • 40
    • 77954120850 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Strauss's contention, therefore, is not refuted by Weber's alleged personal preference for the ethic of responsibility, for according to Weber's theory of values it is permissible to reject this ethic. Similarly, Brecht's contention that for Weber "values are unequal according to their different origins, implications, and consequences" contradicts Weber's discussion of syndicalism, which shows that these considerations are not decisive (Political Theory, p. 263
    • Strauss's contention, therefore, is not refuted by Weber's alleged personal preference for the ethic of responsibility, for according to Weber's theory of values it is permissible to reject this ethic. Similarly, Brecht's contention that for Weber "values are unequal according to their different origins, implications, and consequences" contradicts Weber's discussion of syndicalism, which shows that these considerations are not decisive (Political Theory, p. 263
  • 41
    • 77954137601 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MWES, pp. 120-121
    • MWES, pp. 120-121).
  • 42
    • 77954098575 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Regarding the consequences of the acceptance of this thesis by social science positivism, consider Strauss, What Is Political Philosophy?, p. 20
    • Regarding the consequences of the acceptance of this thesis by social science positivism, consider Strauss, What Is Political Philosophy?, p. 20.
  • 43
    • 77954095251 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Turner and Factor, Max Weber, p. 41
    • Turner and Factor, Max Weber, p. 41.
  • 44
    • 77954120851 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Guenther Roth's interpretation of this passage testifies to the strength of these temptations. He writes: "But Strauss is fair enough to denounce Reductio ad Hitlerum, the assertion that Weber's thinking led to fascism" (Reinhard Bendix and Guenther, Scholarship and Partisanship: Essays on Max Weber [Berkeley: University of California Press, 1971], p. 64). Strauss, however, argues that even if Weber's thoughts led to fascism, one cannot dismiss them because they can still be true
    • Guenther Roth's interpretation of this passage testifies to the strength of these temptations. He writes: "But Strauss is fair enough to denounce Reductio ad Hitlerum, the assertion that Weber's thinking led to fascism" (Reinhard Bendix and Guenther, Scholarship and Partisanship: Essays on Max Weber [Berkeley: University of California Press, 1971], p. 64). Strauss, however, argues that even if Weber's thoughts led to fascism, one cannot dismiss them because they can still be true.
  • 45
    • 77954104178 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Weber's nice distinction between "value judgments" and "reference to values" is untenable, because "reference to values presupposes appreciation of values," and this appreciation "enables and forces the social scientist to evaluate the social phenomena" (p. 63). Ernest Nagel sees the force of Strauss's criticism and therefore tries to defend value-free social science by making a distinction between "characterizing value judgments" and "appraising value judgments; He admits that science cannot dispense with "characterizing judgments," but he does not show why these judgments are more valid than appraising ones (Structure of Science, pp. 490-95)
    • Weber's nice distinction between "value judgments" and "reference to values" is untenable, because "reference to values presupposes appreciation of values," and this appreciation "enables and forces the social scientist to evaluate the social phenomena" (p. 63). Ernest Nagel sees the force of Strauss's criticism and therefore tries to defend value-free social science by making a distinction between "characterizing value judgments" and "appraising value judgments; He admits that science cannot dispense with "characterizing judgments," but he does not show why these judgments are more valid than appraising ones (Structure of Science, pp. 490-95).
  • 46
    • 77954114292 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But compare Strauss, What Is Political Philosophy?, p. 22.
    • But compare Strauss, What Is Political Philosophy?, p. 22.
  • 47
    • 77954132837 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 22
    • Ibid., p. 22.
  • 48
    • 77954106690 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid
    • Ibid.,
  • 49
    • 77954113313 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Consider Weber's criticism of the attitude of "the mere 'power politician'" for having no relation to the knowledge of tragedy with which all action is truly interwoven (MWES, pp. 116-17). Weber's belief in the supremacy of conflict is the common link that explains the otherwise mysterious connection between Weber's inaugural lecture (Gesammelte Politische Schriften, ed. Johannes Winckelman [Tubingen: J. C. B. Mohr, 1958], pp. 1-25) and his later writings which are based on the notion of a value-free social science
    • Consider Weber's criticism of the attitude of "the mere 'power politician'" for having no relation to the knowledge of tragedy with which all action is truly interwoven (MWES, pp. 116-17). Weber's belief in the supremacy of conflict is the common link that explains the otherwise mysterious connection between Weber's inaugural lecture (Gesammelte Politische Schriften, ed. Johannes Winckelman [Tubingen: J. C. B. Mohr, 1958], pp. 1-25) and his later writings which are based on the notion of a value-free social science.
  • 50
    • 77954099402 scopus 로고
    • The roman caesar with christ's soul
    • Compare this with Nietzsche's preference for tragedy (26n.) and his description of the future ruler as , trans. Walter Kaufman and R. J. Hollingdale [New York: Random House
    • Compare this with Nietzsche's preference for tragedy (26n.) and his description of the future ruler as "the Roman Caesar with Christ's soul" (The Will to Power, trans. Walter Kaufman and R. J. Hollingdale [New York: Random House,1967], p. 513).
    • (1967) The Will to Power , pp. 513
  • 52
    • 77954131008 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MSS, p. 16
    • MSS, p. 16.
  • 54
    • 77954122914 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also 70n
    • see also 70n.
  • 55
    • 77954128358 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MWES, p. 143
    • MWES, p. 143
  • 56
    • 77954133935 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MSS, p. 110
    • MSS, p. 110
  • 58
    • 77954128636 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MWES, pp. 140-143
    • MWES, pp. 140-143
  • 59
    • 77954096096 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MSS, p. 84.
    • MSS, p. 84.
  • 60
    • 77954096727 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 110.
    • Ibid., p. 110.
  • 62
    • 77954102886 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • MWES, pp. 350-357 Strauss argues that Spinoza's ultimate critique of revelation was his argument that "the world and human life are perfectly intelligible without the assumption of a mysterious God," but that Spinoza's system, and every other system, failed to give such an account. Spinoza's Critique of Religion, trans. E. M. Sinclair (New York: Schocken Books, 1965), pp. 28-29. Science, therefore, came to understand itself as infinitely progressive. Weber realized that this really is an unacknowledged admission by science of its defeat: an infinitely progressive science is meaningless and leads to weariness instead of satiety (MWES, pp. 137-40,356). Whereas science presupposes that its object is accessible to reason, the infinitely progressive character of science suggests that "one can say with at least equal right that it [the object of science] is radically mysterious" (Strauss, "Relativism," in Relativism and the Study of Man, ed. Helmut Schoeck and J. W. Wiggens [Princeton: Van Nostrand, 1961], p. 154).
  • 63
    • 77954109970 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MWES, pp. 152-153
    • MWES, pp. 152-153
  • 64
    • 77954106424 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid.; Weber, Protestant Ethic, p. 182.
    • Ibid.; Weber, Protestant Ethic, p. 182.
  • 67
    • 77954092824 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Compare Strauss's account with Weber's argument about the conflict between science and religion: being unable to answer with certainty the question of its own ultimate presupposition and being compelled in the name of intellectual integrity to regard the possession of rational culture as the highest good, the intellect not only shoulders the burden of ethical guilt, but also, and more decisively, is marked with "senselessness-if this cultural value is to be judged in terms of its own standard" (MWES, p. 355).
    • Compare Strauss's account with Weber's argument about the conflict between science and religion: being unable to answer with certainty the question of its own ultimate presupposition and being compelled in the name of intellectual integrity to regard the possession of rational culture as the highest good, the intellect not only shoulders the burden of ethical guilt, but also, and more decisively, is marked with "senselessness-if this cultural value is to be judged in terms of its own standard" (MWES, p. 355).
  • 68
    • 77954129124 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MWES, pp. 323-359 Moreover, since Strauss does not share Weber's preference for tragedy, Strauss takes more seriously both revelation's claim and philosophy's claim to be the one thing needful (compare pp. 74-75 with Weber, MWES, pp. 148-49). Whereas Weber suggests that we should combine the ethics of intention and the ethics of responsibility (MWES, p. 127), Strauss argues that we can be either philosophers or theologians but not both.
    • MWES, pp. 323-359 Moreover, since Strauss does not share Weber's preference for tragedy, Strauss takes more seriously both revelation's claim and philosophy's claim to be the one thing needful (compare pp. 74-75 with Weber, MWES, pp. 148-49). Whereas Weber suggests that we should combine the ethics of intention and the ethics of responsibility (MWES, p. 127), Strauss argues that we can be either philosophers or theologians but not both.
  • 69
    • 77954096488 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Perhaps, a metaphysically neutral science would not be at odds with the Bible. But Strauss suggests that the non-neutrality of social science becomes visible in its analysis of religion: "The new science uses sociological or psychological theories regarding religion which exclude, without considering it, the possibility that religion rests ultimately on God's revealing Himself to man" (Liberalism: Ancient and Modern [Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1968], p. 218). The question is whether this apparent agnosticism is compatible with reverence for revelation or whether it "is actually doubt or distrust" of revelation. It should go without saying that the existence of pious social scientists does not affect the answer to this question
    • Perhaps, a metaphysically neutral science would not be at odds with the Bible. But Strauss suggests that the non-neutrality of social science becomes visible in its analysis of religion: "The new science uses sociological or psychological theories regarding religion which exclude, without considering it, the possibility that religion rests ultimately on God's revealing Himself to man" (Liberalism: Ancient and Modern [Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1968], p. 218). The question is whether this apparent agnosticism is compatible with reverence for revelation or whether it "is actually doubt or distrust" of revelation. It should go without saying that the existence of pious social scientists does not affect the answer to this question.
  • 70
    • 77954103149 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Strauss, therefore, suggests that the Scholastic synthesis of philosophy and Christian revelation was really an attempt to resolve the conflict in favor of revelation. It was on account of this attempted resolution that philosophy first lost its character as a way of life and became an instrument or a department, a view which has survived Scholasticism and continues to obscure the conflict between philosophy and revelation
    • Strauss, therefore, suggests that the Scholastic synthesis of philosophy and Christian revelation was really an attempt to resolve the conflict in favor of revelation. It was on account of this attempted resolution that philosophy first lost its character as a way of life and became an instrument or a department, a view which has survived Scholasticism and continues to obscure the conflict between philosophy and revelation.
  • 71
    • 77954125449 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MSS, p. 16.
    • MSS, p. 16.
  • 72
    • 77954101225 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Plato The Apology 20d-22e
    • Plato The Apology 20d-22e.
  • 74
    • 77954138436 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Micah 6:8. This philosophic enterprise should not be confused with a polemic against religion, which seeks to discredit or weaken religion by hook or by crook
    • Micah 6:8. This philosophic enterprise should not be confused with a polemic against religion, which seeks to discredit or weaken religion by hook or by crook.
  • 75
    • 77954090935 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Strauss, What Is Political Philosophy?, p. 104. Consider also Weber's contention that those who wanted to politicize the German university were turning it "into a theological seminary-except that it does not have the latter's religious dignity" (MSS, p. 7)
    • Strauss, What Is Political Philosophy?, p. 104. Consider also Weber's contention that those who wanted to politicize the German university were turning it "into a theological seminary-except that it does not have the latter's religious dignity" (MSS, p. 7).
  • 76
    • 77954120849 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It may be objected that Easton was not concerned with fundamental riddles, but with important political issues such as urban riots and Vietnam. Yet there is a kinship between resoluteness in following moral and political agendas and the disregard of precision, a disregard nourished by a hope based on either secular or religious faith that one's actions will prove to be correct. Consider Weber's argument that "some kind of faith must always exist" for a politician, because "the final result of political action often, no, even regularly, stands in completely inadequate and often even paradoxical relation to its original meaning" (MWES, p. 117)
    • It may be objected that Easton was not concerned with fundamental riddles, but with important political issues such as urban riots and Vietnam. Yet there is a kinship between resoluteness in following moral and political agendas and the disregard of precision, a disregard nourished by a hope based on either secular or religious faith that one's actions will prove to be correct. Consider Weber's argument that "some kind of faith must always exist" for a politician, because "the final result of political action often, no, even regularly, stands in completely inadequate and often even paradoxical relation to its original meaning" (MWES, p. 117).
  • 78
    • 77954129910 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But must the agreement be an agreement about "ultimate values"? Has not liberalism shown that this is not necessarily the case? To respond adequately to these serious objections, one must investigate the importance of the critique of religion for liberalism. One must also consider Strauss's contention that"a society that tolerates indefinitely many Weltanschauungen does this by virtue of one particular Weltanschauung"(Studies in Platonic Political Philosophy, p. 37)
    • But must the agreement be an agreement about "ultimate values"? Has not liberalism shown that this is not necessarily the case? To respond adequately to these serious objections, one must investigate the importance of the critique of religion for liberalism. One must also consider Strauss's contention that"a society that tolerates indefinitely many Weltanschauungen does this by virtue of one particular Weltanschauung"(Studies in Platonic Political Philosophy, p. 37).
  • 79
    • 17544368130 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Weber suggests that the harmony between religion and politics was shattered by the emergence of universalistic religions of salvation, or more precisely, by the emergence of Christianity. Christianity, however, is still a social phenomenon. Although it came into conflict with the natural sib and the political orders of the world, it did not undermine the authority of the community but sought to reformulate and strengthen its basis. Accordingly, "prophecy has created a new social community" (MWES, pp. 333, 328-29)
    • Strauss, "The Spirit of Sparta or the Taste of Xenophon," p. 532. Weber suggests that the harmony between religion and politics was shattered by the emergence of universalistic religions of salvation, or more precisely, by the emergence of Christianity. Christianity, however, is still a social phenomenon. Although it came into conflict with the natural sib and the political orders of the world, it did not undermine the authority of the community but sought to reformulate and strengthen its basis. Accordingly, "prophecy has created a new social community" (MWES, pp. 333, 328-29).
    • The Spirit of Sparta or the Taste of Xenophon , pp. 532
    • Strauss1
  • 81
    • 84889360058 scopus 로고
    • An unspoken prologue to a public lecture at St. John's
    • Leo Strauss, "An Unspoken Prologue to a Public Lecture at St. John's," Interpretation 7:3 (1978): 2.
    • (1978) Interpretation , vol.7 , Issue.3 , pp. 2
    • Strauss, L.1
  • 83
    • 77954090934 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid
    • Ibid.,
  • 84
    • 77954138774 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Turner and Factor, Max Weber, p. 119.
    • Turner and Factor, Max Weber, p. 119.
  • 85
    • 77954092823 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Strauss argues that divine guidance originally took the form of divine laws, which informed man not only about his obligations to gods but also to other men. Concern for justice seems to be the common ground between classical philosophers and believers. If it is true "that the moral principles have a greater evidence than the teachings even of natural theology" (p. 164), one might hope that the quarrel between philosophy and revelation could be settled by an examination of the nature of justice
    • Strauss argues that divine guidance originally took the form of divine laws, which informed man not only about his obligations to gods but also to other men. Concern for justice seems to be the common ground between classical philosophers and believers. If it is true "that the moral principles have a greater evidence than the teachings even of natural theology" (p. 164), one might hope that the quarrel between philosophy and revelation could be settled by an examination of the nature of justice.
  • 86
    • 77954126231 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chapter 1 Strauss argues that in order to understand the issue between historicism and nonhistoricist philosophy we must have a nonhistoricist understanding of classical philosophy (the subject of chapter 4) and "an understanding of the genesis of historicism that does not take for granted the soundness of historicism" (the subjects of chapters 5 and 6). Political life seems to have been the original matrix of both history and divine revelation
    • In chapter 1 Strauss argues that in order to understand the issue between historicism and nonhistoricist philosophy we must have a nonhistoricist understanding of classical philosophy (the subject of chapter 4) and "an understanding of the genesis of historicism that does not take for granted the soundness of historicism" (the subjects of chapters 5 and 6). Political life seems to have been the original matrix of both history and divine revelation.
  • 88
    • 77954106951 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MSS, p. 18
    • MSS, p. 18.
  • 92
    • 77954121837 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "As far as I know, the present-day arguments in favor of revelation against philosophy are based on an inadequate understanding of classical philosophy" (ibid., p. 300, emphasis added). The classical response to revelation would not lead to the spiritual exhaustion of the individual, if it does not presuppose the solution to the riddle of being. In fact, one may argue that response is necessary so that we may become free to articulate that riddle
    • "As far as I know, the present-day arguments in favor of revelation against philosophy are based on an inadequate understanding of classical philosophy" (ibid., p. 300, emphasis added). The classical response to revelation would not lead to the spiritual exhaustion of the individual, if it does not presuppose the solution to the riddle of being. In fact, one may argue that response is necessary so that we may become free to articulate that riddle.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.