메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 63, Issue 4, 2001, Pages 693-722

Metamorphosis or palingenesis? Political change in kant

(1)  Williams, Howard a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 34248082642     PISSN: 00346705     EISSN: 17486858     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S0034670500032137     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (15)

References (74)
  • 1
    • 0012129895 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a discussion of Kant's relationship with the biological sciences see, (Chicago: Chicago University Press)
    • For a discussion of Kant's relationship with the biological sciences see J. H. Zammito, The Genesis of Kant's Critique of Judgment (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1992), pp. 199-213.
    • (1992) The Genesis of Kant's Critique of Judgment , pp. 199-213
    • Zammito, J.H.1
  • 3
    • 0003803948 scopus 로고
    • Also (Ithaca: Cornell University Press) . As Rosen illustrates Kant believed that the leaders of states had to be active in fulfilling their roles: "For Kant, then, the state has three principal functions and obligations: a duty of justice to ensure a condition of maximum lawgoverned freedom; a duty of benevolence to provide for the needs of its subjects; and a teleological responsibility to create the framework within which all forms of human rationality can flourish" (p. 218).
    • Also Allen D. Rosen, Kant's Theory of Justice (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1993). As Rosen illustrates Kant believed that the leaders of states had to be active in fulfilling their roles: "For Kant, then, the state has three principal functions and obligations: a duty of justice to ensure a condition of maximum lawgoverned freedom; a duty of benevolence to provide for the needs of its subjects; and a teleological responsibility to create the framework within which all forms of human rationality can flourish" (p. 218).
    • (1993) Kant's Theory of Justice
    • Allen, D.1    Rosen2
  • 4
    • 33745690264 scopus 로고
    • Kant's concept of the state
    • On Kant's developmental view of politics see ed. H.Williams (Chicago: University of Chicago Press)
    • On Kant's developmental view of politics see W. Kersting, "Kant's Concept of the State," inEssays on Kant's Political Philosophy, ed. H.Williams (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992), pp. 143-165
    • (1992) Essays on Kant's Political Philosophy , pp. 143-165
    • Kersting, W.1
  • 5
    • 77954037579 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • References to Kant's works are made to the Akademieausgabe (Berlin:Prussian Academy Edition, 1902 onwards), hereafter AA. References to the Critique of Pure Reason are to the first (A) and second editions (B). "Popular enlightenment is the public instruction of the people upon their duties and rights towards the state to which they belong. Since this concerns only natural rights and rights which can be derived from ordinary common sense, their obvious exponents and interpreters among the people will not be officials appointed by the state, but free teachers of right, i.e. the philosophers" (Kant's Political Writings, ed. H. Reiss [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991], p. 186/AA 7: 89.
  • 6
    • 85012511352 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some kantian reflections of a world republic
    • For two recent accounts of Kant's ideal of a world community see
    • For two recent accounts of Kant's ideal of a world community see O. Hoeffe, "Some Kantian Reflections of a World Republic," Kantian Review 2 (1998): 51-71
    • (1998) Kantian Review , vol.2 , pp. 51-71
    • Hoeffe, O.1
  • 7
    • 85012477024 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kant's cosmopolitan law: World citizenship for a global order
    • and
    • and P. Kleingeld, "Kant's Cosmopolitan Law: World Citizenship for a Global Order," Kantian Review 2 (1998): pp. 72-90.
    • (1998) Kantian Review , vol.2 , pp. 72-90
    • Kleingeld, P.1
  • 8
    • 77954056157 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a full discussion of Kant's international thought see, J. Bohman and M. Lutz-Bachmann eds. (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press) .Allgemeines Handwoerterbuch derphilosophischen Wissenschaften nebst ihrer Literatur und Geschichte, vol. 2, second revised edition (Leipzig: Brockhaus, 1833), p. 867
    • For a full discussion of Kant's international thought see J. Bohman and M. Lutz-Bachmann eds. Perpetual Peace: Essays on Kant's Cosmopolitan Ideal (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1997). 5.Allgemeines Handwoerterbuch derphilosophischen Wissenschaften nebst ihrer Literatur und Geschichte, vol.2, second revised edition (Leipzig: Brockhaus, 1833), p. 867.
    • (1997) Perpetual Peace: Essays on Kant's Cosmopolitan Ideal , pp. 5
  • 10
    • 0003757705 scopus 로고
    • London: Institute of Germanic Studies, Nisbet interestingly stresses the influence of Charles Bonnet's inquiries upon Goethe. A recent edition of Goethe's elegy is Metamorphose der Pflanzen (Stuttgart: Freiesgstl., 1992, p. 78
    • H. B. Nisbet, Goethe and the Scientific Tradition (London: Institute of Germanic Studies, 1972), p. 9. Nisbet interestingly stresses the influence of Charles Bonnet's inquiries upon Goethe. A recent edition of Goethe's elegy is Metamorphose der Pflanzen (Stuttgart: Freiesgstl., 1992), p. 78.
    • (1972) Goethe and the Scientific Tradition , pp. 9
    • Nisbet, H.B.1
  • 11
    • 77954069402 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In Reviews of Herder's 'Ideas on the Philosophy of History of Mankind' Kant refers to the "transformation of maggots or caterpillars into little flying creatures" as a wholly individual and "unusual occurrence in nature" (Kant's Political Writings, p. 208/AA 8: 53). Kant, who was very fond of quoting Voltaire, may well have been familiar with Voltaire's entry on Metamorphosis in his Philosophical Dictionary where he writes: "A nearly imperceptible speck becomes a worm, the worm becomes a butterfly. An acorn is transformed into an oak, an egg into a bird. Water becomes cloud and thunder. Wood changes into fire and ashes. In short everything in nature appears to be metamorphosed" (Philosophical Dictionary [London: Penguin 1971], p. 310)
    • In "Reviews of Herder's 'Ideas on the Philosophy of History of Mankind'" Kant refers to the "transformation of maggots or caterpillars into little flying creatures" as a wholly individual and "unusual occurrence in nature" (Kant's Political Writings, p. 208/AA 8: 53). Kant, who was very fond of quoting Voltaire, may well have been familiar with Voltaire's entry on Metamorphosis in his Philosophical Dictionary where he writes: "A nearly imperceptible speck becomes a worm, the worm becomes a butterfly. An acorn is transformed into an oak, an egg into a bird. Water becomes cloud and thunder. Wood changes into fire and ashes. In short everything in nature appears to be metamorphosed" (Philosophical Dictionary [London: Penguin, 1971], p. 310).
  • 12
    • 77954054702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • The Contest of the Faculties (New York: Abaris Books, 1979), p. 99/AA 7: 55: "The idea of a moral metamorphosis (but only through supernatural influence) of the human being may well have been going on in believers' heads for a long time; but only in more recent times has it been clearly enunciated and given rise to a division of sects between the followers of Spener and Franck (Pietists) and the Moravian Brethren of Zinzendorf (Moravians) on the doctrine of conversion." From what follows it seems that Kant associates the idea of metamorphosis with "radical change" (p. 991 AA p. 55) "improvement" and "becoming a new person", (p. 100/ AA p. 56) (Rebirth without death).
  • 13
    • 77954075055 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kant's Political Writings, p. 208/AA 8: 53
    • Kant's Political Writings, p. 208/AA 8: 53.
  • 14
    • 77954075546 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • J. R. Tata, Metamorphosis (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1973); p. 3.
    • (1973) Metamorphosis , pp. 3
    • Tata, J.R.1
  • 15
    • 77954079788 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Allgemeines Handwoerterbuch, 3: 142
    • Allgemeines Handwoerterbuch, 3:142.
  • 16
    • 77954036629 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid
    • Ibid,.
  • 17
    • 77954068169 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid
    • Ibid,.
  • 18
    • 0004291536 scopus 로고
    • trans. M. Gregor (Cambridge: University of Cambridge Press)
    • Metaphysics of Morals, trans. M. Gregor (Cambridge: University of Cambridge Press, 1991), pp.147-48;
    • (1991) Metaphysics of Morals , pp. 147-48
  • 19
    • 77954062770 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A A pp. 339-340 (hereafter MM)
    • A A, pp. 339-340 (hereafter MM).
  • 20
    • 77954061761 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid. 148/AA 6: 340
    • Ibid., 148/AA 6: 340.
  • 21
    • 77954049590 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid
    • Ibid,.
  • 22
    • 77954080026 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • A recent commentator who has used the term palingenesis in a political metaphorical sense is the political scientist Roger Griffin. In The Nature of Fascism (London: Routledge, 1993), he uses the term in a strikingly similar sense to Kant. Griffin uses the term to define fascism and also by implication to rule out as unacceptable certain forms of political change. As Griffin sees it, "fascism is a genus of political ideology whose mythic core in its various permutations is a palingenetic form of populist ultra-nationalism" (p. 27). Griffin points out how unusual is the use of the term palingenesis nowadays "even in the spheres of theology and biology" and suggests it may even be obsolete in modern English (p. 33). Nevertheless he finds it useful, as have a number of commentators on fascism, as a means of describing the kind of political upheaval and transformation fascists generally have in mind (p. 33). Griffin employs palingenesis "as a generic term for the vision of a radically new beginning which follows a period of destruction or perceived dissolution." Fascists quite often saw themselves as fighting against national decadence and saw themselves as countering this through an attempted regeneration of the nation. Griffin does not see this preoccupation with regeneration and a return to a lost past as confined to fascist political doctrine. As he sees it, "the most obvious well-head of palingenetic myth in the wider sense is religion. The resurrection of Jesus Christ places one such myth at the very centre of a whole faith." As he further remarks, "notions of metaphorical (to believers, metaphysical) death and rebirth pervade the symbolism of baptism, communion, and Easter celebrations, while generations of Christian mystics have elaborated intricate verbal, pictorial and ritual mythologies to invoke the reality of spiritual rebirth on a higher plane of being after dying to the world of flesh" (p. 33). The connection that Griffin makes between palingenesis and the mythology of Christianity is extremely interesting from the standpoint of the interpretation of Kant's philosophy. Kant is well known for his objection to the literal interpretation of the Biblical story of Christ's life and death. In Kant's Religion within the Limits of Pure Reason Alone we are told the true significance of the account of Jesus Christ's life lies in the moral dimension. The rational person takes the biblical story as a symbolic indication of how we might truly become virtuous and not as an empirical guide as to how the world is. Kant is extremely skeptical about all organized religion and does not recommend that one should become a member of any Christian sect. Kant is also very wary of the mystical side of religion. He believes we would be mistaken to rely on theoretical ideas which inevitably take us beyond the bounds of ordinary experience. Possibly this may underlie his strong antipathy to the transfer of religious imagery concerning resurrection, rebirth and transformation into the political realm. He may have seen the notion of metamorphosis as having a much more secular and unemotional ring to it than the notion of palingenesis.
  • 23
    • 0040157803 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Another recent commentator who has looked closely at Kant's use of the term is, (Chicago: Chicago University Press) ,240, and 420
    • Another recent commentator who has looked closely at Kant's use of the term is S. Shell, The Embodiment of Reason (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1996), pp. 195,240, and 420.
    • (1996) The Embodiment of Reason , pp. 195
    • Shell, S.1
  • 24
    • 77954051492 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Charles Bonnet's La Palingenesie philosophique, ou idees sur le' etatfutur des etres vivans, 2vols. Geneva: Chez Caude Philibert et Bathelmi Chirol, 1769)
    • Charles Bonnet's La Palingenesie philosophique, ou idees sur le' etatfutur des etres vivans, 2vols. (Geneva: Chez Caude Philibert et Bathelmi Chirol, 1769).
  • 25
    • 77954050336 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • In the first twelve volumes of the Academy edition of Kant's writings the term is used seven times: 2: 256; 3: 450; 6: 340; 8: 9: 365; 10:161; 10: 161. The final reference is made in a letter from Hamann to Kant. Kant uses the term almost synonymously with "rebirth" as, for instance, in the first reference from Observations on the feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime: "The monastic vows made out of a great portion of useful men numerous companies of diligent idlers, whose brooding way of life fitted them for hatching out a thousand scholarly grotesqueries, which went thence out into the larger world and spread their kind. Finally, after the human genius has happily raised itself anew from an almost complete destruction by a kind of palingenesis in our own days we see the sound taste of the beautiful and noble blossoming forth both in the arts and sciences and in respect to morals." The fifth reference in Kant's Physical Geography (9: 365) speaks significantly and, in a similar vein, of the "fable of the palingenesis of plants.
  • 26
    • 77954064447 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A683/B711
    • A683/B711.
  • 27
    • 77950030815 scopus 로고
    • Cf. Cambridge Edition of the Works of lmmanuel Kant, trans, and ed. David Walford and Ralf Meerbote (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
    • Cf. Cambridge Edition of the Works oflmmanuel Kant, Theoretical Philosophy, 1755-1770, trans, and ed. David Walford and Ralf Meerbote (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992);
    • (1992) Theoretical Philosophy , pp. 1755-1770
  • 28
    • 0010700857 scopus 로고
    • and, New Haven: Yale University Press
    • and E. Cassirer, Kant's Life and Thought, (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1981), pp. 79-82.
    • (1981) Kant's Life and Thought , pp. 79-82
    • Cassirer, E.1
  • 29
    • 77954044108 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MM 131IAA 6: 320
    • MM 131IAA 6: 320.
  • 30
    • 77954049589 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In a curious postscript to his book The Nature of Fascism Griffin remarks that "the horrific consequences of fascism" can be ascribed to "its mythic core of a palingenetic vision, a vision which encourages, not a creative interaction and healthy integration with the external world, but a total and perverse identification with only a narrow part of it" (p. 236). This might imply that Griffin entirely rejects the notion of a political resurrection and that it was the pursuit of such a wholly fresh start that led to the disasters of fascism. But this is not so. In a wholly un-Kantian turn he goes on to argue, "perhaps there is still time for the course of history to be changed by the force of a healthy palingenetic movement, a supra-national movement of ecological humanism working from below and above which centres its hopes, not on 'one people, one empire, one leader/ but on 'one humanity, one life, one world'" (p. 236). Griffinhere demonstrates strikingly the continuing appeal of a form of political change which Kant wholly rejects.
  • 32
    • 0005351854 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. L. B. Eyre (New York: Alfred A. Knopf)
    • Erik Nordenskiold, The History of Biology, trans. L. B. Eyre (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1928), p. 244.
    • (1928) The History of Biology , pp. 244
    • Nordenskiold, E.1
  • 34
    • 77954036628 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 245
    • Ibid., p. 245.
  • 35
    • 77954078509 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 244
    • Ibid., p. 244.
  • 37
    • 77954044615 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • According to Raymond Savioz, La Philosophie de Charles Bonnet de Geneve, (Paris: Libraire Philosophique J. Vrin, 1948), the publication of the translation of Bonnet's book on palingenesis "exercised a great influence" in Germany (p. 341).
  • 38
    • 77954057632 scopus 로고
    • For the published Correspondence between Lavater and Mendelssohn, and Mendelssohn and Bonnet see, (Brockhaus: Leipzig)
    • For the published Correspondence between Lavater and Mendelssohn, and Mendelssohn and Bonnet see M. Mendelssohn, Gesammelte Schriften, vol 33 (Brockhaus: Leipzig, 1843), pp. 37-127.
    • (1843) Gesammelte Schriften , vol.33 , pp. 37-127
    • Mendelssohn, M.1
  • 39
    • 77954079532 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kant corresponded with both Lavater and Mendelssohn in the 1770s when the controversy was at its height. Kant's detailed philosophical correspondence with Mendelssohn began in 1766 in Letters 38 and 39 (AA X, pp.67-73) and his more reticent correspondence with Lavater in 1774 in Letters 81 and 81a (AA X, pp.148-50). It is highly likely therefore that Kant would have been aware of what was at issue between the two
    • Kant corresponded with both Lavater and Mendelssohn in the 1770s when the controversy was at its height. Kant's detailed philosophical correspondence with Mendelssohn began in 1766 in Letters 38 and 39 (AA X, pp.67-73) and his more reticent correspondence with Lavater in 1774 in Letters 81 and 81a (AA X, pp.148-50). It is highly likely therefore that Kant would have been aware of what was at issue between the two.
  • 42
    • 77954045580 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • For Bonnet "there is no true generation in nature; but we improperly call generation the beginning of a development that makes visible to us what we previously had not been able to perceive" (Roger, Life Sciences in Eighteenth Century, p. 501).
  • 45
    • 77954071483 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For him the created universe was not immutable. Perhaps it had undergone great revolutions, and the account of Genesis might well be describing to us, not the creation of the world, but the last of those revolutions" (Roger, Life Sciences in Eighteenth Century French Thought, p. 507
    • "For him the created universe was not immutable. Perhaps it had undergone great revolutions, and the account of Genesis might well be describing to us, not the creation of the world, but the last of those revolutions" (Roger, Life Sciences in Eighteenth Century French Thought, p. 507
  • 47
    • 77954063270 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Critique of Pure Reason, A668/B696. See Roger, The Life Sciences in Eighteenth Century, "Bonnet had read Leibniz's Theodicy in 1748 which had been 'one of the most important moments in his intellectual life.'" p. 498.
  • 48
    • 77954055820 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Critique of Pure Reason, A668/B696
    • Critique of Pure Reason, A668/B696.
  • 49
    • 77954074808 scopus 로고
    • The publication of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason presented Bonnet in his later years, with a challenge to the 'psychological principles' with which he had worked all his life, regarding the way in which we come to knowledge of the exterior world through sensations (experience) as well as the way in which we have access to a direct apperception of our soul, of its unity or simplicity, through the sentiment intime. "Certainly Kant reversed the direction Bonnet had moved in for the latter's efforts to establish a 'science of the soul' had meant, from the start, binding psychology more directly to physiology." And at the end of 1788, Bonnet was moved to write several precis and commentaries on that work (CPR) and to conclude that Kant's strange doctrines tend to reverse all received opinion in rational psychology, "and even to annihilate all metaphysics. He ceaselessly shook the sources of all our knowledge, sentiment intime and experience" [Dordrecht/Boston: D.Riedel]
    • "The publication of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason presented Bonnet in his later years, with a challenge to the 'psychological principles' with which he had worked all his life, regarding the way in which we come to knowledge of the exterior world through sensations (experience) as well as the way in which we have access to a direct apperception of our soul, of its unity or simplicity, through the sentiment intime." "Certainly Kant reversed the direction Bonnet had moved in for the latter's efforts to establish a 'science of the soul' had meant, from the start, binding psychology more directly to physiology." And at the end of 1788, Bonnet was moved to write several precis and commentaries on that work (CPR) and to conclude that Kant's strange doctrines tend to reverse all received opinion in rational psychology, "and even to annihilate all metaphysics. He ceaselessly shook the sources of all our knowledge, sentiment intime and experience" (Lorin Anderson, Charles Bonnet and the order of the known [Dordrecht/Boston: D.Riedel, 1982], p. 28).
    • (1982) Charles Bonnet and the Order of the Known , pp. 28
    • Anderson, L.1
  • 51
    • 77954082023 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reviews of herder's ideas on the philosophy of history of mankind
    • AA 8:53
    • "Reviews of Herder's Ideas on the Philosophy of History of Mankind," Kant's Political Writings, p. 208/AA 8: 53.
    • Kant's Political Writings , pp. 208
  • 52
    • 0010170368 scopus 로고
    • Kant and evolution
    • Ibid. Arthur Lovejoy regards the essay on Herder's Ideas as evidence of Kant's antagonism toward evolutionary theory, ed. Bentley Glass [Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press] . Kant clearly repudiates in the essay the outlook of Bonnet and Herder which attempts to trace all species back to the one original germ, but Kant does not reject altogether the possibility of the continuous gradation of natural creatures" ("Reviews of Herder's Ideas on the Philosophy of History of Mankind," 208/AA 8: 53). What Kant wants most of all to distance himself from is the metaphysics of Bonnet and Herder who try to find in the continuity of species evidence for the immortality of the individual human being
    • Ibid. Arthur Lovejoy regards the essay on Herder's Ideas as evidence of Kant's antagonism toward evolutionary theory (A. Lovejoy, "Kant and Evolution," in Forerunners of Darwin, ed. Bentley Glass [Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1959], pp. 189-190). Kant clearly repudiates in the essay the outlook of Bonnet and Herder which attempts to trace all species back to the one original germ, but Kant does not reject altogether the possibility of the "continuous gradation of natural creatures" ("Reviews of Herder's Ideas on the Philosophy of History of Mankind," 208/AA 8: 53). What Kant wants most of all to distance himself from is the metaphysics of Bonnet and Herder who try to find in the continuity of species evidence for the immortality of the individual human being.
    • (1959) Forerunners of Darwin , pp. 189-190
    • Lovejoy, A.1
  • 54
    • 77954042249 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MM 148/AA 6: 341
    • MM 148/AA 6: 341.
  • 55
    • 77954051025 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid
    • Ibid,.
  • 56
    • 77954074809 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid
    • Ibid,.
  • 57
    • 0002185974 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a full discussion of the concept of character in Kant's philosophy see (Chicago: Chicago University Press), For a discussion of our hierarchy of aptitudes see, in particular, pp. 111
    • For a full discussion of the concept of character in Kant's philosophy see G. Felicitas Munzel, Kant's Conception of Moral Character (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1999). For a discussion of our hierarchy of aptitudes see, in particular, pp.111.
    • (1999) Kant's Conception of Moral Character
    • Felicitas Munzel, G.1
  • 58
    • 77954061492 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View (Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press 1978), p. 202
    • Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View (Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press, 1978), p. 202;
  • 59
    • 77954058870 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AA, 7: 292
    • AA, 7: 292.
  • 60
    • 77954036627 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 247
    • Ibid., p. 247;
  • 61
    • 77954074088 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • AA, 7:329. (The term revolution does not occur in the English translation, although it appears in the original.)
    • AA, 7:329. (The term revolution does not occur in the English translation, although it appears in the original.)
  • 62
  • 65
    • 77954064446 scopus 로고
    • A. Liebich, ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press) ,55n
    • A. Liebich, ed., Selected Writings of August Cieszkowski (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979), pp. 22,55n.
    • (1979) Selected Writings of August Cieszkowski , pp. 22
  • 66
    • 77954054845 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MM 132 IAA 6: 320
    • MM 132 IAA 6: 320.
  • 67
    • 77954075311 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid
    • Ibid,.
  • 68
    • 77954057377 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid. 131 /AA 6, 320
    • Ibid., 131 /AA 6,320
  • 69
    • 77954075545 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kant draws a distinction between the "form of sovereignty" of a state and its "form of government." The form of government can only be of two kinds: despotic or republican, whereas the form of sovereignty can be of three kinds: autocratic, aristocratic and democratic. the republican form of government laws have to be made by the united will of the people and carried out by an executive that is separate from the law making body and subject to its laws. Kant's Political Writings, p. 100-102/ AA 8: 352-53
    • Kant draws a distinction between the "form of sovereignty" of a state and its "form of government." The form of government can only be of two kinds: despotic or republican, whereas the form of sovereignty can be of three kinds: autocratic, aristocratic and democratic. In the republican form of government laws have to be made by the united will of the people and carried out by an executive that is separate from the law making body and subject to its laws. Kant's Political Writings, p.100-102/ AA 8: 352-53.
  • 70
    • 77954039838 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MM 133/ AA 6: 322
    • MM 133/ AA 6: 322.
  • 71
    • 77954057897 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid. 148 VI, 340
    • Ibid., 148 VI, 340
  • 72
    • 77954081570 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Cf. G. F. Munzel's views on the role of the idea of grafting in Kant's educational theory. Kant's Conception of Moral Character, pp. 335-345
  • 73
    • 77954036866 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • As C. Korsgaard puts it: "This interpretation of history is offered, not as something knowable, and not as a reason for moral quiescence, but as a way those morally committed to peace can envisage nature's cooperation with their efforts" (Creating the Kingdom of Ends [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 1996], p. 34).
  • 74
    • 77954044365 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MM 148/ AA 6: 341.
    • MM 148/ AA 6: 341.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.